I support the intent for an A.N. and object to the intent for a M.N.
Although the thesis is interesting, it is also very limited in scope.

-Aris

On Fri, Oct 27, 2017 at 1:51 PM, Publius Scribonius Scholasticus
<p.scribonius.scholasti...@gmail.com> wrote:
> I support the intent for an A.N.
>
> I object to the intent for a M.N.
>
>
> On 10/27/2017 01:13 PM, Kerim Aydin wrote:
>>
>> For the below Thesis:
>>
>>
>> I intend to award Alexis the Associate of Nomic Degree, with 2 Agoran 
>> Consent.
>>
>>
>> I intend to award Alexis the Master of Nomic Degree, with 2 Agoran Consent.
>>
>>
>> Please be clear which intents you are supporting/objecting to!
>>
>>
>> I pledge to act on exactly one of the above intents (assuming at least
>> one receives the appropriate Consent), using the ratio of Support/Object
>> as a guide to the appropriate one, with ties or mixed consensus broken
>> in favor of the higher degree.
>>
>>
>>
>> ALEXIS'S FINAL THESIS SUBMISSION
>>
>> TL;DR (aka abstract): Conditional votes work, but with two caveats.
>> First, they operate prospectively and, when cast, their value is
>> determined by looking into the future to the end of the voting period.
>> Hence, they are indeterminate. Second, the default of PRESENT does not
>> work at all, meaning that the validity of a conditional vote is also
>> indeterminate. Also, CFJ 3569 is FALSE because Trust Token endorsement
>> must be direct.
>>
>> This thesis and judgment is written as a reconsideration of CFJ 3569.
>> The statement of the CFJ is "If grok had not deregistered, e would have
>> issued trust tokens to both Aris and G. by eir vote on Proposal 7899."
>>
>> The context of the CFJ is as follows: grok voted :Endorse Aris" on
>> proposal 7899, but Aris's vote was "Endorse the Arbitor". G. was the
>> Arbitor at the end of the voting period. In effect, the CFJ is asking
>> whether grok's endorsement was effective of endorsing G. as well for the
>> purpose of Rule 2452.
>>
>> I originally judged CFJ 3569 to be FALSE, finding that Rule 683's
>> condition requiring that a "valid vote" be clearly indicate meant that
>> conditional votes failed altogether; since a conditional vote does not
>> clearly indicate a single valid vote. A number of arguments were raised
>> in response, leading to a Motion to Reconsider. I will summarize the
>> critical arguments below:
>>
>> From G.:
>>
>> - The judgment cited precedent that the correctness of a ballot is
>> evaluated at the time of its submission, but did not specify which
>> precedent, most precedent being around informally conditional actions
>> (e.g. "if I own an X, I do Y with it")
>> - Rule 2127 is explicitly intended to define the effect of conditionals
>> and get around the usual definition, by defining what "clearly
>> specified" means in the context of a vote. This could operate either by
>> deferral of the determination of clearly specified, or by operating
>> retroactively.
>> - Even in absence of the above effects, Rule 2127's default of PRESENT
>> would apply to a ballot cast conditionally, so that such a ballot is at
>> least evaluated in the instant to PRESENT.
>>
>> From myself:
>> - If Rule 2127 had retroactive effect, then it would create the
>> possibility of retroactively changing the outcome of another proposal,
>> by making a vote conditional on a vote on a different proposal; if the
>> latter was a conditional then retroactively changing it could also
>> retroactively change the first vote. From this, paradox could arise.
>>
>> From Aris:
>> - Present conditionals are well-understood to succeed, under the general
>> built-up framework of interpreting conditional actions, as such a
>> conditional always identifies a vote.
>> - A ballot is a textual entity, containing a conditional that should be
>> evaluated when the ballot is evaluated, i.e. when the decision is
>> resolved. The ballot is merely a notice of something in the future.
>>
>> To begin, I will first point to Rule 217, which states "When
>> interpreting and applying the rules, the text of the rules takes
>> precedence. Where the text is silent, inconsistent, or unclear, it is to
>> be augmented by game custom, common sense, past judgments, and
>> consideration of the best interests of the game." In regards to
>> conditionals votes, it is clear that all of the augmenting factors point
>> to conditional votes functioning in some fashion: game custom certainly
>> establishes that they do, as do the best interests of the game. Past
>> judgments on conditional voting are in line with them functioning at
>> all, and common sense (into which one can likely subsume legal
>> principles of statutory interpretation) imply that Rule 2127 (the rule
>> defining conditional votes) would not exist if it did not have some purpose.
>>
>> So the question then is, what does the text of the rules state? CFJ 3465
>> is the strongest precedent I am aware of regarding ballot evaluation. In
>> it, I successfully argued to the H. Judge nichdel that the correctness
>> (note: this is distinct from validity) of a ballot was evaluated at the
>> time of its submission.
>>
>> I will reiterate the critical arguments here. Rule 683 states "An entity
>> submits a ballot on an Agoran decision by publishing a notice satisfying
>> the following conditions:" followed by a list of conditions. The term
>> "notice" is, in this context, undefined by the rules. Per usual English
>> interpretation, in this context, "notice" simply means a document.
>>
>> Rule 683 is clear that the mechanism to submit a ballot is to publish
>> the notice. Publishing is defined by Rule 478 as sending a public
>> message. It follows that if, at the time of publication, the notice does
>> not satisfy the conditions set out in Rule 683, no ballot is submitted.
>> The fact that the notice may later satisfy the conditions is immaterial,
>> as the notice is not being published at that point.
>>
>> So can conditional votes generally satisfy the conditions? The condition
>> at issue is "4. The ballot clearly identifies a valid vote, as
>> determined by the voting method." The definition of valid vote was
>> discussed at length in my previous reasons, and I will not discuss them
>> here. Absent confounding factors, then, it would be clear that the
>> published notice must indeed identify a valid vote. I do agree with
>> Aris's arguments that the general rules regarding conditional actions
>> apply here. There is nothing disallowing a notice which is conditional,
>> at the time of its publication; assuming the conditional is effective
>> per the precedents on conditional actions, such a notice does identify a
>> valid vote once the conditional is resolved.
>>
>> Rule 2127 is, however, a confounding factor. As G. argued, it is clearly
>> intended to get around the usual way that conditionals can act only in
>> the present, and instead creates a form of future-conditional vote. Note
>> that I must at this point reject Aris's argument that a conditional vote
>> is evaluated at the time of the decision's resolution. Rule 2127 is
>> explicit that the conditional is evaluated at the end of the voting
>> period, and there is nothing in the rules or game custom to contend
>> otherwise.
>>
>> As G. noted in eir arguments, Rule 2127 states "If a vote on an Agoran
>> decision is submitted conditionally (e.g. "FOR if <X> is true, otherwise
>> AGAINST"), then the selected option is evaluated based on the value of
>> the condition(s) at the end of the voting period, and, rules to the
>> contrary notwithstanding, is clearly specified if and only if the value
>> of the condition(s) is/are determinate at the end of the voting period.
>> If the option cannot be clearly identified, a vote of PRESENT is cast."
>> Of note is the fact that it explicitly attempts to take precedence over
>> other rules (including 683) to define that "the selected option... is
>> clearly specified" under the circumstances it provides when a
>> conditional vote is made.
>>
>> Does this apply to condition 4? After reexamining the circumstances, it
>> appears to me that the answer is yes. While the language used is
>> slightly different (option vs vote, clearly indicated vs clearly
>> specified), and while some of those terms are terms of art within the
>> rules, none is explicitly defined, so there is some leeway in
>> interpretation here. Note also that 2127 itself uses "clearly
>> identified" in the following sentence, indicating some looseness in
>> terminology. In my original judgment, I had not considered this line of
>> text in the way that G.'s arguments encouraged, and this represents the
>> critical change in my reasoning.
>>
>> Unfortunately, this still presents some difficulty, because the
>> definition is prospective. The direct consequence of interpreting
>> condition 4 using the definition specified in Rule 2127 is that the
>> correctness of the ballot at the time of its submission is determined by
>> looking into the future. The only potential save could be, as G. argued,
>> the following sentence: "If the option cannot be clearly identified, a
>> vote of PRESENT is cast." This does not directly bear on the outcome of
>> CFJ 3569, but in the interests of completeness and avoiding simply
>> postponing the controversy, I will analyze how to evaluate conditional
>> votes below.
>>
>> Having determined that a conditional vote is indeed valid provided its
>> condition is determinate, the only remaining questions required to
>> resolve this case is whether grok's vote had a determinate condition and
>> whether Aris and G., who both cast valid votes on the decision, were
>> "endorsed by [grok]'s valid vote on the Decision" (Rule 2452). It is
>> clear that grok's vote had a determinate condition, making it valid, and
>> it clearly endorsed Aris (regardless of how such it would actually be
>> evaluated). So grok would have issued Aris a trust token. However, did
>> grok's vote endorse G.?
>>
>> Per Rule 2127, "Casting a vote endorsing another voter is equivalent to
>> conditionally casting a vote whose value is the same as the most common
>> value (if any) among that voter's valid votes on that decision." While
>> this definition technically applies only to the point when the vote
>> would cast, it would be unreasonable to interpret the meaning of "a vote
>> endorsing that voter" as meaning anything other than "a conditional vote
>> whose value is the same as the most common value (if any) among that
>> voter's valid votes on that decision." There are two reasonable ways to
>> evaluate this definition on grok's vote then: either it is an inherent
>> property of the vote, or it is evaluated, like all conditionals, at the
>> end of the voting period.
>>
>> A quirk in the wording of Rule 2127 gives a possible hint. It defines
>> endorsing votes as an equivalence with a specific class of votes, rather
>> than merely defining what it means to endorse a player. Consequently, if
>> "equivalent" is interpreted as it would be in a mathematical context,
>> any conditional vote whose value is as described in Rule 2127 is an
>> endorsing vote, regardless of whether or not the vote explicitly uses
>> the word "endorse". The terms are interchangeable.
>>
>> Substituting this into Rule 2452, that would mean that grok issues a
>> Trust Token to G. if "grok had a valid conditional vote whose value is
>> the same as the most common value (if any) among G's valid votes on the
>> decision". If we evaluate this at the end of the voting period, then a
>> thoroughly absurd result ensues: not only would G. be issued a trust
>> token, but also every other player who cast the same vote. As such, we
>> must interpret the definition as applying to an intrinsic property of
>> the conditional. Thus, we cannot consider Aris's vote when we decide
>> whether grok's vote endorsed, G. and so it did not. grok would not have
>> issued G. a Trust Token.
>>
>> It's not necessarily clear, however, that "equivalent" in the Agoran
>> ruleset should be interpreted this way (an old rule that mathematical
>> definitions take precedence having been repealed). If we interpret this
>> wording as being merely an odd way of defining the term endorsement,
>> then the outcome is the same, however. The definition of endorsement
>> specifically applies to valid votes; thus, in order to resolve grok's
>> conditional vote, we must first resolve Aris's. A different definition
>> of endorsement, where grok's vote copied the "Endorse the Arbitor" from
>> Aris's vote, might lead to a conclusion where grok did endorse G., but
>> we clearly must resolve Aris's vote first, so grok's vote is never
>> directly dependent on G.'s.
>>
>> Thus, either way, CFJ 3569 is FALSE.
>>
>> With that resolved, how then should a conditional vote be evaluated?
>> This is unfortunately a thorny issue. As I wrote above, whether or not
>> the vote is valid is effectively determined prospectively, by looking
>> into the future. Before digging deeper, however, I will draw attention
>> to one key point: the question of a ballot's correctness (i.e. whether
>> it meets the requirements of Rule 683) is independent from the question
>> of how it is evaluated in an Agoran decision. Thus, I see two remaining
>> questions: first, is a conditional vote with an indeterminate condition
>> correctly submitted, or does it fail to clearly identify a valid vote?
>> and second, how does one evaluate a conditional vote?
>>
>> To address the first question, I quote again Rule 2127: "If a vote on an
>> Agoran decision is submitted conditionally (e.g. "FOR if <X> is true,
>> otherwise AGAINST"), then the selected option is evaluated based on the
>> value of the condition(s) at the end of the voting period, and, rules to
>> the contrary notwithstanding, is clearly specified if and only if the
>> value of the condition(s) is/are determinate at the end of the voting
>> period. If the option cannot be clearly identified, a vote of PRESENT is
>> cast." The first sentence provides very clear conditions about when the
>> option is clearly specified. What does the second sentence do in this
>> context? Does it indicate that, when the condition is indeterminate, the
>> selected option is clearly specified as PRESENT?
>>
>> I think that this cannot be the case, because to do so would completely
>> obviate the definition of "clearly specified" in the first place. Why
>> would the rule state that an option is not clearly specified if the
>> conditional is indeterminate, only to change its mind in the next
>> sentence? This does not actually matter, however, because the first
>> sentence contains a precedence claim and the second sentence does not.
>> Per Rule 2240, this means that the first sentence takes precedence and,
>> consequently, the second sentence does not modify it. If the condition
>> is indeterminate at the end of the voting period, the vote is not
>> clearly specified. Per the reasoning above, this means that the
>> conditional ballot is not submitted.
>>
>> What, then, is the meaning of the second sentence? The most reasonable
>> interpretation, in context, is that it is trying to say that if the
>> condition is indeterminate, then at the end of the voting period, we
>> resolve it to PRESENT rather than attempting to evaluate it. If this is
>> the correct interpretation, it is meaningless, because by the above we
>> can never get to that point. There is an alternative interpretation: the
>> second sentence is not providing for a way to evaluate the original
>> conditional ballot but instead provided for an altogether new,
>> unconditional ballot of PRESENT to be cast.
>>
>> Unfortunately, this interpretation also fails to have any meaningful
>> effect. The vote counting procedure is defined in Rule 955 in terms of
>> valid ballots, and Rule 683 provides a clear definition: "A valid ballot
>> is a ballot, correctly submitted, that has not been withdrawn. During
>> the voting period of an Agoran decision, a player CAN by announcement
>> withdraw (syn. retract) a ballot that e submitted on that decision." As
>> Rule 683 has a lower ID number than Rule 2127, by Rule 1030, Rule 683
>> takes precedence. There is thus no possibility of Rule 2127's "vote of
>> PRESENT" actually being a valid ballot.
>>
>> So in conclusion, the answer is that a conditional vote is valid if and
>> only if the condition ends up being determinate. If it is not, the
>> entire vote fails; PRESENT is not an alternative.
>>
>> Finally, the question comes of evaluating a conditional vote. Happily, I
>> see no reason why, for a valid vote, Rule 2127 should be anything other
>> than what it straightforwardly says. Provided that the conditional is
>> valid (i.e. determinate at the end of the voting period), it is
>> evaluated as one would expect, at the end of the voting period. Prior to
>> then, however, just like with the validity of the vote in the first
>> place, the actual value of the vote is indeterminate.
>>
>> What are the practical implications of this? First, it is important to
>> distinguish between prospective and retroactive effects here. The
>> validity of a conditional vote is not retroactively changed at the end
>> of the voting period, when we finally are able to decide if it is
>> determinate or not. Rather, the validity *in the first place* is
>> dependent on the future. In some cases, this can create
>> effectively-retroactive effects. For instance, a subsequent, otherwise
>> valid ballot cast by the same voter, without withdrawing the first one,
>> would enter the same indeterminate state of validity, since it is valid
>> if and only if the first ballot is invalid.
>>
>> This may present situations where the game may be difficult to play, but
>> the concept of indeterminacy provides a shield in some cases. Rule 1023
>> means that the validity of the vote is indeterminate before the voting
>> period ends, since it cannot be determined from information reasonably
>> available. Rule 2127 itself provides that if a conditional vote is
>> indeterminate, it doesn't work. So, taking from the example in my
>> arguments, if a vote on one proposal is conditional on a vote on another
>> proposal ending later, then it necessarily fails because the condition
>> will be indeterminate. Likewise, Rule 2162 protects against
>> indeterminately-valued switches.
>>
>> In conclusion, rules are hard.
>>
>>
>
>

Reply via email to