-Caveat Lector-

Library: Risk prevention and the political control of genetic engineering:
lessons from a participatory technology assessment on transgenic
herbicide-resistant crops

Wolfgang van den Daele  Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin für Sozialforschung,
Reichpietschufer 50, D-10785, Berlin, Germany Email:
[EMAIL PROTECTED]

ABSTRACT  The review describes the political experiment of a participatory
technology assessment which was organized in Germany to test whether the
endless battle over genetic engineering could be transferred from the
public arena to a dialogue of rational argumentation. Transgenic
herbicide-resistant crop plants were the topic of the technology
assessment. The claim that such plants pose particular risks because they
have been genetically modified could not be defended in an exchange of
arguments. The critics continued to reject the technology, but on different
grounds, arguing that there was no acceptable social need for
herbicide-resistant plants, since better alternatives were available. This
shift seemed to indicate that the real issue behind the conflict over
genetic engineering is not the prevention of risk, but the quest for more
democratic control of the dynamics of technological innovation. The critics
refused, however, to ratify this finding as a result of the dialogue and
thus avoided the redefinition of the conflict in the public agenda.

Putting risk arguments to test  In July 1998 the Swiss citizens rejected
the claim that an unconditional ban on the release of genetically modified
organisms into the environment should be included in the Swiss
constitution. It remains to be seen whether, with this referendum, the long
argument over the risks of genetic engineering which have dominated the
public debate, particularly in German-speaking countries, will finally come
to a halt. We had earlier put the arguments to the test of a participatory
technology assessment organized by the Science Center for Social Research
from 1991-1993 on transgenic herbicide-resistant crop plants. This
technology assessment was specific for two reasons. Firstly, it was
participatory. It involved some 50 persons from environmental groups,
industry, regulatory agencies and the scientific community, giving full
representation and a fair share of resources (for commissioning expert
reports) to the critics of the technology. Secondly, it was discursive.
Participants were expected to collect and discuss all available arguments
in an ongoing process of communication and interaction. For that purpose
they attended a series of conferences which lasted more than 10 days in
all.  Discourse in such a social setting is remarkably different from the
so-called "public" discourse pursued in mass communication. Participants in
mass communication tend to use the rhetoric of arguments but rarely observe
the disclipine of argumentation. They normally confine themselves to the
statement of their own strongest points, neglecting countervailing
arguments or selecting for consideration only those which they can easily
refute. In contrast, the participants in our technology assessment were
bound to take the rules of argumentation seriously. The presence of
advocates of opposing views guarantees that the full range of arguments and
counterarguments are considered. Selectivity cannot be maintained. The
participants may well be committed to restrictive positions and strategic
interests, but as long as they participate in the process of communicative
interaction they can hardly ignore requests to substantiate reasons, to
take objections into account, to present the empirical evidence for a
statement, and to consider counter-evidence.  Discussions over risks
proceeded through various stages in our technology assessment:  from
recognizable risk with predictable consequence to hypothetical and unknown
risks with unforseeable consequences  from the isolated assessment of risks
involved in genetically modified plants to a comparison of risk between
transgenic and non-transgenic plants  from the need to substantiate
suspected risk to a reversal of the burden of proof; the absence of risk
should be demonstrated  from arguments over risks to arguments over social
benefits; socio-economic need should be a prerequisite for the introduction
of new technology. All these aspects had been raised in the public debate
before. What the technology assessment showed was that there is a logical
order or pattern of transformation, to which the criticism of genetic
engineering will be submitted if put to the test of argumentation.

Comparing the risks of transgenic and non-transgenic plants  Basically, no
risks from transgenic herbicide-resistant plants were recognizable which
were not already known from non-transgenic plants. Recognizable risks were
"normalized" through comparison. They no longer appeared dramatic if
compared to the risks which are accepted with conventional agricultural
crops and practices. The participants in the technology assessment agreed
that it was not enough to consider risks which can be described and tested.
The real issue with transgenic plants might well be that we do not know the
risks. However, it was pointed out that in conventional breeding too one
can neither foresee nor control what the physiological impact of new genes
might be, given the genetic background of the host plant. Unexpected and
undesirable side-effects are abundant and must be coped with through
testing and selection in the further development of new varieties. Thus,
comparison with conventional plants not only "normalized" the recognizable
risks of transgenic plants, but also the uncertainties and the hypothetical
risks which might be implied by the fact that we have limited foresight of
the possible consequences of such plants.  The critics had two arguments as
to why it was not legitimate to compare conventional breeding and the
construction of transgenic plants. More serious side-effects should be
expected with the latter because: (1) transgenes insert at random and may
cause insertional mutations in the host genome which can trigger changes in
the transformed plant that are unrelated to the information coded in the
transgene; and (2) genes can be transferred across species barriers and
introduce metabolic pathways which have never belonged to the host plant
species. Both arguments refer to hypothetical risks. There is no empirical
evidence yet that more serious side-effects do in fact occur in transgenic
plants, nor is it possible to anticipate such effects theoretically in any
detail. It is, however, held that, as one critic put it, one can infer from
the "specific quality" of genetic engineering that transgenic plants
present a "specific type of uncertainty".  In our technology assessment,
the first of the above arguments was invalidated through comparison, by
pointing out that insertional mutations (and pleitropic effects) are not
specific to genetic engineering. They also occur with conventional breeding
techniques and when natural transposable elements, which are known to exist
in most plants, and also insert at random, jump around in the plant genome.
The second argument was considered as valid in principle, but again weakend
through comparison. While it may be true that the probability of side
effects is theoretically higher in transgenic plants, because (and if) new
metabolic pathways are transferred, it can also be argued that the
probability of side effects is theoretically lower in transgenic plants,
because with genetic engineering a single, identifiable gene product is
transferred, whereas with crossing techniques an uncontrolled number of
undetermined genes may be exchanged, all of which can interact with the
existing metabolism. Thus, the assumption that transgenic plants will have
more unexpected side effects than non-transgenic plants seemed as only as
good in theory as the contrary assumption that transgenic plants have less
unexpected side effects than non-transgenic plants.  The critics of genetic
engineering finally retreated to the argument that even if our present
knowledge does not warrant the assumption that transgenic plants involve
specific and more severe risks than non-transgenic plants it is still
theoretically possible that such risks do in fact exist and may become
apparent later. This argument could only be effectively turned against new
technology if the rule that risk assumptions have to be substantiated was
abandoned and the burden of proof shifted from those who claim risks to
those who claim safety. At this point of the debate our technology
assessment proceeded beyond the established framework of risk prevention
and raised fundamental issues of the politics of innovation.

Socio-economic need and the quest for democratic control of innovation  It
became quickly apparent in our discussions that a full reversal of the
burden of proof is not an operational rule. The unsubstantiated assumption
that there may be unknown risks can easily be raised against any new
technology and can hardly be refuted. No innovation would survive under
such a rule. Consequently, the critics of genetic engineering made the next
step and demanded that only those innovations should be admitted for which
there is a clear socio-economic need. They concluded that transgenic
herbicide-resistant plants had to be prohibited under this test, because
such plants represented no ecological advantage and little if any agronomic
use; efficient weed control could be achieved in almost all cases using
available selective herbicides, and non-chemical methods of weed control
would be the ecologically preferable alternative, anyhow. Arguments as to
whether transgenic herbicide-resistant plants are useful and satisfy a
proper need were accepted as a necessary and legitimate topic of inquiry
(and controversy) in the technology assessment. The proposal, however, to
make "socio-economic need" a legal prerequisite in the regulation of the
technology was rejected by most participants. It was argued that this would
replace market mechanisms with political decision-making and that the
decline of the socialist countries had demonstrated that no model for an
efficient economy exists in which decisions on innovation and investment
are the domain of politics. The critics conceded the problems but insisted
that nevertheless some revisions of the established institutional balance
between market mechanisms and democratic control of innovation were
necessary and that the question of whether we really need a new technology
must be put on the political agenda. The controversy over this point
remained as unresolved in this technology assessment as it is in the rest
of the society.

The limits of participatory technology assessment  The exchange of
arguments did not achieve a final consensus in our technology assessment.
However, the dissent at the end of the discussions was not the same as at
the beginning. The issues of debate had been transformed. They had shifted
from arguments about risk prevention to arguments about the reform of
political institutions and the future development of society. This shift
seems to indicate that no conclusive reasons against the use of transgenic
herbicide-resistant plants could be formulated within the framework of
established risk regulation, and that the real issue behind the conflict
over genetic engineering is the quest for democratic control of the process
of technological innovation.  It would have been a real accomplishment if
we had been able to publicize this transformation of issues, and hence a
refiguration of the landscape of political controversy in Germany, as a
finding of our participatory technology assessment. The critics of genetic
engineering were not, however, prepared to take this step. They withdrew
their participation in the technology assessment at the beginning of the
final conference, at which they were expected either to accept the proposed
conclusions or to reject them, giving additional reasons why they
considered them incorrect. Apparently, it would have been difficult for
them to declare explicitly that the conflict was not about risks, but about
social goals and political reform, after they had committed themselves
categorically to the rhetoric of risk, and used it successfully in the
mobilization of the general public. As long as one claims risks it is easy
to argue that the dominant policy is irresponsible and offends against
generally accepted values. When risk arguments no longer play a role, it
seems more legitimate to apply majority decisions in the choice of
conflicting goals.  Participatory technology assessments are not a
procedural fix to resolve political conflicts over technological
innovation. They provide a forum for rational discourse in which
controversial arguments will not only be exchanged but also examined. Such
discourse implies learning. However, while the learning may easily be
accepted by the observing public (including parliaments, administrations,
and the courts) the participants who represent the parties of the political
conflict may refuse to adapt to what has been learned. Participatory
technology assessment constitutes a limited context of cooperation and it
operates at a distance from the real political arena. It remains a small
island of argumentation in a large sea of strategic battle. Thus, in terms
of "realpolitik" it must be expected that arguments which have been refuted
within the technology assessment will continue to be used outside the
technology assessment, as long as they can still impress the public. Even
then, participatory technology assessments may be a valuable contribution
to the political culture. They will not lead to consensus, political
decisions will still have to be taken in dissent. However, procedures that
give the critics a fair chance and submit controversial issues to the
discipline of rational argumentation will contribute to the legitimacy of
decision-making in dissent.

References  For a full acount of the technology assessment see: van den
Daele, W.; Pühler, A.; Sukopp, H. (1996): Grüne Gentechnik im Widerstreit.
Weinheim: Verlag Chemie. An English summary report is available as
WZB-discussion paper FS II 97-302: van den Daele, W.; Pühler, A.; Sukopp,
H. (1997): Transgenic herbicide-resistant crops. A participatory technology
assessment. Requests for papers should be addressed to the author: Wolfgang
van den Daele, Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin für Sozialforschung,
Reichpietschufer 50, D-10785, Berlin. [Fax: (49) 30 25491-219, e-mail:
[EMAIL PROTECTED]]

Library: Risk prevention and the political control of genetic engineering:
lessons from a participatory technology assessment on transgenic
herbicide-resistant crops

http://binas.unido.org/binas/Library/cabi/daele.html

DECLARATION & DISCLAIMER
==========
CTRL is a discussion and informational exchange list. Proselyzting propagandic
screeds are not allowed. Substance—not soapboxing!  These are sordid matters
and 'conspiracy theory', with its many half-truths, misdirections and outright
frauds is used politically  by different groups with major and minor effects
spread throughout the spectrum of time and thought. That being said, CTRL
gives no endorsement to the validity of posts, and always suggests to readers;
be wary of what you read. CTRL gives no credeence to Holocaust denial and
nazi's need not apply.

Let us please be civil and as always, Caveat Lector.
========================================================================
Archives Available at:
http://home.ease.lsoft.com/archives/CTRL.html

http:[EMAIL PROTECTED]/
========================================================================
To subscribe to Conspiracy Theory Research List[CTRL] send email:
SUBSCRIBE CTRL [to:] [EMAIL PROTECTED]

To UNsubscribe to Conspiracy Theory Research List[CTRL] send email:
SIGNOFF CTRL [to:] [EMAIL PROTECTED]

Om

Reply via email to