-Caveat Lector-

from:
http://philadelphiatwo.org/library/specificsolution.htm
-----

A SPECIFIC SOLUTION: “Time To Walk The Talk”
By Senator Mike Gravel, June 6, 2000


Over the last quarter century, awesome improvements in communications
technology have enhanced the ability of the citizenry to participate in
lawmaking. In states that permit citizen initiatives, the people have enacted
meaningful reforms such as campaign financing and term limits. This assertion
of legislative power by the people has led to reforms by representatives
under the guise of correcting abuses of the initiative process.

This contest over who will rule – government officials or the people – has
attracted the attention of the political science community and media pundits.
Their articles, papers and books address all aspects of citizen lawmaking,
but often in a vacuum.

Analysis of the methodologies of governance requires a comparative context.
Analysis of one approach to democratic governance – the initiative process –
without a contemporaneous comparison to the alternative – the legislative
process of representative government – denies outside observers a basis for
judgment andchoice.

As a lifelong student of political science, I read with relish all the
excellent papers to be presented at this conference. Most of the references
to the practices of legislatures and initiatives are familiar to me due to my
sixteen years in elective office: four in the Alaska Legislature, two as
Speaker; and twelve years in the U.S. Senate. My experiences have taught me
the dangers of legislative monopoly by representative government.

In the early nineties I founded and continue to head up the nonprofit
corporations Philadelphia Two and Direct Democracy. These organizations are
sponsors of the Direct Democracy Initiative (DDI) [1]. The DDI is a proposed
federal law that will empower citizens to set policy and enact laws
nationally and in every state and local jurisdiction of the United States,
with procedures to promote deliberation and debate, while prohibiting the
influence of corporate, union and association money. The DDI will establish
an administrative agency, the Electoral Trust, to implement the procedures
that will in effect create a Legislature of the People. This new direct
democracy institution will legislate in a manner parallel and complementary
to the legislative bodies of representative governments. We hope thereby to
set in motion improved governance through an evolutionary process, rather
than the revolutionary upheaval likely to come if representatives and their
acolytes insist on retaining and exploiting their monopoly of political
power.

The sponsors of the DDI see no chance that Congress would enact anything like
it. Therefore, we are pursuing the DDI’s passage through a self-enacting
process (in DDI Sections 6 and 7) similar to the self-enactment adoption
provision of the federal Constitution written into it by James Madison and
his colleagues. They secured self-enactment of the Constitution via that
special ratification process by the people (U.S. Constitution, Article VII)
in what was effectively a national initiative in 1787-89.

The Influence of Money

Money is the mother’s milk of politics. This statement is immutably true and
vital.  However, empirically, it has proven to be less true with respect to
the initiative process than in the representative legislative process. The
failure of money to buy the enactment of initiatives discredits the
disingenuous arguments of initiative opponents. Yet, the substantial sums
spent in initiative campaigns does affect some initiatives negatively. The
amounts of money spent on initiatives will continue to grow, as they have in
candidate elections. The main culprit is not money itself but soft money
coming from unidentified sources. The likelihood of Congress reforming
meaningfully either candidate or initiative funding practices is remote.

The money problem commenced with the U.S. Supreme Court decision in Santa
Clara Co. v. Southern Pacific Railroad Company, 118 U. S. 394, (1886). In
that case the Court expanded Chief Justice Marshall’s earlier definition of
the corporation as an artificial being, into a corporation as a person under
the law. The Court explicitly, but for unnamed reasons, chose not to hear
arguments against this significant assumption, now ensconced in case law.

Two subsequent decisions expanded the Court’s corporate edifice: Buckley v.
Valeo, 424 U.S. 1 (1976) and First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435
U. S. 765 (1977). These decisions effectively allow the definition of
“corporation” to include political rights for this artificial person.  The
Valeo decision, abridging First Amendment rights of free speech, limited the
income side of the equation – personal contributions, without limiting the
expense side of the equation – campaign expenditures. The limit on individual
contributions, coupled with the lack of limits on corporate expenditure,
unleashed the floodgate for soft money.  In Bellotti, the Court extended the
Santa Clara logic to permit corporate wealth to work its will on initiatives,
striking down Massachusetts’ efforts to limit corporate spending on
initiatives.

The negative impact of these cases on the polity and a spate of subsequent
decisions by the Court adding additional confusion suggest the need for the
Court to revisit these cases, particularly Santa Clara. DDI’s prohibition
against corporate contributions (in Section 4 L) effectively reverses
Bellotti. This could trigger a suit, thereby opening an argument about the
Santa Clara corporate “person.” Additionally, DDI removes any possibility of
a Buckley-like limitation on personal contributions for initiatives.

We are not foolishly courting judicial review. The Bellotti decision was a
close 5-4 vote, with three written opinions. Justice Rehnquist wrote a
separate dissent questioning acceptance of the corporation as a person – a
perspective that was adopted in Santa Clara but never examined.  He noted for
future Court consideration that in Northern National Life Insurance Company
v. Riggs, 203 U.S. 243, 255 (1906), “liberty” was applied to natural persons
alone and not artificial persons. If the Court were to revisit Santa Clara,
it could have ramifications well beyond the initiative question.

DDI’s approach to initiative campaign financing is to remove all barriers to
a person’s exercising free speech by means of the expenditure of money, but
to restrict such money expenditures to persons alone. Civil and political
rights should be restricted to human beings – persons – and not to
artificial, legal entities.  DDI’s mandatory disclosure provisions (in
Section 4 M) place responsibility for policing money’s impact on campaigns
with the people. Since there seems to be no fair way to reapportion the
disparity of private property within the polity, the DDI relies on
transparence.

The Competence Issue

Questioning the competence of the people in the initiative process touches
the foundation of human governance. It is an argument commonly used to
discredit direct democracy, and, even more frequently, an unconscious
assumption. The obvious retort to this unflattering judgment of others is:
what are the options? Since the Age of Enlightenment positioned the
individual as sovereign as much as any king, who is there to rule other than
the people? If the people are not competent to govern themselves, then we
must suffer whatever kind of government the people’s competence chooses. This
principle operates in Borneo or in New York City, where former mayor Jimmy
Walker is reported to have said: “I may have been a jerk in office, but it
took a lot of jerks to put me there.”

Considerably less competence is required to set policy or enact laws, both
usually involving straightforward decisions, than to select agents with
complex personalities, with bundles of “positions” and indiscernible
motivations. Or, as Madison put it in Federalist 10 [2]:

Men of factious tempers, of local prejudices, or of sinister designs, may, by
intrigue, by corruption, or by other means, first obtain the suffrages, and
then betray the interests, of the people.

How can we as voters have the discernment to anticipate betrayal when
candidates for our agency assure us of their fidelity by urging that we read
their lips?

Philadelphia Two’s DDI is premised on the belief that people, possessed of
proper information, will make decisions as good or superior to that of their
representatives. Majoritarian decisions by the people need not be filtered
through the ambitious self-interest of representatives or the economic
self-interest of their supporters.

Qualifying Initiatives

The use of petitions to qualify initiatives is legitimate. However, the
unusually high number of required signatures, the short time allowed for the
collection of those signatures, silly identification requirements levied on
signature gatherers, the serve-no-purpose certification of petition forms,
and numerous other ploys of government are not designed to improve the
initiative process but to impede the participation of people in their own
governance.

The problems with professional signature gatherers also apply to volunteer
gatherers. Signature gathering is a numbers game restricted by time. Success
requires putting aside time-consuming edification and getting as many
signatures as possible, as quickly as possible.

The DDI (in Section 4 C) lowers the number of signatures to qualify
initiatives and extends the period of time to gather signatures. More
importantly, it establishes a new qualifier, the Public Opinion Poll. Polling
comes much closer to the ideal of accurately determining if an appropriate
number of people wish an issue to be placed on the ballot. It is also less
costly and more democratic.

I make no comment in this paper about the professionalism that has emerged in
the initiative process for the obvious reason that professionalism is a
welcome improvement in almost any human endeavor.

The Information Issue

The lynchpin of competency is the information people acquire or can cue on to
make their decisions. While reading about the information cues people rely on
to make decisions, I often say to myself: “that’s exactly the way we did it
in the Senate.”

Let me share a recent a conversation I had with my good friend Senator Alan
Cranston, as an illustration of the extent cues are relied upon in
legislatures. I asked his reaction to my estimate that 75% of the members of
Congress do not read 75% of the legislation they vote on. Alan’s view is more
experienced, having served longer in the Senate (and as majority whip, with
the task of monitoring votes). He thought my estimate was off, that more than
90% of the members of Congress do not read 90% of the laws on which they
vote.

The informational shortcomings in the initiative process stem from the fact
that the people are deprived of the publicly-funded, specialized staff
assistance that representative legislative bodies receive. This, of course,
is correctable. The DDI (in Section 4) makes available to the people the same
kind of information cues now available only to our elected representatives.

After an initiative is qualified, a professional hearing officer from the
Electoral Trust (Section 5 E (4)), in conjunction with the initiative’s
sponsors and representatives from the relevant legislative body, will conduct
hearings to receive the testimony of experts, advocates, opponents and any
interested parties. These interactive hearings can use all forms of advanced
technology to inform all interested communities – going far beyond what the
Congress presently employs for its hearings.

In the next legislative step (Section 4 E) the Electoral Trust convenes a
committee of randomly selected ordinary citizens from the relevant
jurisdiction for each initiative to review the hearing transcript, deliberate
the merits, and prepare a written report with recommendations.  The committee
can amend the initiative so long as the amendments are consistent with the
original intent of the initiative.

Like the committee of a legislature, the Deliberative Committee marks up a
bill and sends it to the legislative body of the relevant jurisdiction – a
city council, a legislature, or Congress. That body then conducts a public
advisory vote (Section 4 F). Through these procedures, the DDI’s process
provides the people with the information cues of a deliberative process,
minus the personal and private contacts that permit and encourage logrolling
in legislative bodies.

As an aside, I question the assertion that legislative compromises, resulting
from the give and take in legislative bodies, are a serious loss to the
initiative process. Of course, compromise is a very positive word in our
democratic culture. Unquestionably, compromise, as a verb, helps mediate
among the divergent merits of a measure. However, as a noun, compromise often
describes a half-baked solution. Moreover, the give and take of compromises
is often totally extraneous to the merits of a bill. A vote in exchange for a
judgeship, a dam, a road, a seat on the next junket, or an endorsement in the
next election has no relevance to fashioning a meritorious compromise –
rather, it relates more closely to corruption than merit. The initiative
process suffers no great loss in this regard.

DDI contains three limits on initiatives (in Section 4 A and B) that enhance
their clarity. Initiatives must have relevance to public policy, a limit on
the number of words, and a limitation to a single subject. It’s worth noting
that lack of these limits opens sources of great mischief in legislatures.

To assist the people and assure the quality of initiative laws, a legislative
drafting and research service is established within the Electoral Trust
(Section 5 E (3)). Similar services are available to legislatures.

Today, public communications about the content of an initiative is very
limited and print-exclusive. DDI (in Sections 4 N and 5 E (5)) expands upon
the means of making information available to voters through the use of current
 technology.

The Courts

The courts dare not invade the legislative branch prior to the enactment of
legislation, absent overt fraud. The executive is less restricted in its
legislative participation, at least informally. Nevertheless, the separation
of these two branches from the legislative branch is a mainstay of our checks
and balances system. But the executive and judicial branches wantonly invade
the people’s legislative venue, the initiative. Their reasons for the
invasion – usually self-serving – are that initiatives lack the deliberative
procedures of legislatures.

The executive branch in states with initiatives has administrative and
ministerial responsibilities for the processing of initiatives. Under DDI,
the Electoral Trust assumes this function; it is less likely to have a
conflict of interest. As the executor of the government’s laws, elected
officials and bureaucrats in the executive branch may stop measures they
dislike before they can get off the ground. By refusing to perform certain
ministerial duties, they discourage sponsors or force them to sue. Judges,
who in many cases rely on the executive branch for appointment or promotion,
experience subtle pressures to go beyond the ministerial questions and delve
into the merits of the proposed initiative, e.g., its constitutionality.
Often, they find ways to strike down initiatives before they ever reach the
people. What special powers or political qualifications do judges have to
determine what people – the ultimate sovereign – should or should not vote
on?

This criticism in no way denigrates the court’s responsibility to adjudicate
the constitutionality of initiative laws. DDI (Section 4 H) explicitly
acknowledges the court’s power and duty to determine the constitutionality of
statutory initiative laws, but cautions judicial restraint prior to a law’s
enactment.

First Principles

Recent initiative literature traces the origins of the initiative to
Populists and Progressives. This is correct with regard to the explicit
aspects and procedures of Initiative, Referendum and Recall (IRR) laws
introduced in the first quarter of the last century. However, that shortened
lineage skews the dialogue and falsely suggests that the people’s involvement
in lawmaking lacks an adequate foundation in history.

The dialogue is better served by pushing back the initiative’s lineage, at
least with respect to our nation, to its proper and earliest beginnings: the
Mayflower Compact, Jamestown, and the New England Town Meeting, to name some
of the highlights. The initiative originates with the First Principles of
governance – wherein people initiate and “just do it.” First Principles are
embodied in the initiative process. Madison pointed to the primacy of First
Principles on August 31, 1787 at the Constitutional Convention in response to
a Maryland delegate who feared that the proposed adoption of the federal
Constitution would violate procedures in Maryland’s Constitution:

The difficulty in Maryland was no greater than in other States, where no mode
of change was pointed out by the Constitution, and all officers were under
oath to support it. The people were in fact, the fountain of all power, and
by resorting to them, all difficulties were got over. They could alter
constitutions as they pleased. It was a principle in the Bill of rights, that
first principles might be resorted to.

Opponents of initiatives cite Madison’s Federalist 10 as the prime source of
justification for representative government’s supremacy over the people’s
legislative power. Two points need to be made with regard to this. First,
Madison made those arguments in the heat of the ratification campaign.
Earlier, at the Constitutional Convention, James Wilson describes the deeper
context of republican governance:

The Legislature ought to be the most exact transcript of the whole society.
Representation is made necessary only because it is impossible for the people
to act collectively.

The Framers had no choice but to build and defend a representational
structure. However, what was impossible in 1787 has become possible with the
incredible level of technology we enjoy today.

The second contextual point: Madison, in the last seven paragraphs of
Federalist 10, argues that state governments, with more people and larger
areas, are well-suited to resolve the problems of local smaller governments.
He then extends that argument to sell the federalism of the Constitution,
arguing that a national government is well suited to resolve difficulties
that plague the smaller state governments. Extending Madison’s logic, the
people, our highest venue of authority, can address and have the
responsibility to address today’s problems of an unresponsive national
government. The way to implement this logic is pointed to by James Wilson:

All power is originally in the people and should be exercised by them in
person, if that could be done with convenience, or even with little
difficulty.[3]

Conclusion

Let me conclude with a macro perspective of our deliberations. Analysis of
the methodologies of governance must be comparative if it is to help us make
choices that improve governance. I conclude that governance that includes the
people, rather than their representatives alone, better serves the polity.
The initiative process we advocate is not the initiative process that we see
today, which is almost as defective as our representative legislative
process. To the contrary, we fashioned draft legislation to address the
shortcomings of the governance process in general.   With Philadelphia Two,
we advance a measure, evolutionary in nature, that protects the institutions
of representative government while bringing forward the people to fully
participate in the central act of self-governance – the establishment of
policy and lawmaking.

This partnership of the people and their agents would be achieved by the
enactment of the Direct Democracy Initiative, which at this stage should be
scrutinized, constructively critiqued, and amended where necessary. The DDI
will never find a venue of more qualified individuals for that purpose than
this conference.

Direct Democracy, which may seem radical to some, is the essence of our
Constitution, as expressed in the initial words of the Preamble, “We, the
People...do ordain and establish this Constitution.” Alexander Meiklejohn,
the great constitutional scholar, defined the real meaning of
self-government:

The citizens of this nation shall make and shall obey their own laws, shall
be at once their own subjects and their own masters.[4]


-----
Aloha, He'Ping,
Om, Shalom, Salaam.
Em Hotep, Peace Be,
All My Relations.
Omnia Bona Bonis,
Adieu, Adios, Aloha.
Amen.
Roads End

<A HREF="http://www.ctrl.org/";>www.ctrl.org</A>
DECLARATION & DISCLAIMER
==========
CTRL is a discussion & informational exchange list. Proselytizing propagandic
screeds are unwelcomed. Substance—not soap-boxing—please!  These are
sordid matters and 'conspiracy theory'—with its many half-truths, mis-
directions and outright frauds—is used politically by different groups with
major and minor effects spread throughout the spectrum of time and thought.
That being said, CTRLgives no endorsement to the validity of posts, and
always suggests to readers; be wary of what you read. CTRL gives no
credence to Holocaust denial and nazi's need not apply.

Let us please be civil and as always, Caveat Lector.
========================================================================
Archives Available at:
http://peach.ease.lsoft.com/archives/ctrl.html
 <A HREF="http://peach.ease.lsoft.com/archives/ctrl.html";>Archives of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]</A>

http:[EMAIL PROTECTED]/
 <A HREF="http:[EMAIL PROTECTED]/";>ctrl</A>
========================================================================
To subscribe to Conspiracy Theory Research List[CTRL] send email:
SUBSCRIBE CTRL [to:] [EMAIL PROTECTED]

To UNsubscribe to Conspiracy Theory Research List[CTRL] send email:
SIGNOFF CTRL [to:] [EMAIL PROTECTED]

Om

Reply via email to