Any time that IRV does not elect the sincere CW (when there is one) there is 
going to be a strong incentive for order reversal under IRV, except under the 
(non-existent) zero information case.  [The only real life cases that exist in 
hot elections are the positive information and positive disinformation cases.]
 
Why is there an incentive for order reversal under IRV when the CW is not 
elected on the basis of sincere rankings?
 
Because the losing faction(s) on the opposite side of the CW from the IRV 
winner would rather have the CW than the sincere IRV winner, so they have an 
incentive to rank the CW ahead of their favorite.
 
On the other hand, Condorcet Compliant methods have divers ways of resolving 
cycles, which cycles can be created artificially by some non-CW faction that 
thinks it might have a chance of winning in the particular cycle resolution 
method that has been adopted.
 
It seems that to avoid significant incentives for order reversals the method 
must satisfy the FBC (Favorite Betrayal Criterion).  Both IRV and proposed 
Condorcet methods fail even the weak version of FBC.
 
Mike Ossipoff's last thrust before he retired from this list was his (well 
considered) opinion that if a method is known not to satisfy the FBC, then many 
voters will panic and rank only perceived viable candidates in first place.
 
[That wouldn't be so bad if perception weren't so tricky in the face of all of 
the disinformation floating around.]
 
All known deterministic FBC proposals allow for equal ranking at the top, or 
make no instrumental difference in the top two ranks,  i.e. the difference is 
expressive only, so all of these methods fail the Strong FBC.
 
The only known methods that satisfy the Strong FBC are non-deterministic, i.e. 
what Jobst and I call "lotteries," and most lotteries fail the FBC, too, though 
Random Ballot satisfies the Strong FBC.
 
IRV supporters like being able to rank Favorite strictly above Compromise with 
the illusion of optimality.
 
But that's all it is, an illusion of satisfying the Strong FBC.
 
The simplest deterministic method that satisfies the (weak) FBC is Approval.
 
In my opinion, more complicated methods based on rankings or ratings can 
justify their increased complication only by allowing the "Select from a 
Published List of Rankings or Ratings" option.
 
Also (in my opinion) Asset Voting is another method that is so inexpensive that 
it is worth promoting.  It satisfies the Strong FBC when you take into account 
that you can write in yourself, and thereby represent yourself in the asset 
concentration process, if you are unwilling to delegate that role to one of the 
regular candidates.
 
Randomly chosen juries are another idea worth promoting in some contexts.
 
I used to believe that DSV methods would be the wave of the future.  But DSV 
methods usually turn out to be either non-monotonic or non-deterministic.  I'm 
more willing to give up determinism than monotonicity.
 
[From here on proceed with caution.]
 
Here's a some recent thoughts along these lines (only for those aren't afraid 
of weird thoughts):
 
The DLE (Democratic Lottery Enhancement) process is monotonic, in the sense 
that if ballot set B' improves candidate X's standing compared to ballot set B, 
then lottery L enhanced by B will not give X a better chance than lottery L 
enhanced by B'.
 
Furthermore, given L, your optimal ballot for enhancing L is your sincere 
ballot.
 
However,  if you are told that the enhancement process will be iterated, then 
your sincere ballot is no longer optimal.  In particular, if some lottery is 
iterated to equilibrium, i.e. to a fixed point of the enhancement process, then 
it may not be optimal to vote sincerely.
 
But what if the equilibrium were (perhaps by chance) the original lottery, so 
that no iteration was necessary?
 
Then it depends on whether or not you knew ahead of time that the original 
lottery would be chosen from the set of  fixed points.  If you knew that, then 
you might have enough information to vote insincerely in order to change the 
set of fixed points (to your advantage) from what their positions would be on 
the basis of sincere ballots.
 
If you could vote twice, once to help determine the equilbrium lottery, and 
then again to vote optimally once that lottery was determined, then it would be 
to your advantage to vote insincerely the first time and sincerely the second 
time, but then it would turn out that the supposed equilibrium was not really 
an equilibrium.
 
Ideally, the equilbrium lottery would be determined from a random sample of 
innocent voters who had no idea why they were being polled.  Then they would 
have no reason to vote insincerely.  Etc.
 
But if you polled only innocent voters, the sample would not be random.
 
This reminds me of the uncertainty prionciple of quantum mechanics and of 
Maxwell's Demon in thermodynamics.  Here the demon would have to  filter out 
the sophisticated voters and allow only the innocents to vote.
 
I suspect that most if not all DSV equilibria, deterministic or not, will 
suffer from this same complementarity problem.
 
 
Forest
 
 
 

<<winmail.dat>>

----
election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

Reply via email to