On 04/19/2012 03:56 AM, Richard Fobes wrote:
Finally I have time to reply to Kristofer's comments about whether or
not VoteFair popularity ranking is the same as the Condorcet-Kemeny method.

If the Smith set does not contain more than six candidates, then yes
VoteFair popularity ranking always identifies the same top-ranked
candidate (the "winner") as the Condorcet-Kemeny method.

This occurs even if there are fifty (or more) candidates because the
VoteFair algorithm quickly moves to the top of the ranking the
candidates who are in the Smith set. (I'll back up this claim when I
finally have time to reply to Jameson's even-earlier message.)

The VoteFair algorithm cross-checks the top six choices using the full
sequence-score calculation method. For this reason, plus the
above-explained reason, there cannot be a discrepancy in identifying the
winner for cases that involve no more than six candidates within the
Smith set.

Okay, so you're saying VoteFair gives the same winner as Kemeny when, in Jameson's terms, N <= 6, but not necessarily when N > 6. So VoteFair is distinct from Kemeny in the strict sense.

If the Smith set contains more than six candidates, then the open-source
algorithm for calculating VoteFair popularity ranking results could
possibly identify a different "winner" compared to the Condorcet-Kemeny
method. Yet this discrepancy can only occur if the voters are not clear
in expressing any kind of consistency in their preferences, which means
there is a high level of circular ambiguity. (I hope to have time to say
more about this later.)

In such cases (involving a discrepancy) the "correct" Condorcet-Kemeny
winner would be highly controversial, and that winner could easily fail
to win a runoff election (against the VoteFair-algorithm-ranked most
popular candidate). Plus the results would be controversial regardless
of which Condorcet method were used.

Granted, but I was talking about Kemeny in the mathematical sense. You have said (or I identified you as saying, as did Warren), that VoteFair *was* Kemeny.

The Wikipedia article titled "Approximation algorithm" (at
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Approximation_algorithm) provides a name
for the relationship between the VoteFair-popularity-ranking algorithm
and the Condorcet-Kemeny method (for cases in which the Smith set
exceeds six candidates), and this is the same relationship that exists
between an algorithm that quickly and reasonably (but not _always_
_exactly_) solves the Traveling Salesman Problem and the exactly
calculated NP-hard Traveling Salesman Problem.

This matches what I've said before, but gives a specific name for the
relationship.

Yes. However, that raises another question.

Why VoteFair at all? If it is true that N <= 6 in all practical elections, then the proper, exact, integer programming formulation will always finish quickly. So we could just as easily use "proper" Kemeny. Proper Kemeny would be more elegant to mathematicians - no need to tinker with insertion sorts and pivoting. Furthermore, were by some unfortunate coincidence N to be greater than 6, proper Kemeny would satisfy all the criteria Kemeny does not just in an approximate manner, but in an exact one. In that manner, exact Kemeny scales better. Furthermore, if the voters don't care about complexity underlying a method, they're not going to care about the complexity of the integer linear programming solver that would underlie the exact Kemeny method, either.

Or to put it another way: say you constrain yourself to N <= 6. Then both exact Kemeny and VoteFair will work. Whither the advantage of VoteFair?

In logistics problems like the TSP, we have two particular properties. First, "almost right" is nearly as good as "exactly right". Second, we're dealing with very large instances so that it becomes prohibitively expensive to do an exact calculation. If all practical voting situations have N <= 6, then the second doesn't hold. If, on the other hand, N > 6 (and the voters insist on Kemeny), then the *first* doesn't hold.

Kristofer implies that the well-studied characteristics of the
Condorcet-Kemeny method cannot apply to the VoteFair popularity ranking
method if there is ever any inconsistency in the results. This
perspective is overly simplistic. Of course it is true that if the
Condorcet-Kemeny method always produces results that meets a specified
criteria, then we cannot be sure that the VoteFair popularity ranking
calculations also meet the specified criteria if the case involves more
than six candidates in the Smith set. Yet it is also true that the
VoteFair popularity ranking calculations may meet the specified
criteria. We don't know which situation applies until we check the results.

Not necessarily. One might devise proofs that state that *only* Kemeny can pass certain criteria. To quote Wikipedia:

"In 1978 Peyton Young and Arthur Levenglick showed[3] that [the Kemeny] method was the unique neutral method satisfying reinforcement and the Condorcet criterion (...)".

Reinforcement is the major criterion where Kemeny differs from the other advanced Condorcet methods. If only Kemeny can pass both Condorcet and reinforcement, then approximations of Kemeny won't. They might fail it even when N <= 6, as reinforcement concerns itself with full social orders, not just winners.

On 4/7/2012 3:19 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
 >...
 > B>C>D>A has score 44.
 > C>D>B>A has score 44.
 >
 > As far as I understood your post, those are the only with score 44.
 > VoteFair picks neither, nor does it give a direct tie between C and B.

If an implementation of the Condorcet-Kemeny method were to choose one
of these two sequences, then it would be ignoring the other sequence,
and that would ignore the whole point of the Condorcet-Kemeny method,
which is to find the sequence or sequences with the highest score. This
method says that both sequences are equally valid as sequences that have
the highest score, so both must be taken into account in order to be
consistent with the Condorcet-Kemeny method.

But I could very well claim that ignoring either sequence itself ignores the Condorcet-Kemeny method. Consider an analogy to Condorcet and Smith. The Smith set criterion is a generalized case of Condorcet in the sense that it says: if there's a "tie" (cycle) among certain candidates, then the winner should be one of the candidates in the set. Similarly, I could argue that in the case of a tie for Kemeny score, a method that passes Kemeny should pick one of the tied social orders. Otherwise someone could complain that the method gave a social ordering of score 43 when there clearly is some social ordering of score 44 that it could have picked without harming anyone.

I mentioned ties because that might give an out. If you said that "B>something and C>something are tied, thus I have to pick something that puts both B and C at first place to do justice to both parallel worlds", that might work - particularly since the definition of Kemeny scores gives room for interpretation when one considers social orders with ties.

However, VoteFair doesn't give a social ordering with a tie for first. Instead, it picks an ordering with a score of 43. Now, VoteFair may have a reason for doing so, but that reason isn't Kemeny score optimization.

Of course if these two sequences had choices B and C in the first two
positions (such as B>C>D>A and C>B>D>A) then of course choices B and C
are tied. But that is not the case.

Instead, choice B jumps from first place in the first sequence down to
third place in the second sequence, whereas choice C moves from second
place to first place.

The "official" Condorcet-Kemeny method (including Kemeny's original
description) does not specify how to resolve this situation.

The integer linear program goes like this:

1. minimize (sum for all candidates i,j) w_(i,j) * x_(i,j)

subject to

2. for all distinct candidates a, b: x(a,b) + x(b,a) = 1
3. for all distinct candidates a, b, c: x(a,b) + x(b,c) + x(c,a) >= 1
4. for all distinct candidates a, b: x(a,b) is integer.

where w(i,j) is the strength of i's defeat over j according to the transformed (wv, margins, etc) Condorcet matrix, and x(a,b) is 1 if a is ranked lower than b, 0 otherwise. The constraint designated 2. disqualifies all solutions where some pair of candidates mutually beat each other, while 3. disqualifies solutions where the triangle inequality doesn't hold (i.e. the social ordering has cycles).

From the ILP, we can see that it doesn't make any decision about which score-44 ordering it would pick. In that respect, there is a tie. However, the minimization strictly constrains the method to pick one of the score-44 orderings, something that VoteFair does not do.

The paper in which this formulation is given also defines Kemeny as follows:

"For any two candidates a and b, given a ranking r and a vote v, let delta_a,b(r,v) = 1 if r and v agree on the relative ranking of a and b (they either both rank a higher or both rank b higher) and 0 if they disagree. Let the /agreement/ of a ranking r with a vote v be given by (sum over all candidates a,b) delta_a,b(r, v), the total number of pairwise agreements. A /Kemeny ranking r/ maximizes the sum of agreements with the votes, [sum over v] [sum over a,b] [delta_a_b(r, v)]".

I.e. a Kemeny social ordering is one which maximizes the sum of agreements. The paper does not explicitly say that the Kemeny method should pick a Kemeny ordering, but that seems evident; and if it is, the only difference between a tied scenario and a non-tied scenario is how many Kemeny orderings are available for the method to choose from.

The open-source VoteFair ranking software resolves this situation by
calculating the average ranking of each choice over all the sequences
that have the same highest score. In this case, if we number the
positions starting at 1 for the beginning of the sequence, the average
ranking for choice C is 1.5, the average ranking for choice B is 2.0,
the average for choice D is 2.5, and the average for choice A is 4.0.
This puts choice C (at 1.5) above choice B (at 2.0).

So VoteFair runs a virtual Borda election among all Kemeny-optimal orders? That is one way to do it, but it isn't Kemeny.

Simplicity for the person who writes the software is a tiny issue
compared to simplicity for the voters (in terms of ballot type and
marking strategies), and compared to simplicity in terms of
understanding the algorithm (which is a big challenge for the
Condorcet-Schulze method), and compared to the issue of voters trusting
the results (which relates to mathematical arguments being difficult for
most people to understand).

Perhaps mathematical arguments are difficult for most people to understand, but I don't think that mechanism-centric arguments are all that simple, either. In VoteFair, for instance, you have the presort, the actual sort, and then quite a number of post-sort fixes to handle ambiguities. While it's not as directly impenetrable as, say, an eigenvector-based Condorcet method, that would still leave a lot of complexity.

VoteFair seems to be neither the best choice if the voters are concerned about mathematical elegance (in which case Schulze is simpler) or if they're concerned about transparency (because many things could hide in the ambiguity resolution part or the choice of sorting algorithms, and because other methods, like Ranked Pairs, are simpler). So there must be some other reason to prefer VoteFair.

If I recall correctly, Schulze says something like: A indirectly beats B by a magnitude of x if A either directly beats B by at least magnitude X, or A beats someone who indirectly beats B by at least magnitude X. A indirectly beats B (period) if A indirectly beats B by a greater magnitude than B indirectly beats A. The candidate who indirectly beats most of the other candidates wins.

Ranked Pairs is less mathematical: sort defeats in order of magnitude. Go down the list, making your social ordering consistent with the defeat unless that would contradict something you affirmed earlier.

What is VoteFair's advantage in that respect? It's not as mathematically simple (being Kemeny-but-not-just) as Schulze and it's not as mechanism-design simple as Ranked Pairs/MAM; and both of those methods are among the advanced Condorcet methods. (In addition, though I didn't mention that above, both Ranked Pairs/MAM and Schulze are cloneproof, but since Kemeny isn't, neither is VoteFair.)

As for the Condorcet-Schulze method being better known, that's because
software for it was available years ago, which relates to the concept
that it is easy to program (except for dealing with ties, which
complicates all methods). History is filled with examples of the
first-available choice not surviving over time. As one example, CPM and
MS-DOS came before MS-Windows (and that race isn't over yet).

In politics, however, precedence usually carries a very heavy weight. If it didn't, we wouldn't be saddled with Plurality in the first place. How can VoteFair counter that preference towards that which is already established? What "features", so to speak, does VoteFair have that Schulze doesn't (or Ranked Pairs doesn't)?

I regard VoteFair ranking as having advantages that are not yet
appreciated. Remember that the voting characteristics listed in the
Wikipedia "Voting system" comparison chart are just checklist-like
yes-versus-no attributes that fail to reveal how often, and under what
circumstances, each method fails each of the failed criteria. (I am not
disputing the importance of those criteria; I am saying that numeric
information can be more revealing than true/false information.)

Sure. Yet one should be careful not to walk into the trap of "oh, my method fails X but it's okay, it doesn't count". Down that road lie long arguments and counters; but if one knows a method passes a criterion, then one knows the method always does so and that there's no wiggle room for it.

If you have numbers, go ahead and show them, as well as the arguments for their importance.

 > On the other hand, if the max Smith set size is high, then VoteFair may
 > not approximate Kemeny well enough. In that case, if what you want is
 > Kemeny, then you pretty much have to go to Kemeny.

If someone wants exact Condorcet-Kemeny results for a large Smith set
then I have to wonder why. If it's needed to simulate results for
studying its mathematical characteristics, then of course that's
different from a group of voters wanting to know which candidate
deserves to win an election.

And if it's a small Smith set, then you can use a constraint program which will cover the eventuality that the Smith set isn't small.

 > The fine-tuning argument then is: it appears that for VoteFair to have a
 > substantial advantage over other Condorcet methods, the max Smith set
 > size for realistic elections have to be high enough that the other
 > methods don't approximate Kemeny but simultaneously low enough that
 > VoteFair does approximate Kemeny. Is that the case? It doesn't seem
 > clear *as such*.

I, and the people who use my software at VoteFair.org, have been getting
superbly fair results, and I have not encountered any case in which one
of the other Condorcet methods would be a better choice.

So have Andrew Myers of CIVS, to my knowledge, and he gives the results for not just one Condorcet method, but three and a half.

The advanced Condorcet methods are probably all "good enough". Thus different concerns come into play, like precedence or simplicity.

Personally my view is that there is excessive focus on single-winner
voting methods (partly because they are easier to study), yet there are
bigger frontiers waiting to be pioneered. That's why I've gone beyond
VoteFair popularity ranking to develop VoteFair representation ranking
(because the "second-most popular" choice is not the same as the
"second-most representative" choice), and VoteFair partial-proportional
ranking (which provides a PR method that is designed for the situation
in the U.S.), and VoteFair party ranking (which deals with the problem
that will arise when vote splitting is not around to limit the number of
candidates on the ballot, and which happens to minimize the cloneproof
failure ascribed to the Condorcet-Kemeny method), and VoteFair
negotiation ranking (which allows a Parliament to elect a fair slate of
Cabinet Ministers without using any quota rules to enforce fairness).

I tend to agree. I have made some multiwinner methods myself, and most of the parliamentary European countries have little need for single-winner methods - except possibly on local mayoral levels. I would say, though, that I suspect the kind of optimization that you need to do in order to get really good PR according to voters' preferences implies the method can't be polytime in the worst case.

(Perhaps you'd be interested in my proportionality/majoritarian regret tradeoff picture and data: http://munsterhjelm.no/km/elections/multiwinner_tradeoffs/ )

----
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

Reply via email to