Since it's taking longer than I expected to write a long reply to Mike's post, I'll give some criterion failures for Condorcet//FPP while I work on the reply.

Independence from clones (as I understand it) is defined as follows (Tideman, 1987, "Independence of Clones as a Criterion for Voting Rules"):

    Let X denote the set of alternatives.
Call Y (subset of) X a set of exact clones if, for all y,z (in) Y, every voter ranks y equal to z. Call Y (subset of) X a set of clones if, for all y,z (in) Y and all x (in) X\Y, every voter who ranks x over y also ranks x over z and every voter who ranks y over x also ranks z over x. For all Y (subset of) X which is a set of clones, all x (in) X\Y such that Y union {x} is not a set of exact clones, and all Y' which is a strict subset of Y, the probability that x is elected
    must not change if alternatives in Y' are deleted from all votes.

Or, less formally (but still somewhat, if I got it right):

Call Y a clone set if all candidates in Y have the property that:

- every voter who ranks a candidate in Y over some other candidate q, ranks all candidates in Y over q,

- and every voter who ranks some candidate q over a candidate in Y, ranks q over all candidates in Y.

Then eliminating a strict subset of Y should neither increase nor decrease the probability that r is elected the winner, where r is any candidate outside Y not equal-ranked with Y by every voter who ranks both Y and r.

While the formal proof does not explicitly say so, I think that "ranks A above B" means "ranks A strictly above B", since Tideman makes use of "ranks y equal to z" in his definition of a set of exact clones, and he does not mention equal-rank otherwise in the conditions for the independence from clones criterion.

-

On to some criterion failures:

If there is no truncation or no equal-rank, then (I've been told) ICT is equal to Condorcet//FPP. Hence, finding an example where Condorcet//FPP fails independence from clones with no equal-rank or truncation suffices:

        70: A > B > C
        68: B > C > A
        66: C > A > B

        There's no CW, so A wins.

        Now clone A into A1 and A2:

        35: A1 > A2 > B > C
        35: A2 > A1 > B > C
        68: B > C > A1 > A2
        66: C > A2 > A1 > B

        Now B wins. Cloning A made A lose (or B win).

And some other failures while I'm at it:

Reversal symmetry:
        1: A>B>C
        1: C>B>A
        1: B>A>C
        1: C>A>B

There's no CW and reversing every ballot leads to the same ballot set. Hence, the outcome must be A=B=C (since the method can't distinguish between this set and its reverse), but C has a Plurality count of 2 and thus wins.

Condorcet loser, majority loser, mutual majority, Smith, Schwartz, Landau, others?:
        2: A>B>C>D
        2: B>C>A>D
        3: D>C>A>B

There's no CW. The Smith set is {ABC}. 4 voters, constituting a majority, rank the candidates {ABC} above D. Yet D has the greatest FPP count and thus it wins. I also think this example shows C//FPP failing Minimal Defense, but I'm not sure - I don't know MD that well. It might also show that C//FPP fails GSFC, but I'm even less sure of that.

Independence from Smith-dominated alternatives:
Start with the Condorcet loser example above, but without D. Then C wins. Now add D, which is not in the Smith set. Then D wins, so the method fails ISDA.

Mono-add-top, Participation:
        51: A>B>C>D
        50: B>A>C>D
        50: C>B>A>D
        51: D>C>A>B
         1: D>B>C>A

There's no CW, so D wins by an FPP count of 52. Now two more D>B>C>A voters appear:

        51: A>B>C>D
        50: B>A>C>D
        50: C>B>A>D
        51: D>C>A>B
         3: D>B>C>A

        B is now the CW and wins.

----
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

Reply via email to