On 1/5/2025 7:20 PM, Jesse Mazer wrote:


On Sun, Jan 5, 2025 at 6:36 PM Bruce Kellett <bhkellet...@gmail.com> wrote:

    On Mon, Jan 6, 2025 at 10:21 AM Jesse Mazer <laserma...@gmail.com>
    wrote:

        On Sun, Jan 5, 2025 at 5:35 PM Bruce Kellett
        <bhkellet...@gmail.com> wrote:

            On Mon, Jan 6, 2025 at 9:14 AM Jesse Mazer
            <laserma...@gmail.com> wrote:

                On Sun, Jan 5, 2025 at 12:44 AM Bruce Kellett
                <bhkellet...@gmail.com> wrote:

                    On Sun, Jan 5, 2025 at 7:46 AM John Clark
                    <johnkcl...@gmail.com> wrote:


                        *About a month ago Sean Carroll uploaded a
                        very good video explaining the Many Worlds
                        theory, but it's over an hour long so I know
                        there's about as much chance of a dilettante
                        such as yourself of actually watching it is
                        there is of you reading a post of mine if it's
                        longer than about 100 words. *
                        *
                        *
                        *The Many Worlds of Quantum Mechanics | Dr.
                        Sean Carroll
                        <https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=FTmxIUz21bo&t=8s>
                        *


                    I watched this video, but it is not as
                    comprehensive as Carroll's book "Something Deeply
                    Hidden".

                    However, something came up in the question period
                    that might warrant a comment. Talking about the
                    Born rule, Carroll justifies it by saying that if
                    you measure the spin of 1000 unpolarized
                    particles, you get 2^1000 different UP-DOWN
                    sequences. However, the vast majority of these
                    sequences will show proportions of UP vs DOWN
                    close to the Born rule prediction of 50/50. In the
                    limit, if such a limit makes sense, the proportion
                    of sequences that show marked deviations from the
                    Born Rule proportions will form a set of measure
                    zero, and can be ignored.

                    That is just the law of large numbers at work, and
                    is all very well if the amplitudes are such that
                    the Born probabilities are equal to 0.5. But it is
                    easy to rotate your S-G magnets so that the Born
                    probabilities are quite different, say, 0.9-Up to
                    0.1-DOWN. Now take 1000 trials again.  According
                    to Everett, you necessarily get the same 2^1000
                    sequences of UP-DOWN that you had before. The law
                    of large numbers will then tell you that the
                    majority of these will have approximately a 50/50
                    UP/DOWN split, which is grossly in violation of
                    the Born rule result of a 90/10 split. In other
                    words, MWI. or Everettian QM. has a problem
                    reproducing the Born rule. It works in the simple
                    case of equal probabilities, but fails miserably
                    once one departs substantially from equal
                    probabilities.

                    Bruce


                David Z Albert mentions that if you define a
                measurement operator that just tells you the
                *fraction* of spin-up vs. spin-down in a large
                sequence of identical measurements, then even without
                any collapse assumption, in the limit as #
                measurements goes to infinity the wavefunction will
                approach an eigenstate of this operator that matches
                the probability that would be predicted by the Born
                rule. See his comments on p. 238 of The Cosmos of
                Science at
                
https://books.google.com/books?id=_HgF3wfADJIC&lpg=PP1&pg=PA238#v=onepage&q&f=false
                
<https://books.google.com/books?id=_HgF3wfADJIC&lpg=PP1&pg=PA238#v=onepage&q&f=false>

                "Then, even though there will actually be no matter of
                fact about what h takes the outcomes of any of those
                measurements to be, nonetheless, as the number of
                those measurements which have already been carried out
                goes to infinity, the state of the world will approach
                (not as a merely probabilistic limit, but as a
                well-defined mathematical epsilon-and-delta-type
                limit) a state in which the reports of h about the
                statistical frequency of any particular outcome of
                those measurements will be perfectly definite, and
                also perfectly in accord with the standard quantum
                mechanical predictions about what the frequency out to
                be."


            But then Albert goes on to say that there are all sorts of
            reasons why this simple theory cannot be the answer to the
            origin of the Born rule. I have pointed out one of the
            most cogent of these. If you perform similar measurements
            on N identically prepared systems (say z-spin measurements
            on systems prepared in an x-spin-left state), then
            according to Everett, you get all 2^N possible sequences
            of UP/DOWN spins. This exhausts the possibilities for the
            outcome of N trials, and, significantly, you must get
            exactly the same 2^N sequences whatever the amplitudes of
            the initial superposition might be. So you get these 2^N
            sequences if the amplitudes are equal, and also if the
            amplitudes are in the ratio 0.9/0.1. This behaviour is
            incompatible with the Born rule, and hence with ordinary
            quantum mechanics.


        You do get all these sequences but this tells us nothing about
        what their relative probabilities/frequencies are. I assume as
        an extension of his analysis, if we did repeated experiments
        where on each trial we performed exactly N measurements and
        this was repeated over many trials (approaching infinity),
        then you could define a measurement operator that would tell
        you the fraction with any specific N-sequence (for example,
        for N=3 there would be an operator giving the fraction of
        trials with result 000, likewise other operators for 001 and
        010 and 011 and 100 and 101 and 110 and 111). If you had a
        setup where the relative probability of these sequences was
        not uniform according to the Born rule, then if the number of
        trials with that setup goes to infinity, it will presumably
        likewise be true that the state approaches the eigenstate of
        this operator with the frequency predicted by the Born rule,
        without ever actually invoking the Born rule.

        Albert would presumably say that this still doesn't resolve
        the measurement problem because it doesn't give an outcome on
        any particular trial, only a sort of aggregate over many
        trials, but this is different from the criticism you are
        making. Even if we do use the Born rule in the above scenario,
        it's still true that each of the specific outcomes that are
        possible for a given trial with N measurements (eg the
        outcomes 000, 001, 010, 011, 100, 101, 110, and 111) will
        occur in the long term, but that doesn't mean they are
        equiprobable.


    The trouble that I have pointed to is that if every possible
    outcome occurs for each measurement, then the sequences are all
    present whatever the amplitudes in the wavefunction. so the
    sequences 000...,001...,010...,100...,011...,... etc are all
    equiprobable, whatever the wave function.


How do you get from "all present" to "equiprobable"? If you flip a pair of coins enough times you will surely get all the sequences HH, HT, TH and TT, but you could easily be using weighted coins that don't have 50/50 chances of landing heads and tails, in which case those 4 sequences won't occur equally often.

    Thus, the operator that Albert talks about does not give the
    relative probabilities for each sequence.


But he's talking very generally about any sort of operator that gives relative frequencies of different results of quantum experiments, so do you disagree that it's plausible this could be generalized to an operator that gives frequencies of different multi-measurement sequences in the way I described? Making N measurements in a row can itself be considered a type of repeatable experiment that has 2^N possible outcomes each time you perform it. And each of those 2^N outcomes would be assigned some probability by the Born rule, so you should be able to design an operator that gives you the frequency of any one of those 2^N outcomes, which may not be equiprobable depending on the experimental setup.
If you know what answer you want it's trivial to design an operator to give it.  You don't even need the data.



Albert's statement about the wavefunction converging to the correct eigenfunction of such an operator wasn't limited to cases where all outcomes are equiprobable, I can't say for sure but I'd expect his statement would cover this sort of case as well.
It seems to me that he generalizes from the equiprobable example to say that in the limit you will get the Born rule whatever the probability.

Brent

    Actually, Albert is talking about the case where there is only one
    outcome for each measurement.


He doesn't specify that each "outcome" has to be a single spin measurement though. There's also another presentation of the same idea (apparently called 'Mittelstaedt’s theorem') starting on p. 13 at https://www.academia.edu/6975159/Quantum_dispositions_and_the_notion_of_measurement and it seems to be stated in a very general way, talking about an operator that gives "the relative frequency of the outcome a_k in a given sequence of N outcomes" without placing any conditions on an "outcome" only involving a single particle measurement.

Jesse
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group. To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com. To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAPCWU3KA_eot8RQ5%2BkhtXZz_%2BZL3gYy1ygvFm9So3k%2BjQK9MVw%40mail.gmail.com <https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAPCWU3KA_eot8RQ5%2BkhtXZz_%2BZL3gYy1ygvFm9So3k%2BjQK9MVw%40mail.gmail.com?utm_medium=email&utm_source=footer>.

--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
"Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email 
to everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit 
https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/83288a3d-01b3-42da-90d7-c37baec1f50f%40gmail.com.

Reply via email to