Dear Bruno, 
Thanks for your nice and kind comments!
I'm honoured that you got through my manuscript.
--
Inviato da Libero Mail per Android lunedì, 25 settembre 2017, 07:47PM +02:00 da 
Bruno Marchal  marc...@ulb.ac.be :

>Dear Arturo,
>
>
>On 24 Sep 2017, at 21:35,  tozziart...@libero.it wrote:
>>Dear FISers,
>>
>>This text is brief is an effort to provide a viable solution for a double 
>>concern:
>>a)    1)  the proliferation of models, theories and interpretations that 
>>suggest pseudoscientific explanations (e.g., lacking the even theoretical 
>>possibility of empiric testability) for not-observable quantities, such as 
>>“God”, the “quantum brain”, “phenomenalistic” accounts of experience, 
>>“holistic” accounts of “Nirvana-like” psychological states, “observer-based 
>>information”, “string theories”, “quantum loop gravity” theories, and so on.
>>b)     2)  the attitude of scientists to generalize their results beyond 
>>their own experimental observations.  For example, it is easy to read, in the 
>>CONCLUSIONS of good papers, claims such as: “we demonstrated that some 
>>Primates acquired the vision of the red; this occurred because this novel 
>>ability gave them the evolutionary benefit to detect red soft fruits in the 
>>green bushes’ background”. 
>> 
>>In order to avoid the inconsistencies that undermine the (otherwise good) 
>>legitimacy of scientific claims and to make them as accurate as possible, 
>>here we provide a few suggestions concerning the very structure of scientific 
>>propositions.
>>Our formulation of the required language for scientific propositions wants to 
>>be as simple as possible and, at the same time, to encompass syntactic, 
>>semantic and pragmatic concerns.    We take into account the claims of 
>>several Authors and sources who tackled the difficult issue to cope with the 
>>structure of scientific language: Galileo, Mach, Frege, Brower, Carnap, 
>>Popper, Quine, Godel, Zermelo and Fraenkel, Brigdman, Feyerabend, Kellogg and 
>>Bourland, Kripke, Gadamer, McGinn, Badiou.
>> 
>>We suggest, so as to describe facts and observables of our physical and 
>>social environment, to make use of phrases written or spoken according to the 
>>following rules (provided in sparse order):
>> 
>>1)     1)    Never use the verb “to be”, including all its conjugations, 
>>contractions and archaic forms.  Indeed, the misuse of this verb might give 
>>rise to a “deity mode of speech” that allows people “to transform their 
>>opinions magically into god-like pronouncements on the nature of things” 
>>(Kellogg and Bourland, 1990-91)
>
>I think I understand. But it is hard in practice to avoid existential words. I 
>would say: be clear of what is assumed, and what is derived, and if the 
>derivation is ontological or phenomenological. "to be" has many meanings, and 
>the effort must be to reason validly with each of the possible meaning. (cf 
>Frege, Carnap, Quine, Godel, Zermelo and Fraenkel).
>
>
>
>
>
>
>>2)     2)    Clearly define the universe of discourse in which your 
>>proposition is located.
>
>Yes, that is important. But some domain, like metaphysics or theology will 
>have multidisciplinar facets. 1) above still applies. 
>
>
>
>>3)     3)   Define your concepts not in abstract terms, but in terms either 
>>of observables, or, if observables are not properly definable, in a language 
>>as closest to observable quantities as possible.
>I agree. But that should be only on "observable in principle". How we could 
>kill the next good theory, which not only predict better, but linked the many 
>observable better.
>
>Here, if doing metaphysics, it is important to distinguish, observable, 
>believable, knowable, justifiable and ... true. 
>
>
>
>>4)     4)    Do not compare and mix sets and subsets in the same context 
>>(e.g., cat and feline).
>And don't confuse A included in B, with B included in A, like the paper 
>justifying prohibition of "drugs" do systematically.
>
>
>>5)     5)    Do not use the first order logic (based on universals described 
>>in the very premises of the propositions), rather describe just the 
>>relationships between the observables you are coping with.
>Why? First order logic is the best tool to avoid metaphysical baggage. But it 
>is OK to use set theory or second order logic. It will really depends on the 
>goal.
>>6)     6)    Use (at least qualitative) terms that indicate the probability 
>>of an event.  
>
>Or laws that such probabilities have to conform with. Some theories can 
>predict higher order relation between measurable numbers.
>
>
>>7)     7)    Describe events or things that are (at least in principle) 
>>testable.  
>
>OK. That's imporant too.
>
>
>>Otherwise, state clearly that yours is just a speculation.
>
>In the case of "my theory", it is a subtheory of all theories in physics, and 
>of most of math. So it is obviously the less speculative theory, except for 
>one strong axiom, two actually (Church thesis, and the existence of a digital 
>substitution level). Some would argued that the theory of evolution would not 
>make sense without assuming some mechanist subtitution level, to get notably 
>the redundancy and the error tolerance).
>
>In metaphysics, when aboarded with the scientific attitude, we must be aware 
>that Aristotle's assumption of the existence of a primary physical universe 
>(physicalism) is a speculation until now, when we can test it against 
>mechanism. A bit like with the violation of Bell's inequality which makes 
>possible concludes "action-at-a-distance OR superposition propagate on their 
>environments (many-histories/worlds)". Metaphysics enters the experimental 
>realm, and not just through physics.
>>  
>>8)     8)    Do not generalize your descriptions, but take into account just 
>>the specific content of what you are assessing.  
>
>To talk about laws and make prediction, we have to generalize. Without 
>generalization, there is no testing possible.
>
>
>
>>9)     9)    Be as vague as possible about cause/effect relationships. 
>
>?
>
>Be valid about them, which asks for not being too much vague. I think. Vague, 
>means generalization. I think I have to disagree with 8) and 9) for the same 
>reason. 
>
>
>
>
>>1010)       10)    Do not make inferences not supported by your data.  
>
>I agree.
>
>
>
>>11)         11)     Do not use too formal or specialized languages.
>
>Use them appropriately. I would just say. depending on the hypothesis and the 
>domain, formal things (like physical objects notably) are the things about 
>which we theorize, and when people want the real things, you have to name a 
>cat a cat, and carbon dioxyde CO_2.
>
>
>>12)           12)     Try you hidden your own theory-laden approach and your 
>>personal considerations.   
>
>Absolutely.
>
>
>
>> 
>>
>>Here we provide a few practical examples.
>>
>>John is nice.
>>A lot of people state that John looks pleasant. 
>> 
>>E=mc 2   
>>In our Universe, it has been demonstrated that a given experimentally 
>>measured value of energy corresponds to a experimentally measured value of 
>>mass at rest, multiplied for the fixed value of the speed light constant.
>
>E = mc^2 is more vague, and to say "in our Universe .." should be: "in our 
>current theory of the universe (which is still inconsistent (cf gravity and 
>quantum)), theoiry coming from many (but finite) number of evidences, we 
>assume that a given experimentally measured value of energy corresponds to a 
>experimentally measured value of mass at rest, multiplied for the fixed value 
>of the speed light constant.
>
>More or less OK, although some translation seems more jargon in some, and 
>remind me of political correctness.
>
>
>
>>The brain is equipped with a functional and anatomical network consisting of 
>>edges and nodes, termed the connectome.
>>When researchers experimentally assess brain activity and anatomy in terms of 
>>network theory, they find anatomical and functional structures that fully fit 
>>their theoretical framework and that they term the “connectome”. 
>> 
>>John is ill, because he took the flu.
>>John suffers an alteration of his statistically normal biological parameters, 
>>because his Medical Doctor diagnosed, based on clinical and epidemiological 
>>findings, the highly-probable occurrence of an infection due to the Influenza 
>>virus.
>
>This one!
>
>
>> 
>>Scientific studies of the brain must take into account the first-person, 
>>epistemological phenomenalistic standpoint, because the latter is the only 
>>way to gain sure knowledge.
>>Some scientists and philosophers believe, in touch with the accounts of the 
>>philosophical mainstream of the “phenomenalism”, that the better way to gain 
>>knowledge from neuroscientific experimental procedures is to assess the 
>>subjective first-person account, rather than the individual-unrelated 
>>experimental findings detectable by objective operational procedures.
>
>Here the problem is that we have not yet the solution of the mind-body 
>problem, and many implicit assumptions are made, in both sentences.
>I certainly want a dentist taking into account the phenomenal pain which would 
>occur for his patient if he does not use some pain killer in the process. 
>
>Also, if the subject of study is the first person experience, it is obvious we 
>have to compile many experiential reports, and try to interpret them in some 
>way.
>
>Thank you for the effort. Some of your points are very important. Others are 
>more debatable, I would say.
>
>Best regards.
>
>Bruno
>
>
>
>> 
>>
>>REFERENCES
>>1)        Badiou A. 2005.  Being and Event, transl. by Oliver Feltham, New 
>>York: Continuum.   
>>2)        Brigdman PW.  1959. The Way Things Are. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard 
>>University Press.
>>3)        Brouwer LEJ. 1976. Collected Works, Vol. II, Amsterdam: 
>>North-Holland.
>>4)        Carnap R.  1947. Meaning and Necessity: a Study in Semantics and 
>>Modal Logic. University of Chicago Press, 1957.
>>5)        Feyerabend PK. 1981.  Realism, Rationalism and Scientific Method: 
>>Philosophical papers, Volume 1. 
>>6)        Frege G.  1879.  Concept Notation, the Formal Language of the Pure 
>>Thought like that of Arithmetics.
>>7)        Galileo G. 1932. Dialogo sopra i due massimi sistemi del mondo. 
>>8)        Godel K. 1940. The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the 
>>Generalized Continuum Hypothesis with the Axioms of Set Theory. Princeton 
>>University Press.
>>9)        Kellogg EW. Bourland Jr DD.  1990-91. Working with E-Prime: Some 
>>Practical Notes.   Etc. 47 (4):  376-392. 
>>10)    Kripke S. 1972. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard 
>>University Press.
>>11)    Mach E. 1897. The Analysis of Sensations.  
>>12)    McGinn C. 2004. Consciousness and Its Objects. Oxford University Press.
>>13)    Popper K. 1963. Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific 
>>Knowledge.  
>>14)    Quine WVO. 1963. Set Theory and Its Logic. Harvard Univ. Press, 1969.  
>>15)    Gadamer H-G. 1981. Reason in the Age of Science. Trans. by Frederick 
>>Lawrence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
>>16)    Zermelo E., Ebbinghaus H-D; Fraser CG, Kanamori A.   2013. eds., Ernst 
>>Zermelo—collected works. Vol. I. Set theory, miscellanea, Schriften der 
>>Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftlichen Klasse der Heidelberger Akademie der 
>>Wissenschaften, 21, Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
>>
>>
>>
>>
>>If you want to quote this manuscript, please write: 
>>Tozzi A.  2017.  A pragmatic language for scientific purposes.  ViXra,  
>>http://vixra.org/abs/1709.0362
>>
>>
>>
>>Arturo Tozzi
>>AA Professor Physics, University North Texas
>>Pediatrician ASL Na2Nord, Italy
>>Comput Intell Lab, University Manitoba
>>http://arturotozzi.webnode.it/  
>>
>>_______________________________________________
>>Fis mailing list
>>Fis@listas.unizar.es
>>http://listas.unizar.es/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/fis
>
>http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/
>
>
>
>_______________________________________________
>Fis mailing list
>Fis@listas.unizar.es
>http://listas.unizar.es/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/fis
_______________________________________________
Fis mailing list
Fis@listas.unizar.es
http://listas.unizar.es/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/fis

Reply via email to