Let me give this a try. Moral hazard, yes, is a kind of market failture, but
one rooted in psychology. We desperately want there to be low-cost solutions
to climate change. So, each time a "solution" arrives that looks like it is
low cost, we embrace it and are not adequately critical. That's just how
we're wired. Moral hazard captures the tendency to self-deception. If we
assessed low-cost proposals with appropriate skepticism, there would be no
problem. The arrrival of each new "solutions: should lower our level of
effort on what we are already getting ready to do, but we allow these
"solutions" to distract us -- we systematically overvalue them -- and thus
we lower our level of effort more than we should. We know thjis is one of
our own weaknesses, and we are trying to warn ourselves.
 
We need cognitive psychologists here to frame these issues better than I
have.
 
Rob

  _____  

From: geoengineering@googlegroups.com
[mailto:geoengineer...@googlegroups.com] On Behalf Of Lane, Lee O.
Sent: Saturday, September 18, 2010 2:39 PM
To: Ken Caldeira
Cc: joshuahorton...@gmail.com; geoengineering; David Keith
Subject: RE: [geo] Re: Fwd: NERC Geoengineering dialogue report published
today


Dear Ken,
 
A good suggestion. The list that you provide is a reasonable one. I would
add that my understanding is that moral hazard refers to a specific kind of
market failure. It is not just risky behavior. A simple definition that I
think corresponds quite well to the way that the term is commonly used Is:
 
"The risk that the existence of a contract will change the behavior of one
or both parties to the contract, e.g. an insured firm will take fewer fire
precautions. " Asymmetric information between the contracting parties is a
typical feature moral hazard problems. The insurer or principal knows less
than the insured or agent about the latter's behavior or state. 
 
Climate engineering is not such a case. It's a policy choice by government.
There is no contract. There is no information asymmetry. True, risk is
involved, but GHG control also implies accepting some risks in order to curb
others. Nobody argues that emission limits entail moral hazard, and no one
should. People can agree or disagree about the prudence of either or both
approaches. As you know, I would buy some of both, but neither of the
policies has much in common with insurers' or share owners' options as they
try to align the incentives of the insured or their firm managers' with
their own interests. 
 
These just seem to me to present issues that are quite different from the
optimization problems under uncertainty entailed by climate change. And as
my previous post suggested, trying to force climate policy into this mold
seems to me to invite misunderstanding of the issues at hand.  
 
Lee     

  _____  

From: kcalde...@gmail.com on behalf of Ken Caldeira
Sent: Sat 9/18/2010 12:23 PM
To: Lane, Lee O.
Cc: joshuahorton...@gmail.com; geoengineering; David Keith
Subject: Re: [geo] Re: Fwd: NERC Geoengineering dialogue report published
today


Lee,

It would help in this discussion to provide a clear definition of "moral
hazard" and then say why or why not that definition is relevant in this
context.

If you look on the web, you can get quite a range of definitions:
http://www.google.com/search?q=define%3A+moral+hazard

The first definition that comes up is:

Moral Hazard (economics) the lack of any incentive to guard against a risk
when you are protected against it (as by insurance)

The UN Capital Development Fund defines it as follows:

Moral Hazard arises from the incentive of an agent holding an asset
belonging to another person to endanger the value of that asset because the
agent bears less than the full consequences of any loss.

So, the question is "Why are these definitions not relevant to climate
intervention?"

By the way, most but not all definitions of "moral hazard" do not imply that
"moral hazard" has anything to do with morality.

Climate intervention seeks to diminish risk and not simply transfer risk,
which is one distinguishing factor.

Here is a little parable:

Let's say that people think you should change farming practices to slow
runoff to decrease flooding downstream. Let's further say that people
downstream build dikes to prevent flooding despite poor upstream land use
practices. Would we say that a moral hazard of building dikes is that it
will relieve pressure on people living upstream to improve their land use
practices (which could have other co-benefits, such as limiting nutrient
runoff)?

[The analogy is that CO2 emission reduction gets at fundamental cause of
problem, has other co-benefits (e.g. w.r.t. ocean acidification) but that
climate intervention may really reduce risk and not just transfer risk.]

Anyway, Lee, it would be nice if you would provide what you think is a good
definition for "moral hazard" and then clearly explain why you think it does
not apply in this case.

Best,

Ken

PS. David Keith may want to chime in, as I think he was one of the first to
use "moral hazard" in this context and now wishes he had been more precise
with his language.

___________________________________________________
Ken Caldeira

Carnegie Institution Dept of Global Ecology
260 Panama Street, Stanford, CA 94305 USA
+1 650 704 7212 kcalde...@carnegie.stanford.edu 
http://dge.stanford.edu/labs/caldeiralab  @kencaldeira



On Sat, Sep 18, 2010 at 8:56 AM, Lane, Lee O. <leol...@crai.com> wrote:


Dear Josh,

 

I would suggest that in the future we would all be better off without the
term "moral hazard". Moral hazard, as I suspect you know, is a kind of
market failure. The concept is perfectly useful for describing a class of
problems that arise in insurance markets and other kinds of risk-spreading
contracts. It does not, I would argue, fit the case of climate engineering
(CE) at all well.

 

The relative priority of climate engineering and GHG control is a matter of
public policy. It does not involve insurance markets or contracting. The
asymmetric knowledge, so typical of moral hazards, does not obtain.   

 

In fact, if CE works and does not cause unacceptable side effects, it would
lower the expected damage from an adding a ton of CO2 to the atmosphere. As
a result, optimal carbon tax rates or emission allowance prices would fall,
and the optimal pace of controls would slow. 

 

True, even if CE works well, it may exhibit diminishing marginal returns,
and it does not combat ocean acidification. Thus, controls retain some
value; so does adaptation. The three approaches, as Scott Barrett has often
noted, are imperfect substitutes. (Doing more of one implies doing less of
the others, but there is a limit to how far that substitution can stretch.)
Each of the three is likely to encounter rising marginal costs; hence,
relying over-much on any one of them will lower over-all cost effectiveness.

 

In this context, the term moral hazard adds nothing but confusion. Its
misuse can be taken to imply that sole reliance on GHG control is somehow
the correct response. Indeed the naïve may take it that controls are the
only “moral” response. The more we think, speak, and write in these
evocative but misleading terms the harder it becomes to see that climate
policy should entail finding the most cost beneficial mix of strategies for
dealing with a compound challenge in the face of uncertainty. 

 

Josh, I suspect that you know all of this; indeed, you could probably write
it more articulately than I have. My guess is that you use the term merely
as a convenience. Its misuse has seemed to take root in the debate about CE.
Maybe it is too late to expunge it. Still, I would urge that we at least
avoid sowing further confusion—even if it involves taking a little extra
trouble to explain. 

 

Best regards,

 

Lee Lane   

 



  

 

 

 

One of the more interesting findings pertains to the "moral hazard"
argument against geoengineering, that is, people will embrace
geoengineering as an excuse to avoid emissions reductions, and current
levels of fossil fuel consumption will persist if not increase. Moral
hazard has emerged as one of the principal arguments against climate
engineering, despite the fact that geoengineering advocates generally
support aggressive mitigation as the preferred option, and are quick
to note the limitations of specific strategies, such as continued
ocean acidification and the so-called "termination problem" in the
case of stratospheric aerosol injections.

Evidence from the public dialogue summarized in the NERC report
indicates that participants viewed mitigation and geoengineering as
complementary policies, not as mutually exclusive alternatives.
Stakeholders saw a link between geoengineering and emissions controls,
and preferred a suite of mitigation and geoengineering measures to
reliance on any single approach. "This evidence is contrary to the
'moral hazard' argument that geoengineering would undermine popular
support for mitigation or adaptation," notes the report. While this
study represents only one set of empirical data gathered in one
particular sociocultural context, it is to my knowledge the first time
the moral hazard argument has been tested, and demonstrates little
support for this proposition.

Josh Horton
joshuahorton...@gmail.com
http://geoengineeringpolitics.blogspot.com/


On Sep 9, 10:45 am, Emily <em...@lewis-brown.net> wrote:
>   best wishes,
> Emily.
>
> Dear Colleague,
>
> NERC has published the final report of Experiment Earth? , our public
> dialogue on geoengineering. It can be found
at:http://www.nerc.ac.uk/about/consult/geoengineering.asptogether with a
> short leaflet summarising the findings and recommendations from the
report.
>
> The latest issue of NERC's Planet Earth magazine also contains an
> article about the public dialogue, which can be found
here:http://planetearth.nerc.ac.uk/features/story.aspx?id=744
>
> Regards,
>
> Peter
>
> Peter Hurrell
>
> Stakeholder Liaison Officer | Policy and Partnerships Team
>
> Natural Environment Research Council (NERC)
>
> Putting NERC science to use: find out more through NERC s Science
> Impacts Database <http://sid.nerc.ac.uk/>
>
> --
> This message (and any attachments) is for the recipient only. NERC
> is subject to the Freedom of Information Act 2000 and the contents
> of this email and any reply you make may be disclosed by NERC unless
> it is exempt from release under the Act. Any material supplied to
> NERC may be stored in an electronic records management system.

--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
"geoengineering" group.
To post to this group, send email to geoengineer...@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to
geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
<mailto:geoengineering%2bunsubscr...@googlegroups.com> .
For more options, visit this group at
http://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering?hl=en.





-- 
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
"geoengineering" group.
To post to this group, send email to geoengineer...@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to
geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com
<mailto:geoengineering%2bunsubscr...@googlegroups.com> .
For more options, visit this group at
http://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering?hl=en.



-- 
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
"geoengineering" group.
To post to this group, send email to geoengineer...@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to
geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit this group at
http://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering?hl=en.

-- 
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
"geoengineering" group.
To post to this group, send email to geoengineer...@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering?hl=en.

Reply via email to