Professor Smith, cc List

        1.  This is to urge that in your forthcoming Part II, you avoid the 
word “geoengineering” - and instead refer to SRM (solar radiation management) 
and CDR (carbon dioxide removal), according to your intent.  Because you at one 
point refer to ocean iron fertilization, one could believe your really did mean 
to treat them identically.  I don’t believe that the case as other papers I 
found you have written came to the same negative conclusion about only SRM - 
not geoengineering.  Thanks for making these other papers available.
        
        2.  I believe CDR is critically needed, but your lumping CDR together 
with your obvious target of SRM can easily cause readers who are new to “geo” 
to believe they all forms of CDR suffer from the same risks as SRM.   I don’t 
think you believe that, but I fear your essay will be used against CDR.

        3.   But the 10 or so CDR approaches are also vastly different.  It is 
just as important that they also all not be considered as identical.   The 
recent identification of a new paper by Professor Svoboda, somewhat like your 
paper, is helpful in raising the subject of “hybrid” geoengineering.  This is a 
helpful, and I think new, approach for this list, which I will expand on 
separately.  There is certainly a range of possible hybrids out there awaiting 
comparison.

        4.  I do think it valuable for persons like yourself to raise these 
issues;  thanks for taking it seriously.  I look forward to reading about civil 
disobedience - especially with the CDR concept getting some attention.

Ron


> On May 19, 2016, at 3:24 AM, Andrew Lockley <andrew.lock...@gmail.com> wrote:
> 
> 
> http://dcgeoconsortium.org/2016/05/18/who-may-geoengineer-self-defense-civil-disobedience-and-revolution-part-one/
>  
> <http://dcgeoconsortium.org/2016/05/18/who-may-geoengineer-self-defense-civil-disobedience-and-revolution-part-one/>
> Who May Geoengineer: Self-defense, Civil Disobedience, and Revolution (Part 
> One) – Patrick Taylor Smith
> 
> Much of the discussion about the appropriateness or usefulness of 
> geoengineering—particularly dangerous and risky geoengineering strategies 
> like sulfate aerosol injection—has relied upon a shared assumption aboutwho 
> will end up deploying these new tools. That is, we’ve (mostly) assumed that 
> fairly wealthy, high-emitting states, private actors based in those 
> countries, or international institutions dominated by those states will be 
> the ones to finally inject sulfates or fertilize the ocean. This is entirely 
> reasonable. Rich and high emitting states have the resources (or contain 
> private agents with the resources) to engage in geoengineering research and, 
> potentially, deployment. Powerful states will have the political wherewithal 
> to either ignore the entreaties of global governance institutions and civil 
> society, or to gain their assent. From a practical perspective, the rich and 
> powerful states are those that are likely to fund the research that would be 
> needed should risky geoengineering strategies ever be deployed, and perhaps 
> even if they are not.
> 
> Yet, there is something odd, from a normative perspective, about this 
> emphasis. After all, geoengineering is presented as a solution to a problem 
> that has been—to a great extent—created by rich and powerful, high emitting 
> nations. There is something unsavory—or as Stephen Gardiner has put it, 
> morally corrupting—about the idea that rich countries would geoengineer in 
> order to allow them to retain a greater proportion of the benefits they’ve 
> accrued from emitting in the first place. Of course, one can try to justify 
> risky geoengineering as a way of reducing the negative impacts of climate 
> change on the poor, marginalized, and low-emitting. But again, this is an odd 
> argument for those responsible for those impacts to make: “I’ve caused a 
> terrible threat to hang over your head and I’ll remove it through a strategy 
> that is risky for you but more convenient for me.” So, the idea that rich 
> countries could justify risky climate strategies by appealing to the 
> protection of the people their policies endanger is problematic.
> 
> What can we say if this nation decides to engage in an act of self-defense, 
> protecting its territorial integrity and political autonomy from the actions 
> of more powerful nations?
> 
> This kind of worry doesn’t apply if those victims themselves decide to 
> geoengineer. They are simply defending themselves, or so the thought goes. 
> Let’s consider a scenario (borrowed liberally from Oliver Morton in The 
> Planet Remade); imagine a fairly wealthy but low emitting island nation that 
> will suffer catastrophic flooding. Adaptation measures are either unavailable 
> or prohibitively expensive. So, what can we say if this nation—that is not 
> responsible for climate change but nonetheless suffering from its ill 
> effects—decides to engage in an act of self-defense, protecting its 
> territorial integrity and political autonomy from the actions of more 
> powerful nations? Consider an analogous case. Suppose that a nation builds a 
> dam which it knows will destroy all of the arable land of a neighboring 
> country. It seems pretty clear that the the flooded state can—assuming that 
> it met all of the conditions of just war—engage in a military action to 
> destroy the dam. In other words, risky geoengineering could very well be a 
> response to a set of bad consequences that—under different 
> circumstances—would justify going to war. And if something as potentially 
> risky and dangerous as military action could be justified, then it seems hard 
> to deny that similarly risky geoengineering could be as well.
> 
> There is something appealing about this scenario. The weak and powerless get 
> to take matters into their own hands and defend themselves from the 
> predations and exploitation of the rich and powerful. Setting aside any 
> contingent issues about proportionality, effectiveness, or necessity, I want 
> to suggest that there nonetheless some problems with thinking about 
> geoengineering this way. Consider two different scenarios.
> 
> Accident: I am attacked by a ninja assassin. I defend myself by firing a gun 
> at the assassin, but I miss and the bullet goes through the wall, striking an 
> innocent bystander.Redirection: I see that a ninja assassin is about to 
> attack me, but I change the number on my apartment so that the assassin 
> attacks my innocent neighbor.
> 
> While fully working out the difference between the two examples would take a 
> lot more argument than a single blog post, it seems pretty clear to me that 
> Accident is much more easily justified or defended thanRedirection. And this 
> is not merely due to risk; after all, I know that firing a gun in an 
> apartment complex is a dangerous thing to do and that changing my address 
> might not actually work. The difference, or so it seems to me, is how I use 
> the death of the innocent bystander. In one case (Redirection), the death 
> is—in some sense—a necessary part of defending myself and in the other 
> (Accident) it seems like a merely contingent feature of the case. In 
> Redirect, I seem to be allying myself with the ninja assassin in order to 
> kill my neighbor. That does not seem to be true in Accident. The conclusion 
> we can draw is that even when there is an uncontroversial and obvious case of 
> self-defense, you are not allowed to dojust anything in order to save 
> yourself.
> 
> Potentially dangerous geoengineering activities—like iron fertilization or 
> sulfate aerosol injections—will inflict harm on others in the course of 
> saving our island nation. And these people will be disproportionately those 
> who are also suffering and suffering innocently from climate change (note, if 
> you redirected the ninja assassin to killanother ninja assassin that is 
> coming to kill you, that might be okay, but that isn’t the case here). So, is 
> dangerous geoengineering more like Accident or Redirection? I leave it to the 
> reader to make their own judgment, but I want to point out two things. First, 
> it is interesting that the potential permissibility of dangerous 
> geoengineering might ride on a fairly subtle distinction in moral philosophy; 
> trolley problems are not so impractical or useless. Second, I think there is 
> a strong case to be made that dangerous geoengineering is a redirection (see 
> my commentary in Ethics, Policy, and the Environment for a somewhat longer 
> case)Redirecting Threats, the Doctrine of Doing and Allowing, and the Special 
> Wrongness of Solar Radiation Management, Ethics, Policy, and the Environment 
> 17, no. 2, pp. 143-146 (2014) . The key feature of sulfate injections—for 
> example—is the very mechanisms that make it is so effective as a potential 
> shield also create the negative impacts. The bullet hitting the bystander in 
> Accident plays no role in making the gun a useless tool for defending myself, 
> but the very cooling effects that make SRM useful are also what make it 
> dangerous; they seem very closely linked.
> 
> Of course, I could be wrong about that. But the fact that dangerous 
> geoengineering looks like a redirection of a threat against an innocent 
> population would, if true, seriously undermine any claim that it can be used 
> in self-defense.
> 
> Next up in part two: Civil disobedience and the global governance
> 
> Patrick Taylor Smith, PhD, is an Assistant Professor in the Department of 
> Political Science at the National University of Singapore.  He is writing a 
> book titled “A Leap Into Darkness: Domination and the Normative Structure of 
> International Politics,” and researches climate change and climate 
> engineering. His papers can be found here.
> 
> 
> -- 
> You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
> "geoengineering" group.
> To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an 
> email to geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com 
> <mailto:geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com>.
> To post to this group, send email to geoengineering@googlegroups.com 
> <mailto:geoengineering@googlegroups.com>.
> Visit this group at https://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering 
> <https://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering>.
> For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout 
> <https://groups.google.com/d/optout>.

-- 
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
"geoengineering" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email 
to geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
To post to this group, send email to geoengineering@googlegroups.com.
Visit this group at https://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering.
For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout.

Reply via email to