Time to try to answer some of Barkley Rosser's questions.

1.  There were two main aspects of my postings on the LTV, relating 
respectively to the formation of prices in capitalist economies and to 
the issue of rational costing in a planned economy.  In my last posting 
(part 12) I argued that these questions were at least loosely 
connected; nonetheless they are analytically separable.  Barkley's 
questions seem to pertain primarily to the second question; at any rate, 
I shall answer them in that light.  

2.  Barkley raises two concerns, regarding (1) the putative 
*uniqueness* or special privilege of the LTV among X-content 
theories of value, and (2) the *adequacy* of the LTV for a rational 
costing.  Basically, he seems to reckon that the LTV is neither unique 
nor adequate.  I shall deal with these points in turn.  

3.  Uniqueness: Barkley is right to say that in principle any Sraffian 
"basic," X, may be selected as the base for an X-content theory of 
value; but as I remarked in LTV defense, part 12, there are two 
further requirements on non-labor X if the resulting XTV is to be at all 
meaningful, let alone genuinely relevant.  X must *not* be prodicible 
using only labor and natural materials that are for practical purposes 
inexhaustible; and X must be treatable as homogeneous, as a tolerable 
approximation.  Question to Barkley: Would he dispute that?  

4.  On a couple of occasions, Barkley has floated "land" as a suitable 
X.  But what does he mean by "land"?  I presume he doesn't mean 
literally floor-space on the planet, so to speak, but is using "land" in 
the generic sense to refer to non-reproducible natural resources (?).  
But in that case, land clearly fails the homogeneity requirement: it has 
no natural units.  The embodied "land"-content of a certain commodity 
might be say (x bauxite, y uranium, z crude oil, p iron ore, q 
germanium, ...).  How are these elements supposed to be added up?  
In terms of their mass, their volume, or what?  

5.  Barkley has said that labor too is heterogeneous.  Well, yes it is; 
but at an intuitive level, adding up hours of human labor-time seems 
much more meaningful than adding up kilograms or cubic meters of 
oil, iron ore, uranium, etc.  How may this intuition be supported?  
Labor is the supremely flexible resource.  With the exception of 
certain talents that require an extraordinary genetic endowment, 
people can be taught to do almost anything (but try to teach a 
Norwegian hillside to grow olive trees, or germanium to power a jet 
engine).  And this means that while specific labors do differ in their 
particular skills, these particularities can, for the most part, be "cashed 
out" or reduced in terms of further labor inputs (i.e. the labor-time 
involved in education and training).  I think that Bob Rowthorn has 
written on this point; Paul Cockshott and I certainly address it in our 
book on socialism.  As a secondary point, given the highly complex 
division of labor that characterizes a modern economy, most goods 
are likely to contain (directly or indirectly) quite a thorough mixture of 
different sorts of specific labors.  

6.  In light of the above, I don't see that Barkley has seriously 
damaged the uniqueness claim I made on behalf of the LTV.  It would 
take very special circumstances (where a *specific* natural resource, 
homogeneous to a tolerable approximation, is definitely the limiting 
factor on production, economy-wide) to make a non-labor XTV a 
serious competitor to the LTV.  

7.  I now turn to the question of *adequacy*.  Here I would second 
what Paul C. has already said.  No scalar X-content figure can be 
expected to give a fully adequate representation of the cost of 
producing a given good (not even if X is labor) -- but then, *neither 
can any other scalar one chooses to attach to the good*, be it a 
Sraffian price or an actual market price.  The claim on behalf of the 
LTV is that labor-content (a) accounts for most of the bits carried by 
actual prices in capitalist economies, and (b) provides an 
indispensable basis for rational costing in a planned system.  Focussing 
on the second of these points, we would readily agree that labor-
content, while an indispensable basis, is not enough.  A calculus of 
labor-time must be supplemented by other decision criteria.  But how?

8.  Take Barkley's example of over-fishing leading to the destruction 
of fish populations.  Suppose the marine biologists are able to tell us 
the maximum annual tonnage of catch consistent with the continued 
reproduction of the fish population.  This should then be a 
*parameter* for the planning of fisheries.  Other things equal, one 
wants to use the fishing method that minimizes the total labor-time 
required per tonne of catch; but if something about that method will 
lead to the destruction of fish stocks, it is out of bounds.  The 
requirements of environmental stewardship properly override the 
labor-time calculus.  

9.  More generally, consider the moves towards environmental 
protection in advanced capitalist economies.  Are these an *effect* of 
the working of the price system?  Of course not.  The banning of 
CFCs, the mandating of lead-free gasoline, the limitation of sulfur 
dioxide emissions, and so on, are accomplished by governmental 
regulation, in response to pressures from the general population or the 
environmentalist lobby or the scientific community.  In a democratic 
socialist economy, the same pressures would operate.  Just as the 
imperatives of profit-maximization are (sometimes) overriden by 
environmental/conservationist concerns under capitalism, so may the 
application of a labor-time calculus, in a planned system, be 
constrained by the same concerns.  Paul and I have argued in our 
book that it is a mystification to suppose that environmental issues, 
involving non-reproducible resources, can be "factored into" a scalar 
representation of cost: they must, if people regard them as important, 
be imposed as external constraints on narrowly "economic" 
calculation.  


==========================
Allin Cottrell 
Department of Economics 
Wake Forest University
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
(910) 759-5762
==========================

Reply via email to