Maggie C. writes: >> That magic is reality and physical reality 
is a manifestation of magic. Poisonally, I think there may be 
some truth in this. After all, how much magic and how much 
reality exists in economic theory as taught in most universities? 
I also think we make physical reality by our beliefs. If we 
believe that pollution will not take over the world, we will 
continue to pollute....<<

I think that the answer here is in the distinction I made before 
between the practical social construction of reality and the 
epistemological social construction of reality. Yes, there are 
self-fulfilling prophecies, where thinking that the stock market 
is going to crash (or that women are fragile or pollution is 
inevitable) actually causes the market to crash, women not to 
work out or buy guns, or pollution to prevail, as we act on our 
thinking. This is practical: our conceptions of reality, put into 
practice now, help create future reality. 

But what's controversial is the (idealist) view that our 
conceptions of reality actually affect reality without our acting 
on those conceptions. 

Barkley R. writes: >> There really is a profound mystery about the 
nature of reality that none of the contestants in this 
discussion can resolve. On the one hand, at the sub-atomic 
particle level, we have this ephemeral quantum world where 
things really are very strange and apparently even 
"subjectivized" in some deep way...<<

It's been a long (looooong) time since I studied quantum physics 
as an undergraduate in college. But if I remember correctly, the 
problem is that it's not our _perception_ that makes the quantum 
world "ephemeral," spawning the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle 
and the like.  (The H.U.P. indicates that the position and 
momentum of an electron cannot be determined simultaneously.) 
Rather, it's the _activity_ of measurement that interferes with 
our ability to measure both momentum & position. I know that 
there are other interpretations of the H.U.P., but this is the 
only one that makes sense to me. 

IMHO, this says that one can't always draw the fine line 
(posited above) between perception of an object of study and 
involvement with that object. This also applies in sociology; 
it's called the participant-observer problem. However, though 
the line can't always be drawn in practice, often it can be. (I 
can study the macroeconomy of the US without affecting it.) 
Further, the distinction makes sense as a theoretical first 
step. That step indicates that it's not the perception as much 
as the involvement that affects the nature of the object of 
study. 

In addition, one's perceptions -- even of the physical world -- 
are determined by one's societal and natural environments, one's 
social status, and one's biography and biology. But that doesn't 
mean that this environment is _same as_ one's perception. It also 
doesn't mean that one can't (once and awhile) get beyond one's 
training and come to a more complete, less ideological, vision. 
Consciuousness of the forces that encourage ideology can help 
here.

Ajit S. writes>>... On the other hand a phenomenologist 
epistimology would suggest that we extend the feeling of personal 
space to the whole enviorenment. In this case, the subject object 
dichotomy breaks down. The whole enviorenment becomes part of our 
body....<<

I didn't know that anyone was arguing that there was a 
subject/object _dichotomy_ (i.e., a hard-and-fast and permanent 
distinction, as between the Forces of Good and the Forces of Evil 
in some religions). Rather, there's a dynamic interaction, a 
dialectic, between subject and object. I transform the world as it 
transforms me.

And that dialectic might be unequal, with one part dominating the 
other. The whole environment might be seen as part of one's body, 
just as one's body is part of the environment. But the natural 
environment affects me more than I (as an individual) affect the 
environment. (If one looks instead at the dialectic between the 
natural environment and humanity as a whole, then the balance 
swings toward humanity having a big (negative) impact on the 
natural environment.) 

I don't understand the appeal of phenomenology, by the way. Isn't 
phenomenology merely descriptive? (I'm in favor of description, 
of course, but is it really enough?)

In a different note, Ajit says: >>Doug, your kind of thinking as 
been in power for a few hundered years now. And we all know what 
it has done to the world. ... <<

This is very unhelpful (please stop the ad hominem argumentation). 
Doug has already answered this, but I want to add the following 
points. 

It might be said that modernist ideology has dominated the world 
for a few hundred years (and I'm assuming that it's that ideology 
to which Ajit is referring). But it's a bourgeois modernism. Doug 
professes a _socialist_ modernism, if it is indeed a modernism. 
That kind of modernism hasn't been dominant. 

It's not just the ideology that is crucial. It's also the social 
structure -- in our case, capitalism -- and the way in which power 
is distributed and used. Frankly, I don't think it matters whether 
the dominant class is modernist, postmodernist, classicist, 
mystic, or even socialist. That dominant class will fight to the 
death to preserve its privileges. In a capitalist system, they 
will also be pushed by the coercive force of competition to seek 
profits by any means necessary. (I'll leave the dynamics of a 
bureaucratic-socialist system to another day.)

in pen-l solidarity,

Jim Devine   [EMAIL PROTECTED]
<[EMAIL PROTECTED]>
Econ. Dept., Loyola Marymount Univ.
7900 Loyola Blvd., Los Angeles, CA 90045-8410 USA
310/338-2948 (daytime, during workweek); FAX: 310/338-1950
"Segui il tuo corso, e lascia dir le genti." (Go your own way
and let people talk.) -- K. Marx, paraphrasing Dante A.



Reply via email to