on the outline of political economy list, i have been playing around 
by analogizing the "pupations" in the monetary measurement of 
commodity value to the collapse in quantum measurement:



        In short, at what point do commodities acquire value?  In A 
Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, Marx did not evade 
the difficulty:

But the different kinds of individual labour represented in these 
particular use values, in fact, becomeŠsocial labour only by being 
actually ex-changed for one anotherŠSocial labour-time exists in 
these commodities in a latent state, so to speak, and becomes evident 
only in the course of their ex-change. The point of departure is not 
the labour of individuals considered as social labour, but on the 
contrary the particular kinds of labour of private individuals, i.e., 
labour which proves that it is universal social labour only by 
supersession of its original character in the exchange process. 
Universal social labour is consequently not a ready made 
prerequisite, but an emerging result. Thus a new difficulty arises: 
on the one hand, commodities must enter the exchange process as 
materialized universal human labor, on the other hand, the labour 
time of individuals becomes materialized universal human labour time 
only as the result of the exchange process. 

In trying to understand how the propensity of a quantum system was 
drawn out in different ways according to how it was surrounded by 
measuring devices,  Werner Heisenberg was led to think of the 
system's potential as a "quantitative version of the old idea of 
'potentia' in Aristotelian philosophy. It introduced something 
standing in the middle between the idea of an event and the actual 
event, a strange kind of physical reality just in the middle between 
possibility and reality."  For Marx, value also seems to exist in 
potentia; money measurement is thus more than the passive 
ascertainment of a pre-existing property but rather the production of 
a datum (value) through the active involvement of measurer and thing 
measured. In other words, value seems to describe a system--the thing 
being measured and the measurement being made--rather than being an 
independent description of the thing being measured.

It would seem then that value is best understood not in terms of the 
now outmoded distinction between primary and secondary qualities but 
rather in terms of the contrast between possessed and latent ones. 
Until the impact of relativity theory and quantum mechanics, it was 
tenable to categorize attributes as primary and secondary (so thought 
Anaxagoras, Galileo, Descartes, Locke); the former was supposed to be 
a feature which an object possesses independent of an observer. 
Classic examples were supposed to be mass, position or size. Primary 
qualities, that is, were thought to be resident within their object; 
inalienable from it and make up  their essence. An observer simply 
measured or read a primary quality, but the quality is in no sense 
dependent upon the observer. Secondary qualities arise from the 
interaction between the object and an observer. Taste and color are 
typical of this type.
That distinction has broken down since with relativity theory: mass 
for example does vary with the relative speed of the object and 
observer. In short, if every quality is secondary, then the 
distinction between primary and secondary is simply uninformative.

As already noted, Heisenberg tried to replace the old distinction of 
primary and secondary attributes with the idea that qualities of an 
object are either essential or potential; possessed or latent. With 
the uncertainty principle latent qualities manifest themselves as 
clearly present only upon measurement; that is, position and momentum 
appear as latent qualities.

This conceptual  innovation is helpful in understanding  Marx for 
whom value is a kind of latent quality of commodities which manifests 
itself as clearly present only upon  successful monetary ex-change or 
"collapse" onto the money price "vector" (of course not everything 
which has assumed the commodity form and sold for a price possess the 
quality of value, but no commodity which has not sold for a price is 
a--or possesses--value). To extend the analogy: Monetary  measurement 
forces a collapse of commodities into one of two eigenstates: value 
or no value. That is, a commodity undergoes a change from one state 
to  another in the process of measurement.

        There are of course at least two places where the analogy breaks down:

(1) In  quantum mechanics,   measurement supplies a determinate value 
for the observable while we are not supplied  with such a determinate 
value by money measurement. That is, we cannot go from  the price at 
which a commodity sells to its value.

(2) In quantum mechanics, we have definite probabilities for the 
values measurement will
return.

However, like measurement in quantum mechanics, money measurement 
seems to invert common sense: while the commodity only possesses the 
quality of having value after that quality has been quantitatively 
measured in a successful exchange, we would find it absurd that if 
only after a quantitative measurement of a thing's quality ("it's 
eleven feet") can we say that it in fact possesses the quality ("it 
has extension").  It is as if objects do not "have" extension until 
they are forced to adopt a particular value through a measurement.

Reply via email to