I agree with Marci that the precedental force of Lukumi has taken a serious hit.  But I don't think it's quite as severe as she suggests.  For one thing, it seems clear that Lukumi would continue to prohibit religious discrimination, even absent proof of animus or hostility, where the state imposes criminal or civil sanctions (see p.6), i.e., where there is a "substantial" burden on religious exercise.  And, even in the context of benefits, the Court goes to great pains to leave open the possibility of a "presumptive" free exercise violation where the state interest is not as "historic and substantial" as the interest in avoiding the subsidization of clergy.  The sentence in the final paragraph is significant:  "The State's interest in not funding the pursuit of devotional degrees is substantial and the exclusion of such funding places a relatively minor burden on Promise Scholars."  Where the interest is less substantial, or the burden less "minor," who knows?

Nevertheless, it is hard to deny that, in the benefits context (including, e.g., cases involving primary- and secondary-school vouchers), it's now going to be awfully difficult for plaintiffs to convince lower courts to invalidate religious exclusions.  Lukumi is of weakened, and uncertain, force.  The Rosenberger trump card is virtually a dead letter outside of some narrow, fora-like contexts
 in which the purpose of the program is to encourage a diversity of private viewpoints.  McDaniel v. Paty apparently is limited to denials of the right to participate "in the political affairs of the community."  And, just as the state has an "historic" and "substantial" interest in not subsidizing the ministry, presumably it has an equally historic and substantial interest in not subsidizing prayer, or the teaching and propagation of particular religious truths, such as the religious instruction that occurs in many sectarian schools.
 
Offhand, I see only two possible lines of argument that might be fruitful. 
 
The first will apply only in very limited circumstances.  Many so-called "baby Blaine" amendments, including one in Washington, prohibit funds from ever being subject to "sectarian control or influence," without regard to what is actually being subsidized.  It's possible that some states would construe such a provision to prohibit funds from being used in institutions run by sectarian organizations, even where the funded program is wholly secular.  In such a case, the exclusion would be triggered not by the religious nature of the activity that is funded, but instead by the religious nature, or affiliation, of the recipient.  In my view, this will usually be a form of unconstitutional condition, punishing folks not for what they do (or for what the dollars subsidize), but for the religious choices and affiliations they have made.  (This is the argument Judge Fernandez made, albeit unsuccessfully, in Gentala, 244 F.3d at 1082-86.)
 
Second, perhaps the basic unconstitutional conditions argument might still have some force in the context of, e.g., school vouchers.  Assume, for instance, that a student chooses to attend a sectarian school, but the state does not permit a voucher to be used at that school because it (legitimately) does not wish to subsidize instruction as to religious truths.  The student, however, is willing to pay for the religious classes with her own funds, and to use the voucher only for the secular classes.  The state does not permit this, because money is fungible.  The student in that case could argue that the restriction not only prevents state subsidy of religious instruction, but also punishes her for attending religious classes with use of her own money.  In Davey, the Court rejected that argument because Washington permitted Davey, at least in theory, to attend two colleges and use the scholarship only at the school where he was not majoring in divinity studies.  At the primary and secondary school level, surely that is unrealistic -- no student will be able to attend two schools.  Therefore, the religious exclusion might, in such a case, "require students to choose between their religious beliefs and receiving a government benefit" (p.7).  
 
Even if this argument has some force, it seems clear that the state could require quite severe segregation as a means of ensuring that its funds do not subsidize religious classes.  In Rust, for example, the state was permitted to insist that a recipient set up a completely segregated, alternative clinic in which it could discuss abortion.  Presumably, then, a state could require, at the very least, that a sectarian school teach its religious classes only after the completion of the "secular" school day, using faculty and administrators unconnected with the secular program.  Of course, few sectarian schools would agree to such a condition, just as few if any title X recipients in Rust would have the wherewithal or desire to set up a separate abortion-speech clinic -- and just as no divinity majors in Washington are about to attend two schools in order to receive a Promise Scholarship.  But in cases where the state does not even offer this unpalatable choice, the plaintiff might have a plausible unconstitutional conditions claim.
 
 
----- Original Message -----
Sent: Thursday, February 26, 2004 2:15 PM
Subject: Re: Locke v. Davey and expanded free exercise rights

On the one hand, Alan is absolutely correct that the Court refers to expansive state constitutional rights.  On the other hand, the Court dramatically narrows the usefulness of Lukumi in attacking laws for violation of the federal Free Exercise Clause.  The argument that Lukumi's strict scrutiny applied simply because religion is mentioned, excluded, or treated differently in a law is defunct.  Lukumi's rationale was narrowed to instances where there is "animus" and "hostility" to religion.  The Court could not have said it more often. 

Marci 


In a message dated 2/26/2004 1:31:32 PM Eastern Standard Time, [EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

I was particularly pleased with footnote 8 in the majority opinion that
pointed out that Washington provides greater free exercise protection than
the federal constitution. Conceptually, this resonates with the argument
that there an important connection or equilibrium in interpreting the
religion clauses such that the rigorous enforcement of one reinforces and
justifies the rigorous enforcement of the other. Pragmatically, it supports
the rhetorical argument that a state that uses the play in the joints it is
allowed to impose more restrictions on the funding of religious
institutions and activities than the federal constitution requires ought to
provide comparably greater protection to religious institutions and
activities on the free exercise side of the constitutional equation as well.

Alan Brownstein
UC Davis



_______________________________________________
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
_______________________________________________
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Reply via email to