This is certainly a broader issue -- and its an interesting point. 

Three quick thoughts.

1. I think Perry overstates "the American legal instinct not to let
theological differences play too large a role in leading to different
legal results." See, e.g. Sunday closing laws, conscientious objector
laws limited to those who oppose all wars, grooming requirements in
institutions and for government employees etc. But he is certainly
correct that in some cases we have generalized religious accommodations
and extend benefits more broadly than necessary to achieve neutrality or
equality among faiths.

2. There has always been some significant tension between the goal of
avoiding discrimination among sects and the goal of equalizing treatment
between religious and non-religious individuals and institutions. Until
recently, during the modern period of religion clause doctrine (post
World War II), avoiding sect discrimination was considered the more
serious constitutional problem. That paradigm is changing.

3. The integration of different religious groups in American society
(which resulted in part from the constitutional commitment to religious
equality) created a kind ecumenical merging of certain sect specific
religious values with popular normative beliefs. I think, for example,
that the Catholic tradition of confidentiality between clergy and
penitent in confession has influenced American beliefs about the
importance of clergy-congregant confidentiality and those more generic
beliefs, in turn, end up being expressed through law. 

Alan Brownstein
 

-----Original Message-----
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Perry Dane
Sent: Thursday, January 12, 2006 10:28 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Drawing lines among religons

         I want to suggest a broader issue if I could, arising out of 
the Davey discussion.

         It seems to me that there is an American legal instinct not 
to let theological differences among religious traditions play too 
large a role in leading to different legal results, even if those 
different results could be justified on objective, secular, 
grounds.  Or, to put it another way, our law often bases a particular 
legal rule on a paradigm case drawn from one religious traditions, 
and then tends to extend the application of that rule to other 
faiths, even if their beliefs or practices don't, strictly speaking, 
fit the original paradigm.

         Some examples, important and less so:

         (1) The strict clergy-penitent privilege makes the most 
sense for those religious traditions that have a strong notion of a 
specific sacrament of confession, and an absolute seal of 
confidentiality surrounding that confession.  Yet it is applied to 
all faiths.  (If the paradigm case for the privilege were rabbis, for 
example, rather than Catholic priests, it would probably be less
stringent.)

         (2) If we applied the broader principles of the modern law 
of charities to the status of churches, it seems fairly clear that 
many, but not all, would qualify as genuine "public benefit" 
institutions.  Yet the assumption is that, barring outright fraud and 
the like, all churches qualify.  (Notice the difficulty that the 
opinions in Walz had in explaining why.  Notice also that English law 
is much less sentimental in this regard:  it famously holds that 
while orders of nuns that do educational or other work in the 
community can qualify as beneficiaries of a valid charitable trust, 
orders of purely contemplative nuns cannot.)

         (3) Still on the topic of the law of charities:  our 
justification for allowing a charitable deduction for "contributions" 
to churches is based on the paradigm of congregants putting money in 
the basket, and seems, technically speaking, not to fit easily into 
religions with compulsory tithes, pew rents, High Holiday tickets, 
etc.  Yet all these practices qualify for the deduction.  (Hernandez 
was an effort to draw some sort of line here, but its practical 
consequence has been nil.  Indeed, the IRS ended up settling with the 
Scientologists.)

         (4) One of my favorite small examples:  the parsonage 
provision in the tax code, whose effect is to treat all clergy as if, 
like Catholic priests, they were required to live in church-provided
rectories.


         Now, it does seem to me that this "instinct" makes a good 
deal of sense for the American dispensation governing the relation of 
religion and the state.  But it is still difficult.  In a sense, the 
choice often comes down to whether we should (a) draw lines among 
religions, or (b) treat all religions alike, but in the process draw, 
secularly-speaking weakly-justified lines between religious and 
non-religious phenomena.  Thus, for example, the effect of the 
parsonage exemption is to give many Jewish and Protestant clergy an 
arguably arbitrary tax preference compared to non-clergy.  On the 
other hand, the effect of repealing the parsonage exemption would be 
to give Catholic clergy an objectively justifiable but still 
discomforting  tax preference compared to their Jewish and Catholic 
colleagues based on the particular ecclesiology and institutional 
set-up of their respective faiths.  This is a real dilemma, and I've 
never found a totally easy way out if it.  (I happen to think that 
there's a fair amount of intractability in this religion-and-law 
business.  But maybe that's just the post-modernist in me.)

         I also think that this "instinct" I'm talking about exists 
below the constitutional surface (though that does not make it any 
less interesting).  But it does raise the usual constitutional 
questions:  When is drawing lines among religions forbidden?  (I.e., 
to what extent does Larson, etc., apply beyond the more blatant cases 
of religious discrimination and gerrymandering.)  When, if ever, is 
refusing to draw lines among religions forbidden?

                                         Perry

*******************************************************
Perry Dane
Professor of Law

Rutgers University
School of Law  -- Camden
217 North Fifth Street
Camden, NJ 08102

[EMAIL PROTECTED]
www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/

Work:   (856) 225-6004
Fax:       (856) 969-7924
Home:   (610) 896-5702
*******************************************************


_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly
or wrongly) forward the messages to others.



_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to