I'm inclined to say that this is exactly right. In fact, the Court's church property and church government cases suggest that religious arbitration is the only permissible mode for resolving those cases that require interpretation of religious doctrine. And U.S. law has certainly coexisted for decades, if not longer, with religious arbitration by Beth Dins, Christian arbitration bodies, and a smaller number of Islamic arbitration bodies. I was curious, though, about two related questions: (1) Does Jewish, Muslim, or Christian religious law, as interpreted by at least some prominent arbitral bodies, set up rules that are either substantively (e.g., men are favored over women in divorce settlements, or vice versa) or procedurally (e.g., male witnesses are treated as more credible than female witnesses, or religiously orthodox witnesses are treated as more credible than apostate witnesses) discriminatory based on sex, religion, or ethnicity? (2) Is there a generally applicable principle of arbitration law (both religious and secular) that declares arbitration awards to be against public policy if they are based on similarly discriminatory rules? It may well be that we shouldn't have such a generally applicable principle of arbitration law, because parties should be free to waive their nondiscrimination rights, at least in certain kinds of contexts. But if there such a generally applicable principle, and some religious arbitral decisions do indeed tend to involve the application of discriminatory rules, then presumably those decisions would be unenforceable unless some religious exemption is granted from the arbitration law principle. Eugene Vance Koven writes:
We've discussed this a bit on the list before, but I don't see why in principle religious courts should not be treated pretty much as commercial arbitration is: as a consensual alternative to the state legal system (with enforcement permissible through the national courts where required). In all such cases, the national legal system provides an umbrella of protections, including among other things the necessity for consent and honesty in obtaining the agreement by which the parties submit to the alternative jurisdiction. It should not be an objection in most instances that the substantive rights of the parties differ from the norms of the secular courts. There are very few rights, even constitutional ones, the exercise of which in particular circumstances cannot be waived. For example, people waive their free speech rights in private contexts all the time (think of non-disparagement clauses and even confidentiality agreements, including those attached to litigation settlement agreements); they waive statutory rights such as nondiscrimination rights and antitrust rights; and so on. Some things cannot be waived, such as one's right to be free as opposed to enslaved, but of course this is understood to be a matter of the perpetuity of the arrangement--any employment agreement restricts one's freedom of action to an extent--and the mechanism for enforcement (prohibition of contrary employment rather than specific performance). One also is restricted in waiving rights of third parties (e.g. one's children), which might create some issues under religious law. Still, the general principle ought to be that as to the consenting party an agreement to refer most matters to religious courts ought to be upheld and enforced by the secular courts. I frankly don't see what Matthew or Luke (or Mark or John, for that matter) have to say on the matters quoted below have to do with the subject. Vance
_______________________________________________ To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private. Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.