The opening brief for Conestoga Wood Specialties Corp. has been filed, and
I believe this may be the first time the Supreme Court has been presented
with an argument in a party's merits brief as to the scope of the so-called
"Sherbert-exception to Smith" -- the idea expressed in both Smith and
Lukumi that
although the Free Exercise Clause does not require religious exemptions to
be made from uniform legal obligations, religious exemptions may be
required when other exemptions to a law are available.

In an article last year, I suggested that there remain at least five major
unresolved questions about the selective-exemption rule:

1.  What is the purpose of the rule: is it designed to guard against the
danger of intentional discrimination or to address the adverse impact on
religious minorities of unintentional neglect or indifference?


2.  Does the rule only apply when a law allows for ad hoc, individualized
exemptions to an obligation (e.g., discretionary excuses under a "good
cause" or "necessary" standard), or does it also apply when the government
makes select categorical exemptions to a law?


3.  If the rule applies when categorical exemptions are made, how should
courts determine whether an existing categorical exemption to a law is
sufficiently analogous to the requested religious exemption to be deemed a
relevant comparator?


4.  How many comparable categorical exemptions must exist before the
selective-exemption rule is triggered by the denial of a religious
exemption?


5. What is the appropriate level of judicial scrutiny to be applied once
the selective-exemption rule is triggered?

Conestoga's positions on questions #2 and #5 are what you would expect. On
#2, it argues that the selective-exemption rule extends to situations
involving categorical exemptions (in this case, the ACA's exemptions for
small businesses and grandfathered plans). On #5, it argues for strict
scrutiny (which is what the Court indicated in both Smith and Lukumi
applies to individualized-exemption situations).

Conestoga's brief does not contain much argument relevant to questions #3
and #4.

As for #1, I found the most relevant passage in Conestoga's brief to be
quite surprising. Usually, advocates of a broad reading of the
selective-exemption rule make a point of contending that the rule is not
limited to situations involving the danger of discriminatory intent. Yet,
Conestoga's brief quotes a portion of the Third Circuit's decision in
Fraternal Order of Police Newark Lodge v. Newark that speaks directly to
discriminatory intent and is not usually quoted by advocates of a broad
reading of the rule:

"Providing secular exemptions 'while refusing religious exemptions is
sufficiently suggestive of discriminatory intent as to trigger heightened
scrutiny under Smith and Lukumi.'" Br. at 46 (quoting Newark Lodge at 365).


As it turns out, this is the very same passage from Newark Lodge that I
suggested in my article may narrow the universe of categorical-exemption
situations that trigger the selective-exemption rule:

"[T]the court’s application of the selective-exemption rule in Newark
Lodge also
included the key phrase, 'while refusing.' That phrase is a reminder of an
important but underappreciated fact in the case: the categorical medical
exemption was *not* part of the original no-beard policy and was only
adopted *after* the request for the religious exemptions was made. Under
those circumstances, granting the categorical medical exemption while
denying the religious exemptions would, as the court notes, seem to raise
the same risk of devaluing religion as a situation in which individualized
exemptions are available and religious exemptions are denied. It is
important to note, however, that the very reason there was a risk of
devaluing religion in Newark Lodge—that the denied religious exemption was
considered alongside other granted exemptions—is a dynamic likely to be
absent in many categorical exemption cases, where exemptions are written
into a law or policy separate from any consideration of a request for a
religious exemption. In those more typical categorical exemption cases,
there would seem to be considerably less reason to draw an inference of
discriminatory intent from the adoption of a categorical exemption." -
Lukumi at Twenty, 19 Animal Law 295, 308 (2013).

With respect to the ACA cases, the denied religious exemptions for
commercial business owners were not considered alongside the granted
secular exemptions. Rather, "the granted secular exemptions (for small
businesses with fewer than fifty employees and for grandfathered plans)
were adopted by Congress in the ACA *prior *to HHS's regulatory
consideration of religious exemptions for commercial businesses." Id. at
328 n.193. So if my reading of the selective-exemption rule is correct, the
rule would not necessarily be implicated in the ACA cases (at least by the
small business and grandfather exemptions; I'll leave to others the merits
of Conestoga's argument that HHS's granting of exemptions to some religious
entities requires exemptions to be granted to all entities with a religious
objection).

Of course, many commentators take a much broader view of the
selective-exemption rule than do I, as reflected in the brief filed by 24
constitutional law professors in Stormans v. Selecky, which is now being
held by the Ninth Circuit pending Conestoga.

That law-scholars amicus brief is available here:
 http://www.becketfund.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/02/Constitutional-Law
-Scholars-Brief.pdf.

My article on the selective-exemption rule is available here:
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2216207

Conestoga's opening brief is available here:
http://www.adfmedia.org/files/ConestogaMeritsBrief.pdf

- Jim
_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to