[peirce-l] evolving universe

2006-03-15 Thread gnusystems
This is probably old news to most of you but since i just found it, i 
thought i'd share it --

Reading some musings by physicist Lee Smolin on Edge.org, i thought "Hey, 
sounds like Peirce." And sure enough, toward the bottom he quotes Peirce.

http://www.edge.org/q2006/q06_4.html#smolin

gary

}If we can see (as we once saw very well) that our conversation with the 
planet is reciprocal and mutually creative, then we cannot help but walk 
carefully in that field of meaning. [David Suzuki]{

gnusystems }{ Pam Jackson & Gary Fuhrman }{ Manitoulin University
 }{ [EMAIL PROTECTED] }{ http://users.vianet.ca/gnox/ }{



---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber archive@mail-archive.com



[peirce-l] Re: on continuity and amazing mazes

2006-03-15 Thread Jerry LR Chandler
Thomas:Your thoughts on the potential relation between Peirce's continuity and mathematical history were fascinating.  I must confess that I am a bit of a skeptic when it comes to the possibility of a sensible relation between logic, any logic, and a philosophy of mathematics.Nonetheless, I remain puzzled by the concept of the "form" of logic, .Should logic be grounded in the logos?  That is, in the sentences of the language?What is it that would trigger the jump to forms?  Roughly speaking, the abstract conceptualization of mental motion from sentences to geometry?I note in passing that Waismann's concept of number as the root of mathematics avoids this particular issue as the concept of "number" already exists in the natural language and does not acquire a sense of geometry in ordinary usage, in ordinary day to day communication.CheersJerryOn Mar 15, 2006, at 1:08 AM, Peirce Discussion Forum digest wrote:Subject: Re: on continuity and amazing mazes From: "Thomas Riese" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> Date: Tue, 14 Mar 2006 13:39:29 +0100 X-Message-Number: 2  On Mon, 13 Mar 2006 19:37:14 +0100, Marc Lombardo <[EMAIL PROTECTED]>   wrote:  Thomas,  If you don't mind my asking, what's wrong with the "nonstandard analysis" approach to illustrating continuum, so long as that approach is VERY nonstandard? I was quite convinced by Hilary Putnam's introduction to "Reasoning and the Logic of Things." Putnam suggests that rather than understanding infinitesimals as deriving from major points, instead we understand all points as themselves infinitesimals and all   infinitesimals as points, such that any infinitesimal point names another infinity of infinitesimals.  It's difficult to express things in a few useful words, Marc, but I'll try.  I know what Hilary Putnam writes. I believe that he extremely   underestimated what a black belt master logician like Peirce can do with these seemingly simplistic, "childish" syllogistic forms.  And it is very important to understand thst Peirce's logic is primarily   focused on "forms". Another master in this way of thinking was the mathematician   Leonhard Euler and in fact Peirce perhaps received his idea for the "cut" from   Euler (in his Letters to a German Princess). John Venn later "amended" this form,   but he misunderstood it completely. Euler wasn't childish. Neither was Peirce.  Euler could work miracles in analysis, but he had no explicit logical   theory. He simply knew what he did. Later then others came, working more or less by rule of thumb and that often landed them in the ditch. They simply did not   know what they were doing. So there was a crisis in mathematics. To save   mathematical logic there had to come Cauchy and Weiertrass, Dedekind and Cantor etc.   Secure foundations were needed.  But that also closed the door to a lot of possibilities.  Peirce found the logic behind what Euler has been doing, I believe. But   now we have "Bourbakism" in mathematics, i.e. set theory as a language, which is by no   means "neutral".  Just an example: in mathematics, if you have discovered an "isomorphism"   you have made a discovery, you have "reduced" things and then you are finished with these   things. They are just simply "the same thing". The equivalence relation is so to speak   the primary mode of _expression_.  Peirce is exactly interested in the relation between isomorphous forms.   His primary relation is the general form of transitivity.  The difference has far reaching, profound implications.  So in nonstandard anylysis as soon as you base things on "point sets",   however generally understood, you have already missed the point (no pun intended) of   Peirce's continuity.  Peirce can represent it in that form (and then mathematical points split   etc), but I don't believe it's possible the other way round.  But what I here say, can be only very loose talk indeed of course. Just to   give you a vague idea what I mean.  Cheers, Thomas.  Jerry LR ChandlerResearch ProfessorKrasnow Institute for Advanced StudyGeorge Mason University 
---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber archive@mail-archive.com




[peirce-l] Re: on continuity and amazing mazes

2006-03-15 Thread Joseph Ransdell



Arnold says:
 
 I would venture to suggest (subject to the better sense of those on 
the list who have greater experince with the MSS than I have) that the notion of 
a Sign contains the concept of a transitive function, making a very strong case 
for what Thomas has said on this subject.  Other transitive functions in 
Peirce can be found in Vols III and IV of the CP (see especially 3.562)RE
 
RESPONSE:
 
You won't get any objections from 
me on that, Arnold.  Let me quote myself (from my dissertation many 
year ago (1966) on CSP's conception of representation):  "Peirce 
indicates in several places that he regards the nota notae as the generic 
inference principle (see esp. 5.320 and 3.183).  [Nota notae est nota rei 
ipsius: the mark of the mark is the mark of the thing itself.]  Further, he 
identifies this with the dictum de omni (4.77) [which is in Aristotle], and with 
what De Morgan called the principle of the transitiveness of the copula.  
(2.591-92).  The latter is in turn identified with the illative relation 
(3.175), and this, again, is explicitly said to be the "primary and paramount 
semiotic relation." (2.444n1). I suggest, therefore, that all of Peirce's 
statements of the representation relation may thus be taken as so many variant 
expressions of what he understands to be expressed by the nota notae, the dictum 
de omni, the notion of the transitivity of the copula, or the principle of 
illation." (Charles Peirce: The Idea of Representation, 
63)
 
Joe 
Ransdell
No virus found in this outgoing message.
Checked by AVG Free Edition.
Version: 7.1.375 / Virus Database: 268.2.1/278 - Release Date: 3/9/2006

---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber archive@mail-archive.com



[peirce-l] Re: on continuity and amazing mazes

2006-03-15 Thread Thomas Riese

Dear Arnold,

I believe L 224, the letter Peirce wrote to William James on 1909 Feb 26 is
exceedingly important here. In print you find it in volume III/2, p.836  
ff. of

"The New Elements of Mathematics", ed.: Carolyn Eisele.

What is important is the fact that general transitivity has a property that
would in Boolean algebra amount to the "Idempotency Law", i.e. AA=A. You  
can see
this clearly on page 838. It would be very tedious to try to cite things  
here in

an email text, so I can only indicate what is meant.

Since the idempotency expresses identity, we can see here quite clearly why
Peirce in connection with the Existential Graphs spoke of "ter-identity"  
(as in

"line of teridentity"). But this very insight in fact goes back to the 1867
paper "On the Natural Classification of Arguments" (see CP 2.461 ff) where
Peirce writes:

"There is, however, an intention in which these substitutions are  
inferential.
For, although the passage from holding for true a fact expressed in the  
form "No

A is B", to holding its converse, is not an inference, because, these facts
being identical, the relation between them is not a fact; yet the passage  
from
one of these forms taken merely as having "some" meaning, but not this or  
that

meaning, to another, since these forms are not identical and their logical
relation is a fact, is an inference. The distinction may be expressed by  
saying

that they are not inferences, but substitutions having the "form" of
inferences."(CP 2.496)

And this then lead to the "On a New List of Categories" in 1867.

I think we should address this as "diagonalization", since in L 224, after
exploring what is meant by "Logical Analysis of a Concept and a Real  
Definition
of it" (p.844) and addressing  Johann Benedict Listing's "Barycentral  
Calculus"
[Sorry, it is impossible to go through all this mathematics; but these  
things,

as e.g. the  Barycentral Calculus is not so much important here in itself,
anyway] Peirce writes (on page 854) concerning the "theory that concepts  
are
combined in a form substantially like that of the combination of points in  
the

barycentric calculus":

"I may remark, that it is in barycentral composition that forces are  
combined

according to the principle of the parallelogram of forces".

I remind you, what Peirce here still is talking about is general  
transitivity

and what he found in 1867! (you'll see that later in the text of L 224/see
below)

Next (poor William James:-)) he gives his proof of what today is known in
mathematics as the Peirce Theorem. It says that "Every linear associative
algebra is isomorphic to a matrix algebra." (compare e.g. Birkhoff/  
MacLane,
Modern Algebra, p.398; by the way interesting to compare this to the  
theorem
that "Any abstract group is isomorphic with a group of transformations" on  
page

139 of the same book;-)).

In the proof  Peirce gives of  his theorem, it is not the isomorphism that  
is

interesting. By way of proof analysis it is interesting to note how Peirce
arranges these (A:A), (A:B) etc forms, which are part of sums, in a square  
and
again compare this to Cantor's ¨€¨Diagonalverfahren¨€œ, secondly it is  
interesting

to note the distinction Peirce makes on page 858 between ���substitution��� and
¨€¨replacement¨€œ and it is interesting to note that the last formula on page  
858
somehow reminds one strongly of the form of the general transitive  
relation back
at the beginning of L 224 and in CP 3.523f. (here then the formula on top  
of the

page 332 in the CP.)

Sorry, if Peirce could do this with poor William James, then I here simply  
do

the same with poor you :-)

I could even "top" it by saying that what is important here, as in the  
Bernoulli
series, is not the concrete system of numbers or abstract algebraic  
"units", but

the relation beween multiplication and addition or "distributivity" and
"collectivity" (just to coin two new terms to be thrown away immediately  
after

use!).

By the way, Jacob Bernoulli didn't derive his "Bernoulli numbers"  
algebraically.
That probably would have been utterly hopeless. He SAW A PATTERN in the  
series
he was exploring. With his very eyes. That's historical fact and not a  
myth, as

it seems. Interesting curiosity, isn't it?

What I want to say: the conception of probability and its logical  
foundation is

not very far here.

Sorry again, I don't say this here to appear "intelligent" or something,  
or to
impress anybody with my "superior personality". I simply don't know a  
better way
to say it and perhaps it is better so to say it, instead that it is lost  
for
further use. In other words: this might be a good field for a research  
project,

Arnold;-)

Again, analysing Peirce's proof, keep categorial structure in mind!

Cheers,
Thomas.

On Wed, 15 Mar 2006 08:32:12 +0100, Arnold Shepperson  
<[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote:



Thomas

TR:  Thomas Riese
AS:  Arnold Shepperson

TR: Peirce is exactly interested in the rel