Francis A. Boyle
Law Building
504 E. Pennsylvania Ave.
Champaign, IL 61820 USA
217-333-7954 (voice)
217-244-1478 (fax)
fbo...@law.uiuc.edu
(personal comments only)
 


-----Original Message-----
From: arch...@blythe.org [mailto:arch...@blythe.org] On Behalf Of
n...@olm.blythe-systems.com
Sent: Tuesday, October 26, 2004 11:04 AM
To: n...@olm.blythe-systems.com
Subject: [NYTr] Students: Boycott Harvard Law School!


Via NY Transfer News Collective  *  All the News that Doesn't Fit
 
sent by Francis Boyle - Oct 26, 2004

[The Harvard Law School Faculty knew full well the nefarious activities that
Goldsmith had performed at the Department of Justice and the Pentagon before
they voted to hire him. Obviously, the Harvard Law School Faculty wanted a
war criminal to join their ranks. For this reason, the Harvard Law School
Faculty is not fit to educate students. I would strongly recommend that you
discourage students from attending the Harvard Law School for any reason. I
already have.

Violations of the Geneva Conventions are war crimes. Therefore, according to
Dean Kagan, the future of International Legal Studies at Harvard Law School
are in the "good hands" of a war criminal. Ditto for Yoo at Boalt.
 
"The CIA, Justice Department and the author of the draft opinion, Jack L.
Goldsmith, former director of the Office of Legal Counsel, declined to
comment for this article. "
 
Harvard Law School Dean Kagan publicly stated that the future of
International Legal Studies at Harvard Law School is in "good hands" with
Goldsmith. That is precisely why you must discourage any student from going
to HLS.]

Francis A. Boyle, 
Harvard Law School, 1976
 
 
The Washington Post - Oct 24, 2004
http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/articles/A57363-2004Oct23.html>  

Detainees Secretly Taken Out Of Iraq 

By Dana Priest 

Practice is called breach of protections.

At the request of the CIA, the Justice Department drafted a confidential
memo that authorizes the agency to transfer detainees out of Iraq for
interrogation - a practice that international legal specialists say
contravenes the Geneva Conventions. 

One intelligence official familiar with the operation said the CIA has used
the March draft memo as legal support for secretly transporting as many as a
dozen detainees out of Iraq in the last six months. The agency has concealed
the detainees from the International Red Cross and other authorities, the
official said. 

The draft opinion, written by the Justice Department's Office of Legal
Counsel and dated March 19, 2004, refers to both Iraqi citizens and
foreigners in Iraq, who the memo says are protected by the treaty. It
permits the CIA to take Iraqis out of the country to be interrogated for a
"brief but not indefinite period." It also says the CIA can permanently
remove persons deemed to be "illegal aliens" under "local immigration law." 

Some specialists in international law say the opinion amounts to a
reinterpretation of one of the most basic rights of Article 49 of the Fourth
Geneva Convention, which protects civilians during wartime and occupation,
including insurgents who were not part of Iraq's military. 

The treaty prohibits the "[i]ndividual or mass forcible transfers, as well
as deportations of protected persons from occupied territory . . .
regardless of their motive." 

The 1949 treaty notes that a violation of this particular provision
constitutes a "grave breach" of the accord, and thus a "war crime" under
U.S. federal law, according to a footnote in the Justice Department draft.
"For these reasons," the footnote reads, "we recommend that any contemplated
relocations of 'protected persons' from Iraq to facilitate interrogation be
carefully evaluated for compliance with Article 49 on a case by case basis."
It says that even persons removed from Iraq retain the treaty's protections,
which would include humane treatment and access to international monitors. 

During the war in Afghanistan, the administration ruled that al Qaeda
fighters were not considered "protected persons" under the convention. Many
of them were transferred out of the country to Guant?namo Bay and elsewhere
for interrogations. By contrast, the U.S. government deems former members of
Saddam Hussein's Baath Party and military, as well as insurgents and other
civilians in Iraq, to be protected by the Geneva Conventions. 

International law experts contacted for this article described the legal
reasoning contained in the Justice Department memo as unconventional and
disturbing. 

"The overall thrust of the Convention is to keep from moving people out of
the country and out of the protection of the Convention," said former senior
military attorney Scott Silliman, executive director of Duke University's
Center on Law, Ethics and National Security. "The memorandum seeks to create
a legal regime justifying conduct that the international community clearly
considers in violation of international law and the Convention." Silliman
reviewed the document at The Post's request. 

The CIA, Justice Department and the author of the draft opinion, Jack L.
Goldsmith, former director of the Office of Legal Counsel, declined to
comment for this article. 

CIA officials have not disclosed the identities or locations of its Iraq
detainees to congressional oversight committees, the Defense Department or
CIA investigators who are reviewing detention policy, according to two
informed U.S. government officials and a confidential e-mail on the subject
shown to The Washington Post. 

White House officials disputed the notion that Goldsmith's interpretation of
the treaty was unusual, although they did not explain why. "The Geneva
Conventions are applicable to the conflict in Iraq, and our policy is to
comply with the Geneva Conventions," White House spokesman Sean McCormick
said.

The Office of Legal Counsel also wrote the Aug. 1, 2002, memo on torture
that advised the CIA and White House that torturing al Qaeda terrorists in
captivity abroad "may be justified," and that international laws against
torture "may be unconstitutional if applied to interrogations" conducted in
the war on terrorism. Bush's aides repudiated that memo once it became
public this June. 

The Office of Legal Counsel writes legal opinions considered binding on
federal agencies and departments. Although the March 19 document obtained by
the Post is stamped "draft" and was never finalized, said one U.S. official
involved in the legal deliberations. Copies of the memo were sent to the
general counsels at the National Security Council, CIA and department of
state and defense. 

"The memo was a green light," an intelligence official said. "The CIA used
the memo to remove other people from Iraq." 

Since the Sept. 11 attacks, the CIA has used broad authority granted in a
series of legal opinions and guidance from the Office of Legal Counsel and
its own general counsel's office to transfer, interrogate and detain
individuals suspected of terrorist activities at a series of undisclosed
locations around the world. 

According to current and former agency officials, the CIA has a rendition
policy that has permitted the agency to transfer an unknown number of
suspected terrorists captured in one country into the hands of security
services in other countries whose record of human rights abuse is well
documented. These individuals, as well as those at CIA detention facilities,
have no access to any recognized legal process or rights.

The scandal at Abu Ghraib, and the investigations and congressional hearings
that followed, forced the disclosure of the Pentagon's behind-closed-doors
debate and classified rules for detentions and interrogations at Guant?namo
Bay, Cuba, and in Afghanistan and Iraq. Senior defense leaders have
repeatedly been called to explain and defend their policies before Congress.
But the CIA's policies and practices remain shrouded in secrecy. 

The only public account of CIA detainee treatment comes from soldier
testimony and Defense Department investigations of military conduct. For
instances, Army Maj. Gen. Antonio M. Taguba's report on Abu Ghraib
criticized the CIA practice of maintaining "ghost detainees" - prisoners who
were not officially registered and were moved around inside the prison to
hide them from Red Cross teams. Taguba called the practice "deceptive,
contrary to Army doctrine and in violation of international law."

Gen. Paul J. Kern, who oversaw another Army inquiry, told Congress that the
number of CIA ghost detainees "is in the dozens, to perhaps up to 100." 

The March 19, 2004, Justice Department memo by Goldsmith deals with a
previously unknown class of people - those removed from Iraq. 

It is not clear why the CIA would feel the need to remove detainees from
Iraq for interrogation. A U.S. government official who has been briefed on
the CIA's detention practices said some detainees are probably taken to
other countries because "that's where the agency has the people, expertise
and interrogation facilities, where their people and programs are in place."

The origin of the Justice Department memo related to the only publicly
acknowledged ghost detainee, Hiwa Abdul Rahman Rashul, nicknamed "Triple X"
by CIA and military officials.

Rashul, a suspected member of the Iraqi Al-Ansar terrorist group, was
captured by Kurdish soldiers in June or July of 2003 and turned over to the
CIA, which whisked him to Afghanistan for interrogation. 

In October, White House Counsel Alberto R. Gonzales asked the Office of
Legal Counsel to write an opinion on "protected persons" in Iraq and rule on
the status of Rashul, according to another U.S. government official involved
in the deliberations.

Goldsmith, then head of the office, ruled that Rashul was a "protected
person" under the Fourth Geneva Convention and therefore had to be brought
back to Iraq, several intelligence and defense officials said. 

The CIA was not happy with the decision, according to two intelligence
officials. They promptly brought Rashul back and suspended any other
transfers out of the country. 

At the same time, when transferring Rashul back to Iraq, then CIA director
George Tenet asked Defense Secretary Donald Rumsfeld not to give Rashul a
prisoner number and to hide him from International Red Cross officials,
according to an account provided by Rumsfeld during a June 17 Pentagon press
conference. Rumsfeld complied. 

As a "ghost detainee," Rashul became lost in the prison system for seven
months. 

Rumsfeld did not fully explain the reason he had complied with Tenet's
request or under what legal authority he could have kept Rashul hidden for
so long. "We know from our knowledge that [Tenet] has the authority to do
this," he said. 

Rashul, defense and intelligence officials noted, had not once been
interrogated since he was brought back into Iraq. His current status is
unknown. 

In the one-page October 2003 interim ruling that directed Rashul's return,
Goldsmith also created a new category of persons in Iraq whom he said did
not qualify for protection under the Geneva Conventions. They are non-Iraqis
who are not members of the former Baath Party and who came to Iraq after the
invasion. 

After Goldsmith's ruling, the CIA and Gonzales asked the Office of Legal
Counsel for a more complete legal opinion on "protected persons" in Iraq and
on the legality of transferring people out of Iraq for interrogation. "That
case started the CIA yammering to Justice to get a better memo," said one
intelligence officer familiar with the interagency discussion. 

Michael Byers, a professor and international law expert at University of
British Columbia, said that creating a legal justification for removing
protected persons from Iraq "is extraordinarily disturbing." 

"What they are doing is interpreting an exception into an all-encompassing
right, in one of the most fundamental treaties in history," Byers said. The
Geneva Convention "is as close as you get to protecting human rights in
times of chaos. There's no ambiguity here." 

Copyright (c) 2004 The Washington Post
       
                                *
Search the NYTr Archives at: http://olm.blythe-systems.com/pipermail/nytr/

To subscribe or unsubscribe or change your settings via the web, visit:
http://olm.blythe-systems.com/mailman/listinfo/nytr

=================================================================
  NY Transfer News Collective   *   A Service of Blythe Systems
           Since 1985 - Information for the Rest of Us
              339 Lafayette St., New York, NY 10012
  http://www.blythe.org                  e-mail: n...@blythe.org
================================================================= 
From j_som...@gmx.net  Tue Oct 26 19:04:17 2004
From: j_som...@gmx.net (Joerg Sommer)
Date: Tue Aug 16 12:14:48 2005
Subject: [Deathpenalty]death penalty news --- USA
Message-ID: <6.1.2.0.2.20041026180100.02354...@mail.stusta.mhn.de>

death penalty news

October 26, 2004


USA:

Can the Sciences Help Us to Make Wise Ethical Judgments?

Scientific knowledge has a vital, if limited, role to play in shaping our 
moral values and helping us to frame wiser judgments. Ethical values are 
natural and open to examination in the light of evidence and reason.


I.
Can science and reason be used to develop ethical judgments? Many theists 
claim that without religious foundations, "anything goes," and social chaos 
will ensue. Scientific naturalists believe that secular societies already 
have developed responsible ethical norms and that science and reason have 
helped us to solve moral dilemmas. How and in what sense this occurs are 
vital issues that need to be discussed in contemporary society, for this 
may very well be the hottest issue of the twenty-first century.

Dramatic breakthroughs on the frontiers of science provide new powers to 
humans, but they also pose perplexing moral quandaries. Should we use or 
limit these scientific discoveries, such as the cloning of humans? Much of 
this research is banned in the United States and restricted in Canada. 
Should scientists be permitted to reproduce humans by cloning (as we now do 
with animals), or is this too dangerous? Should we be allowed to make 
"designer babies?" Many theologians and politicians are horrified by this; 
many scientists and philosophers believe that it is not only inevitable but 
justifiable under certain conditions. There were loud cries against in 
vitro fertilization, or artificial insemination, only two generations ago, 
but the procedure proved to be a great boon to childless couples. Many 
religious conservatives are opposed to therapeutic stem-cell research on 
fetal tissues, because they think that "ensoulment" occurs with the first 
division of cells. Scientists are appalled by this censorship of scientific 
research, since the research has the potential to cure many illnesses; they 
believe those who oppose it have ignored the welfare of countless numbers 
of human beings. There are other equally controversial issues on the 
frontiers of science: Organ transplants-who should get them and why? Is the 
use of animal organs to supply parts for human bodies wrong? Is 
transhumanism reforming what it means to be human? How shall we control 
AIDS-is it wicked to use condoms, as some religious conservatives think, or 
should this be a high priority in Africa and elsewhere? Does global warming 
mean we need a radical transformation of industry in affluent countries? Is 
homosexuality genetic, and if so, is the denial of same-sex marriage 
morally wrong? How can we decide such questions? What criteria may we draw 
upon?


II.
Many adhere today to the view that ethical choices are merely relativistic 
and subjective, expressing tastes; and you cannot disputes tastes (de 
gustibus non disputandum est). If they are emotive at root, no set of 
values is better than any other. If there is a conflict, then the best 
option is to persuade others to accept our moral attitudes, to convert them 
to our moral feelings, or, if this fails, to resort to force.

Classical skeptics denied the validity of all knowledge, including ethical 
knowledge. The logical positivists earlier in the twentieth century made a 
distinction between fact, the appropriate realm of science, and value, the 
realm of expressive discourse and imperatives, claiming that though we can 
resolve descriptive and theoretical questions by using the methods of 
science, we cannot use science to adjudicate moral disputes. Most recently, 
postmodernists, following the German philosopher Heidegger and his French 
followers, have gone further in their skepticism, denying that there is any 
special validity to humanistic ethics or indeed to science itself. They say 
that science is merely one mythological construct among others. They insist 
that there are no objective epistemological standards; that gender, race, 
class, or cultural biases likewise infect our ethical programs and any 
narratives of social emancipation that we may propose. Who is to say that 
one normative viewpoint is any better than any other, they demand. Thus 
have many disciples of multicultural relativism and subjectivism often 
given up in despair, becoming nihilists or cynics. Interestingly, most of 
these well-intentioned folk hold passionate moral and political 
convictions, but when pushed to the wall, will they concede that their own 
epistemological and moral recommendations likewise express only their own 
personal preferences?

The problem with this position is apparent, for it is impaled on one horn 
of a dilemma, and the consequence of this option is difficult to accept. If 
it is the case that there are no ethical standards, then who can say that 
the Nazi Holocaust and the Rwandan, Cambodian, or Armenian genocides are 
evil? Is it only a question of taste that divides sadists and masochists on 
one side from all the rest on the other? Are slavery, the repression of 
women, the degradation of the environment by profit-hungry corporations, or 
the killing of handicapped people morally impermissible, if there are no 
reliable normative standards? If we accept cultural relativity as our 
guide, then we have no grounds to object to Muslim law (sharia), which 
condones the stoning to death of adulteresses.


III.
What is the position of those who wish to draw upon science and reason to 
formulate ethical judgment? Is it possible to bridge the gap and recognize 
that values are relative to human interests yet allow that they are open to 
some objective criticisms? I submit that it is, and that upon reflection, 
most educated people would accept them. I choose to call this third 
position "objective relativism" or "objective contextualism"; namely, 
values are related to human interests, needs, desires, and passions-whether 
individual or socio-cultural-but they are nonetheless open to scientific 
evaluation. By this, I mean a form of reflective intelligence that applies 
to questions of principles and values and that is open to modification of 
them in the light of criticism. In other words, there is a Tree of 
Knowledge of Good and Evil, which bears fruit, and which, if eaten and 
digested, can impart to us moral knowledge and wisdom.

In what sense can scientific inquiry help us to make moral choices? My 
answer to that is it does so all the time. This is especially the case with 
the applied sciences: medicine, dentistry, nursing, pharmacology, 
psychiatry, and social psychology; and also in the policy sciences: 
economics, education, political science; and such interdisciplinary fields 
as criminology, gerontology, etc. Modern society could not function without 
the advice drawn from these fields of knowledge, which make evaluative 
judgments and recommend prescriptions. They advise what we ought to do on a 
contextual basis.

Nonetheless, there are the skeptical critics of this position, who deny 
that science per se can help us or that naturalistic ethics is possible. I 
think that those critics are likewise mistaken and that naturalism is 
directly relevant to ethics. My thesis is that an increase in knowledge can 
help us to make wiser decisions. By knowledge, I do not refer simply to 
philosophical analysis but scientific evidence. It would answer both the 
religionist, who insists that you cannot be moral unless you are religious, 
and the subjectivist, who denies there is any such thing as ethical 
knowledge or wisdom.

Before I outline this position, let me concede that the skeptical 
philosophical objections to deriving ethics from science have some merit. 
Basically, what are they? The critics assert that we cannot deduce ethics 
from science, i.e., what ought to be the case from what is the case. A 
whole series of philosophers from David Hume to the emotivists have pointed 
out this fallacy. G.E. Moore, at the beginning of the twentieth century, 
characterized this as "the naturalistic fallacy" [1] (mistakenly, I think).

But they are essentially correct. The fact that science discovers that 
something is the case factually does not make it ipso facto good or right. 
To illustrate: (a) Charles Darwin noted the role of natural selection and 
the struggle for survival as key ingredients in the evolution of species. 
Should we conclude, therefore, as Herbert Spencer did, that laissez-faire 
doctrines ought to apply, that we ought to allow nature to take its course 
and not help the handicapped or the poorer classes? (b) Eugenicists 
concluded earlier in the century that some people are brighter and more 
talented than others. Does this justify an elitist hierarchical society in 
which only the best rule or eugenic methods of reproduction be followed? 
This was widely held by many liberals until the fascists began applying it 
in Germany with dire consequences.

There have been abundant illustrations of pseudoscientific 
theories-monocausal theories of human behavior that were hailed as 
"scientific"-that have been applied with disastrous results. Examples: (a) 
The racial theories of Chamberlain and Gobineau alleging Aryan superiority 
led to genocide by the Nazis. (b) Many racists today point to IQ to justify 
a menial role for blacks in society and their opposition to affirmative 
action. (c) The dialectical interpretation of history was taken as 
"scientific" by Marxists and used to justify class warfare. (d) 
Environmentalists decried genetics as "racist" and thought that changes in 
species should only be induced by modifications of the environment. Thus, 
one has to be cautious about applying the latest scientific fad to social 
policy.

We ought not to consider scientific specialists to be especially gifted or 
possessed with ethical knowledge nor empower them to apply this knowledge 
to society-as B.F. Skinner in Walden II and other utopianists have 
attempted to do. Neither scientist-kings nor philosopher-kings should be 
entrusted to design a better world. We have learned the risks and dangers 
of abandoning democracy to those wishing to create a Brave New World. Alas, 
all humans-including scientists-are fallible, and excessive power may 
corrupt human judgment. Given these caveats, I nevertheless hold that 
scientific knowledge has a vital, if limited, role to play in shaping our 
moral values and helping us to frame wiser judgments of practice--surely 
more, I would add, than our current reliance on theologians, politicians, 
military pundits, corporate CEOs, and celebrities!


IV.
How and in what sense can scientific inquiry help us?

I wish to present a modified form of naturalistic ethics. By this, I mean 
that ethical values are natural; they grow out of and fulfill human 
purposes, interests, desires, and needs. They are forms of preferential 
behavior evinced in human life. "Good," "bad," "right," and "wrong" relate 
to sentient beings, whether human or otherwise. These values do not reside 
in a far-off heaven, nor are they deeply embedded in the hidden recesses of 
reality; they are empirical phenomena.

The principle of naturalism is based on a key methodological criterion: We 
ought to consider our moral principles and values, like other beliefs, open 
to examination in the light of evidence and reason and hence amenable to 
modification.

We are all born into a sociocultural context; and we imbibe the values 
passed on to us, inculcated by our peers, parents, teachers, leaders, and 
colleagues in the community.

I submit that ethical values should be amenable to inquiry. We need to ask, 
are they reliable? How do they stack up comparatively? Have they been 
tested in practice? Are they consistent? Many people seek to protect them 
as inviolable truths, immune to inquiry. This is particularly true of 
transcendental values based on religious faith and supported by custom and 
tradition. In this sense, ethical inquiry is similar to other forms of 
scientific inquiry. We should not presuppose that what we have inherited is 
true and beyond question. But where do we begin our inquiry? My response 
is, in the midst of life itself, focused on the practical problems, the 
concrete dilemmas, and contextual quandaries that we confront.

Let me illustrate by refer to three dilemmas. I do so not in order to solve 
them but to point out a method of inquiry in ethics. First, should we exact 
the death penalty for people convicted of murder? The United States is the 
only major democracy that still demands capital punishment. What is the 
argument for the death penalty? It rests on two basic premises: (a) A 
factual question is at issue: capital punishment is effective in deterring 
crime, especially murder; and (b) the principle of justice that applies is 
retributive. As the Old Testament adage reads, "Whatever hurt is done, you 
shall give life for life, eye for eye, tooth for tooth. . . ." [2]

The first factual premise can be resolved by sociological studies, by 
comparing the incidence of murder in those states and nations that have the 
death penalty in force and those that do not and by states and nations 
before and after the enactment or abrogation of the death penalty. We ask, 
has there been an increase or a decrease in murder? If, as a matter of 
fact, the death penalty does not restrain or inhibit murder, would a person 
still hold his view that the death penalty ought to be retained? The 
evidence suggests that the death penalty does not to any significant extent 
reduce the murder rate, especially since most acts of murder are not 
deliberate but due to passion or are an unexpected result of another crime, 
such as robbery. Thus, if one bases his or her belief in capital punishment 
primarily on the deterrence factor, and it does not deter, would one change 
one's belief? The same consideration should apply to those who are opposed 
to the death penalty: Would they change their belief if they thought it 
would deter excessive murder rates? These are empirical questions at issue. 
And the test of a policy are its consequences in the real world. Does it 
achieve what it sets out to do?

There are, of course, other factual considerations, such as: Are many 
innocent people convicted of crimes they did not commit (as was recently 
concluded in the State of Illinois)? Is capital punishment unfairly applied 
primarily to minorities? This points to the fact that belief in capital 
punishment is, to some extent, a function of scientific knowledge 
concerning the facts of the case. This often means that such measures 
should not be left to politicians or jurors alone to decide; the scientific 
facts of the case are directly relevant.

The second moral principle of retributive justice is far more difficult to 
deal with, for this may be rooted in religious conviction or in a 
deep-seated tribal sense of retaliation. If you injure my kin, it is said, 
I can injure yours; and this is not purely a factual issue. There are other 
principles of justice that are immediately thrown into consideration. Those 
opposed to the death penalty say that society "should set a humane tone and 
not itself resort to killing." Or again, the purpose of justice should be 
to protect the community from future crimes, and alternative forms of 
punishment, perhaps lifetime imprisonment without the right of parole, 
might suffice to deter crime. Still another principle of justice is 
relevant: Should we attempt, where possible, to rehabilitate the offender? 
All of the above principles are open to debate. The point is, we should not 
block inquiry; we should not say that some moral principles are beyond any 
kind of re-evaluation or modification. Here, a process of deliberation 
enters in, and a kind of moral knowledge emerges about what is 
comparatively the best policy to adopt.

Another example of the methods of resolving moral disputes is the argument 
for assisted suicide in terminal cases, in which people are suffering 
intolerable pain. This has become a central issue in the field of medical 
ethics, where medical science is able to keep people alive who might 
normally die. I first saw the emergence of this field thirty years ago, 
when I sponsored a conference in biomedical ethics at my university and 
could find very few, if any, scholars or scientists who had thought about 
the questions or were qualified experts. Today, it is an essential area in 
medicine. The doctor is no longer taken as a patriarchal figure. His or her 
judgments need to be critically examined, and others within the community, 
especially patients, need to be consulted. There are here, of course, many 
factual questions at issue: Is the illness genuinely terminal? Is there 
great suffering? Is the patient competent in expressing his or her 
long-standing convictions regarding his or her right to die with dignity? 
Are there medical and legal safeguards to protect this system against abuse?

Our decision depends on several further ethical principles: (a) the 
informed consent of patients in deciding whether they wish treatment to 
continue; (b) the right of privacy, including the right of individuals to 
have control of their own bodies and health; and (c) the criterion of the 
quality of life.

One problem we encounter in this area is the role, again, of transcendental 
principles. Some people insist, "God alone should decide life-and-death 
questions, not humans." This principle, when invoked, is beyond 
examination, and for many people it is final. Passive euthanasia means that 
we will not use extraordinary methods to keep a person alive, where there 
is a longstanding intent expressed in a living will not to do so. Active 
euthanasia will, under certain conditions, allow the patient, in 
consultation with his physician, to hasten the dying process (as practiced 
in Oregon and the Netherlands). The point is, there is an interweaving of 
factual considerations with ethical principles, and these may be modified 
in the light of inquiry, by comparing alternatives and examining 
consequences in each concrete case.

I wish to illustrate this process again by referring to another issue that 
is hotly debated today: Should all cloning research be banned? The Canadian 
legislature, in March 2004, passed legislation that will put severe 
restrictions on such scientific research. The bill is called "An Act 
Respecting Assisted Human Reproduction" (known as C-56), and it makes it a 
criminal offense to engage in therapeutic cloning, to maintain an embryo 
outside a woman's body for more than fourteen days, to genetically 
manipulate embryos, to choose the gender of offspring, to sell human eggs 
and sperm, or to engage in commercial surrogacy. It also requires that in 
vitro embryos be created only for the purpose of creating human beings or 
for improving assisted human-reproductive procedures. Similar legislation 
was passed by the U.S. House of Representatives and is before the Senate. 
It is still being heatedly debated. It includes the prohibition of 
reproductive cloning as well as therapeutic stem-cell research. Two 
arguments against reproductive cloning are as follows: (a) It may be unsafe 
(at the present stage of medical technology) and infants born may be 
defective. This factual objection has some merit. (b) There is also a moral 
objection saying that we should not seek to design children. Yet we do so 
all the time, with artificial insemination, in vitro fertilization, and 
surrogate motherhood. We already are involved in "designer-baby" 
technology, with amniocentesis, pre-implantation, genetic testing, and 
chorionic villus sampling (the avoiding of unwanted genes by aborting 
fetuses and implanting desirable embryos).

If it were to become safe, would reproductive cloning become permissible? I 
can think of situations where we might find it acceptable-for example, if 
couples are unable to conceive by normal methods.

It is the second area I mentioned above that is especially telling-the 
opposition to any forms of embryonic stem-cell research. Proponents 
maintain that this line of research may lead to enormous benefits by curing 
a wide range of diseases such as Parkinson's disease, Alzheimer's, or 
juvenile diabetes. Adult stem cells are now being used, but embryonic stem 
cells may provide important new materials. The criterion here is 
consequential: that positive outcomes may result. Opponents maintain that 
this type of research is "immoral" because it is tampering with human 
persons possessed of souls. Under this interpretation, "ensoulment" occurs 
at the moment of conception. This is said to apply to embryos, many of 
which, however, are products of miscarriages or abortions. Does it also 
apply once the division of stem cells occurs? Surely a small collection of 
cells, which is called a blastocyst, is not a person, a sentient being, or 
a moral agent prior to implantation. Leon Kass, chair of President Bush's 
Council on Bioethics, believes that human life cannot be treated as a 
commodity and it is evil to manufacture life. He maintains that all human 
life, including a cloned embryo, has the same moral status and dignity as a 
person from the moment of conception.

This controversy pits two opposing moral claims: (a) the view that 
stem-cell research may be beneficent because of its possible contributions 
to human health (i.e., it might eliminate debilitating diseases) versus (b) 
an ethic of revulsion against tampering with natural reproductive 
processes. At issue here are the questions of whether ensoulment makes any 
sense in biology and whether personhood can be said to have begun at such 
an early stage, basically a transcendental claim that naturalists object to 
on empirical grounds. These arguments are familiar in the abortion debate; 
it would be unfortunate if they could be used to censor scientific 
stem-cell research.

This issue is especially relevant today, for transhumanists say that we are 
discovering new powers every day that modify human nature, enhance human 
capacities, and extend life spans. We may be able to extend memory and 
increase human perception and intelligence dramatically by silicon 
implants. Traditionalists recoil in horror, saying that post-humanists 
would have us transgress human nature. We would become cyborgs.

But we already are, to some extent: we wear false teeth, eyeglasses, and 
hearing aids; we have hair grafts, pacemakers, organ transplants, 
artificial limbs, and sex-change/sexual reassignment operations and 
injections; we use Viagra to enhance sexual potency or mega-vitamins and 
hormone therapy. Why not go further? Each advance raises ethical issues: Do 
we have the reproductive freedom and responsibility to design our children 
by knowing possible genetic disorders and correcting them before 
reproduction or birth?


V.
This leads to an important distinction between two kinds of values within 
human experience. Let me suggest two possible sources: (a) values rooted in 
unexamined feelings, faith, custom, or authority, held as deep-seated 
convictions beyond question, and (b) values that are influenced by 
cognition and informed by rational inquiry.

Naturalists say that scientific inquiry enables us to revise our values, if 
need be, and to develop, where appropriate, new ones. We already possess a 
body of prescriptive judgments that have been tested in practice in the 
applied sciences of medicine, psychiatry, engineering, educational 
counseling, and other fields. Similarly, I submit that there is a body of 
prescriptive ethical judgments that has been tested in practice and that 
constitutes normative knowledge; and new normative prescriptions are 
introduced all the time as the sciences progress.

The question is thus raised, what criteria should we use to make ethical 
choices? This issue is especially pertinent today for those living in 
pluralistic societies such as ours, where there is diversity of values and 
principles.

In formulating ethical judgments, we need to refer to what I have called a 
"valuational base." [3] Packed into this referent are the pre-existing de 
facto values and principles that we are committed to; but we also need to 
consider empirical data, means-ends relationships, causal knowledge, and 
the consequences of various courses of action. It is inquiry that is the 
instrument by which we decide what we ought to do and that we should 
develop in the young. We need to focus on moral education for children; we 
wish to structure positive traits of character and also the capacity for 
making reflective decisions. There are no easy recipes or simple formulae 
that we can appeal to, telling us what we ought to do in every case. There 
are, however, what W.D. Ross called prima facie general principles of right 
conduct, the common moral decencies, a list of virtues, precepts, and 
prescriptions, ethical excellences, obligations, and responsibilities, 
which are intrinsic to our social roles. But how they work out in practice 
depends on the context at hand, and the most reliable guide for mature 
persons is cognitive inquiry and deliberation.

Conservative theists have often objected to this approach to morality as 
dangerous, given to "debauchery" and "immorality." Here, there is a 
contrast between two different senses of morality: (a) the 
obedience/authoritarian model, in which humans are expected to follow moral 
absolutes derived from ancient creeds, and (b) the encouragement of moral 
growth, implying that there are within the human species potential moral 
tendencies and cognitive capacities that can help us to frame judgments.

For a naturalistic approach, in the last analysis, ethics is a product of a 
long evolutionary process. Evolutionary psychology has pointed out that 
moral rules have enabled human communities to adapt to threats to their 
survival. This Darwinian interpretation implies a biological basis for 
reciprocal behavior- epigenetic rules-according to E.O. Wilson (1998). [4] 
The social groups that possessed these rules transmitted them to their 
offspring. Such moral behavior provides a selective advantage. There is 
accordingly an inward propensity for moral behavior, moral sentiments, 
empathy, and altruism within the species.

This does not deny that there are at the same time impulses for selfish and 
aggressive tendencies. It is a mistake, however, to read in a doctrine of 
"original sin" and to say that human beings are by nature sinful and 
corrupt. I grant that there are individuals who lack moral empathy; they 
are morally handicapped. Some may even be sociopaths. The salient point is 
that there are genetic potentialities for good and evil; but how they work 
out and whether beneficent behavior prevails is dependent on cultural 
conditions. Both our genes (genetics) and memes (social patterns of 
enculturation) are factors that determine how and why we behave the way we 
do. We cannot simply deduce from the evolutionary process what we ought to 
do. What we do depends in part upon the choices we make. Thus, we still 
have some capacity for free choice. Though we are conditioned by 
environmental and biogenetic determinants, we are still capable of 
cognitive processes of selection, and rationality and intentionality play a 
causative role. (Note: There is a considerable scientific literature that 
supports this evolutionary view. See Daniel Dennett, Freedom Evolves [New 
York: Viking, 2003] and Darwin's Dangerous Idea [New York: Simon and 
Schuster, 1995]; Brian Skyrm, Evolution of the Social Contract [Cambridge: 
Cambridge University Press, 1996], Robert Wright, The Moral Animal [New 
York: Pantheon Books, 1994] and Nonzero [New York: Vintage Books, 2001], 
Matt Ridley, The Origins of Virtue [New York: Viking, 1996], and Elliott 
Sober and David Sloan Wilson, Unto Others [Cambridge, Massachusetts: 
Harvard University Press, 1998].)

Ethical precepts need not be based upon transcendental grounds or dependent 
upon religious faith. Undoubtedly, the belief that they are sacred may 
strengthen moral duties for many persons, but it is not necessary for 
everyone.

I submit that it is time for scientists to recognize that they have an 
opportunity to contribute to naturalistic ethics. We stand at an 
interesting time in human history. We have great power to ameliorate the 
human condition. Biogenetic engineering, nanotechnology, and space research 
open new opportunities for humankind to create a better world.

Yet there are those today who wish to abandon human reason and freedom and 
return to mythological legends of our premodern existence, including their 
impulses of aggres- sion and self-righteous vengeance. I submit that the 
Enlightenment is a beacon whose promise has not been fulfilled and that 
humankind needs to accept the responsibility for its own future.


Conclusion
A caveat is in order. In the last analysis, some degree of skepticism is a 
necessary antidote to all forms of moral dogmatism. We are continually 
surrounded by self-righteous moralists who claim that they have the 
Absolute Truth, Moral Virtue, or Piety or know the secret path to salvation 
and wish to impose their convictions on all others. They are puffed up with 
an inflated sense of their own rectitude as they rail against unbenighted 
immoral sinners who lack their moral faith. These moral zealots are willing 
to repress or even sacrifice anyone who stands in their way. They have in 
the past unleashed conquering armies in the name of God, the Dialectic, 
Racial Superiority, Posterity, or Imperial Design. Skepticism needs to be 
applied not only to religious and paranormal fantasies but to other forms 
of moral and political illusions. These dogmas become especially dangerous 
when they are appealed to in order to legislate morality and are used by 
powerful social institutions, such as a state or church or corporation, to 
enforce a particular brand of moral virtue. Hell hath no fury like the 
self-righteous moral fanatic scorned.

The best antidote for this is some skepticism and a willingness to engage 
in ethical inquiry, not only about others' moral zeal, but about our own, 
especially if we are tempted to translate the results of our own ethical 
inquiries into commandments. The epistemological theory that I propose is 
based upon methodological principles of skeptical scientific inquiry, and 
it has important moral implications. For in recognizing our own 
fallibility, we thereby can learn to tolerate other human beings and to 
appreciate their diversity and the plurality of lifestyles. If we are 
prepared to engage in cooperative ethical inquiry, then perhaps we are 
better prepared to allow other individuals and groups some measure of 
liberty to pursue their own preferred lifestyles. If we are able to live 
and let live, then this can best be achieved in a free and open democratic 
society. Where we differ, we should try to negotiate our divergent views 
and perhaps reach common ground; and if this is impractical, we should at 
least attempt to compromise for the sake of our common interests. The 
method of ethical inquiry requires some intelligent and informed 
examination of our own values as well as the values of others. Here we can 
attempt to modify attitudes by an appeal to cognitive beliefs and to 
reconstruct them by an examination of the relevant scientific evidence. 
Such a give-and-take of constructive criticism is essential for a 
harmonious society. In learning to appreciate different conceptions of the 
good life, we are able to expand our own dimensions of moral awareness; and 
this is more apt to lead to a peaceful world.

By this, I surely do not mean to imply that anything and everything can or 
should be tolerated or that one thing is as good as the next. We should be 
prepared to criticize moral nonsense parading as virtue. We should not 
tolerate the intolerable. We have a right to strongly object, if need be, 
to those values or practices that we think are based on miscalculation, 
misconception, or that are patently false or harmful. Nonetheless, we might 
live in a better world if inquiry were to replace faith; deliberation, 
passionate commitment; and education and persuasion, force and war. We 
should be aware of the powers of intelligent behavior, but also of the 
limitations of the human animal and of the need to mitigate the cold, 
indifferent intellect with the compassionate and empathic heart. Thus, I 
conclude that within the ethical life, we are capable of developing a body 
of melioristic principles and values and a method of coping with problems 
intelligently. When our ethical judgments are based on rational and 
scientific inquiry, they are more apt to express the highest reaches of 
excellence and nobility and of civilized human conduct. We are in sore need 
of that today.

---

Notes

1. G.E. Moore. Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903).

2. See Exodus 21.

3. Kurtz, Paul (ed.). The New Skepticism: Inquiry and Reliable Knowledge 
(Amherst, New York: Prometheus, 1992), chapter 9.

4. Wilson, E.O. Consilience (New York: Alfred Knopf, 1998).

About the Author
Paul Kurtz is a professor emeritus at the State University of New York at 
Buffalo, and chairman of the Center for Inquiry - Transnational. This 
article is a portion of the keynote address delivered at the conference on 
"Science and Ethics" sponsored by the Center for Inquiry in Toronto, 
Ontario, on May 13, 2004.

(source: Skeptical Inquirer)

Reply via email to