Re: Definition of Relationship Between Variables (was Re: Eight

2002-02-03 Thread Robert Frick

What Don's post lacks in speed in certainly makes up in thoroughness. 
This posts concerns Jan De Leeuw's definition, in which two variables
were not independent if the expected variance changed.  Maybe a good
example is IQ scores, in which the expected mean does not vary with
gender, but the standard deviation does.  Does IQ depend on gender?

Don, if I understand him correctly, is saying that we can define
independence any way we want.  While technically correct, I think it odd
(after reading Jan's post) to define independence completely on the
average.  Why not variance, or why not median, or even mode?  In light
of Jan's comment, I think my intuitive understanding of the phrase
Variable A is independent of Variable B is that the probability
distribution of A does not change with the value of B.

If one wanted to talk about the expected average of A being independent
of B, one could say that directly.  So, I conclude that the average IQ
is independent of gender, but IQ is not.

Bob


=
Instructions for joining and leaving this list, remarks about the
problem of INAPPROPRIATE MESSAGES, and archives are available at
  http://jse.stat.ncsu.edu/
=



Re: Definition of Relationship Between Variables (was Re: Eight

2002-02-03 Thread Robert Frick

Or maybe I didn't understand Don's response to Jan.  Pressing ever
onward, though


I had suggested using 

 DEFINITION: There is a *relationship* between the vari-
 ables x and y if for at least one pair of values x'
 and x of x

  E(y|x') ~= E(y|x).  


as opposed to Don's


   DEFINITION: There is a *relationship* between the vari-
   ables x and y if for at least one value x' of x

E(y|x') ~= E(y) 

  We agree that the two are mathematically equivalent.  But I think
mines better, psychologically.  I think in terms of my definition and I
actually had to translate Don's definition to mine in order to
understand why his definition was true.

Don suggests that mine works well for the case when variable X can take
only two values.  But that is not how I meant it, nor how I stated it. 
My definition captures the continuous case too.

Now let's talk examples.  Don offers the following:

   For example, after several visits to a new bank a
   person may observe, The earlier in the morning I go to the 
   bank, the less time I have to wait to be served.  (Duration
   of waiting time is the response variable and bank arrival
   time is the predictor variable.)

Don concludes that his definition better suits this example.  But I
disagree.  Or I just think of things differently.  The key is this. 
When the person concludes that they have to wait less time in the
morning, what are they comparing that to?
.
.
.
.
.
.
Your supposed to be answering this question
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.



If they are comparing that to when they go at a time other than the
morning, the example follows my definition.  x' versus x'' -- morning
versus not morning -- 10:00 versus 2:00.  To fit Don's definition, they
would have to be comparing that to the average time they wait, overall,
including morning.

Now, to me, it makes more sense to compare morning to not-morning; the
comparison from morning to overall is not how I think.

Or maybe I didn't understand this either.  It's just my thought.  But I
think this is an important topic -- how basic ideas of statistics are
defined, and how to define them in terms of how people think.  I like
Don's work a lot, because he addresses these issues, has useful things
to say, and makes me think.

Bob Frick


=
Instructions for joining and leaving this list, remarks about the
problem of INAPPROPRIATE MESSAGES, and archives are available at
  http://jse.stat.ncsu.edu/
=




Re: teaching statistical methods by rules?

1999-12-22 Thread Robert Frick

Alan McLean wrote, among other things:

 On the other hand, a body of knowledge can be thought of as a set of
 'rules'.

I think you are concentrating on the information in what is learned and
ignoring the format.  This works for computers, which learn in only one
format (memory), but not for people, for which memory is just one
format.  My argument:
For the sake of example, suppose I want to teach students how to tie
their shoes.  I could observe what I do and create a verbal
description.  I could teach students this verbal description, and they
could memorize it.  I could test them on their ability to remember this
information.  A student who could remember it probably could tie their
shoes.
My students might end up knowledge roughly the same information as me,
but their knowledge wouldn’t be stored in their brains the same way it
is stored in mine.  I have a connected series of motor movements built
into my brain as a habit.  And these different storage formats have
different implications.  My students would be good at verbal
descriptions, but probably not so fast at actually tying their shoes.
Now to reality.  Research on implicit learning has suggested that
people can learn something without being able to report what they have
learned.  Presumably, they have no conscious knowledge of what they have
learned.  In my published opinion, there are three types of implicit
knowledge, with habits being just one.  Combined with conscious
knowledge, that makes four different types of learning.
The format in which something is learned has implications.  One is for
memory.  Research suggests that implicit learning is retained much
longer than explicit learning.  Another is for usage.  Obviously, for
verbal report, conscious knowledge is far superior than any other type
of knowledge.  But the other types of learning probably are probably
better for other types of performance.  For example, in one study, we
either gave subjects implicit knowledge of a rule or explicitly taught
them a collection of rules.  The subjects with implicit knowledge could
use the information in an identification task better than they could
report it.  The subjects with conscious knowledge could report the rules
better than they could use them.
The hardest type of learning to describe or define is what I call
mental models, and what often corresponds to what people call
understanding.  For example, you have a mental model of your spouse (or
friend).  You can use this mental model to predict what your spouse or
friend will do.  You can also try to use this mental model to verbally
describe your spouse or friend, but that isn't a natural use of the
mental model and that format of learning isn't that good for verbal
report.  Someone adept at statistics would have a mental model of
standard deviation, the t-test, statistical testing, etc.  Teaching
students rules or formulas does not develop mental models.

Bob F.



Re: teaching statistical methods by rules?

1999-12-18 Thread Robert Frick

Jerry Dallal wrote:
 
 Robert Frick wrote:
 
  I know it is hard to make statistics fun, but FOLLOWING
 RULES IS NEVER
  FUN.  Not in math, not in games, nowhere.
 
 In math and in games, following rules isn't just fun,
 IT'S THE LAW.  In fact, you can't have fun unless
 you follow them.  :-)

Well, technically, most real rules tell you what not to do -- they
usually don't tell you what to do, because that isn't fun.  In bridge,
the language of the bidding is very prescribed, but you almost always
have choices as to what you can bid.  On the other hand, the
prescription to bid 1NT with a balanced hand and 15-17 points tells you
what to do, but is not a real rule of the game.  Instead, it is a rule
the experts constructed so that the game wouldn't be fun.  Ha ha, they
really constructed the rule so that people could play better bridge. 
Destroying the game is an unintended byproduct.

In math, aren't students often taught algorithms for solving problems? 
Again, no fun.

Bob F.



Re: teaching statistical methods by rules?

1999-12-16 Thread Robert Frick

I happened to have a vehement and probably radical opinion on this. 
One of my sayings: "Ironically, our educational system is ideally suited
to teaching computers and ill-suited to teaching human beings."  If you
are going to program a computer to do statistics, tell the computer
rules to follow.

If you give students rules to memorize, they will surely forget them. 
If you had a student who learned and applied the rules, people would say
that the student was mindlessly following rules and couldn't think for
him/herself.  But your best student will just remember half the rules --
and by that, I mean half of each rule.

I know it is hard to make statistics fun, but FOLLOWING RULES IS NEVER
FUN.  Not in math, not in games, nowhere.

There are advantages to teaching rules.  Most students like it.  They
certainly understand that method of teaching.  They just won't learn
anything.

Bob F.



EAKIN MARK E wrote:
 
 I just received a review which stated that statistics should not be
 taught
 by the use of rules. For example a rule might  be: "if you wish to
 infer
 about the central tendency of a non-normal but continuous population
 using
 a small random sample, then use nonparametrics methods."
 
 I see why rules might not be appropriate in mathematical statistics
 classes where everything is developed by theory and proof. However I
 teach
 statistical methods classes to business students.
 
 It is my belief that if faculty do not give rules in methods classes,
 then
 students will infer the rules from the presentation. These
 student-developed rules may or may not be valid.
 
 I would be intested in reading what other faculty say about
 rule-based teaching depending on whether you teach theory or methods
 classes.
 
 Mark Eakin
 Associate Professor
 Information Systems and Management Sciences Department
 University of Texas at Arlington
 [EMAIL PROTECTED] or
 [EMAIL PROTECTED]