[EM] Corrected "strategy in Condorcet" section

2007-07-22 Thread ws
Michael Ossipoff has convinced me that winning votes Condorcet does not suffer
from the mess that margins Condorcet does. I've therefore corrected my paper
(http://www.cs.brown.edu/~ws/approval.pdf) to indicate this.

ws



This message was sent using IMP, the Internet Messaging Program.

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Correction of false statements by Ossipoff & Schudy about range voting.

2007-07-22 Thread Paul Kislanko
 
Steve Eppley wrote in part:
>>Warren Smith's 
example, in which a voter has total knowledge of all other votes before 
casting her own vote, is implausible in the elections we're interested 
in reforming.<<

I might be mistaken, but when I was introduced to this group it was more
about studying methods than "reforming elections." 

Folks who get all on board with election reform when their candidate loses
tend to not discuss things in terms of "methods" but of "practices" and
we're spending an inordinate amount of time on matters that mix voter
behaviour with the mathematics underlying an election method. I've proposed
before that there should be a way to axiomitize the distinctions (I'm not
smart enough to propose one, but I joined the list to learn about how all
the different methods work, not to try to impose one that I like...)

For what it's worth from all I've learned about methods on this list if I
were going to "reform" anything about the mess that is US national elections
I'd pick approval for party primaries and some Condorcet-compliant method
for the general elections. But from my parochial perspective the most badly
broken aspects of US elections aren't related to the choice of election
method - I have first-hand experience with supposedly illegal
dis-enfranchisement. The surest way to win re-election is not to allow your
opponents' supporters the opportunity to vote, and if you can get away with
that then it doesn't matter which method is used to count the votes. 



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Range Voting Strategy

2007-07-22 Thread ws
Clarifications on my claim that range voting strategies use extremes:

1) This claim is only valid in large elections, not small ones. See Myerson and
Weber's paper, which is cited in mine, for details on the reasonable
assumptions made for this claim.
2) It is true that if a voter is indifferent to voting for a candidate or not,
0.5 is also a rational vote. But whenever 0.5 is a rational vote in Myerson and
Weber's model, all other votes are rational too.

Warren Schudy


This message was sent using IMP, the Internet Messaging Program.

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Intermediate Ratings Never Optimal?

2007-07-22 Thread Forest W Simmons
One of the basic theorems of Linear Programming is that when there is 
an optimal value of a linear objective function it will occur at least 
one corner of the feasible region. 

In the rare cases that it occurs at two corners of the feasible region, 
it will also occur at every point on the line segment connecting the 
two corners.

In infinite precision Range voting the set of feasible votes (i.e. ways 
of marking a ballot) form an hypercube of dimension N if there are N 
candidates.  The corners of this hypercube are the points where all 
ratings are at extreme values.

It is possible (but unlikely) that a linear objective function could be 
maximized along a entire line segment on the boundary of this feasible 
region.

FWS



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Correction of false statements by Ossipff & Schudy about range voting.

2007-07-22 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax
At 12:34 PM 7/22/2007, Chris Benham wrote:

>I don't have a "password", so I can't access the given puzzle solution.

Yeah, irritating. I think you can get a password by asking for it, 
there is a procedure

>   Warren Schudy's "never" I suppose meant "never in a remotely
>plausible public political election scenario".

Where is the proof?

This is backpedalling. It's common for writers to make the claim, 
raw, without proof beyond an example which shows that a voter could 
regret voting sincerely. The problem with such a proof is that it can 
ignore all the situations where the voter could regret *not* voting 
sincerely. And, frankly, the pain of the latter is worse, other 
things being equal. That is, if you lost value because you were 
sincere, you can -- and most will -- say to themselves, well, at 
least I was honest. What do you say to yourself if you lose value 
because you exaggerated?

In any case, *now* Benham revises the claim to make it one which is 
far more difficult to test. Indeed, the only way to test it 
thoroughly is with simulations. But, wait a minute, these people 
don't trust simulations. Now, why are we supposed to trust *them*? 
The simulations are reproducible. And, indeed, I'm going to present 
one; I've taken a very simple tack with the three-candidate election 
described, looking at the voter's utilities and payoffs for the two 
strategies proposed: "Approval style" and "Sincere satisfaction 
rating." Or if you want to call it an "acceptance rating," fine.

>   I knew there was the odd exception in elections with very few 
> voters and/or the voter has
>much more precise information than s/he could ever plausibly have in 
>a public election.

Or the reverse! It turns out that in the zero-information case, where 
it is equally likely for all candidates to win, as far as the voter 
knows, it is in the voter's interest, clearly, to vote sincerely. 
Now, when I look at Warren's pages, I find that there is nothing new 
I have discovered. It's all there, but the problem is that ranked 
method supporters have read it skeptically, too skeptically. It's one 
thing to question Smith's *conclusions*, I question them all the 
time, he passes too far beyond what his evidence actually proves, 
sometimes. But his reports of what he has found, his expert 
testimony, if you will, should be taken at face value. Naturally, 
subject to verification.

But it is a long-standing legal principle that testimony is presumed 
true unless controverted.

In any case, I found a way to do an election simulation that takes a 
drastic shortcut; it turns out that if your vote counts at all, in 
Range, the election is equivalent to an election with only one other 
voter! I have not nailed down all the details, there are some aspects 
of the probabilities that are not crystal clear to me, though I 
intuit that I've got it right, but I'm sure there are people here 
capable of detecting any mistakes I've made.

It is categorically false that the optimum strategy is Approval 
style. The voter loses expected satisfaction by voting in this way.

In another post, I outlined the procedure. I'll repeat the outline here:

There is a voter with preference A>B>C, and the sincere ratings or 
utilities or expected satisfaction are such that the A>B preference 
is equally strong with the B>C preference. We will use a Range 2 
election, so the possible ratings are 2, 1, and 0, and these are the 
sincere ratings of our subject voter for the candidates A, B, and C.

With zero knowledge of the rest of the vote, what is the expected 
satisfaction for the voter for the two recommended strategies?

Kids are calling, gotta go. But I now have the answers. It's quite interesting.



>Regarding "social utility", I'm of the school that says that to the 
>extent that it is a real and wonderful thing it will look after itself if we do
>our best to ensure that the election method is as fair and 
>strategy-resistant as possible.
>
>Chris Benham
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Juho--Schudy's statement is correct.

2007-07-22 Thread Steve Eppley
I think Warren Schudy could have written a stronger negative comment 
about Range Voting.  Comparing it to Approval in his paper, he said it 
offers "little or no gain" (see below).  That suggests outcomes with 
Range Voting would tend to be at least as good as with Approval.  
Outcomes with Range Voting could be much worse.  What happens if many 
altruistic voters tend to try to vote sincerely and selfish voters tend 
to use the optimal strategy of extremizing to the limits of the range?  Ugh.
--Steve Eppley
-
Michael Ossipoff wrote:
-snip-
> On Jul 21, 2007, at 8:05 , Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:
>   
>> At 11:00 PM 7/20/2007, Chris Benham wrote:
>> 
>>> I think Warren Schudy put it well in a July 2007 draft paper:
>>>
>>> "Range voting is a generalisation of approval voting where you can
>>> give each candidate any score
>>> between 0 and 1. Optimal strategies never vote anything other than 0
>>> or 1, so range voting
>>> complicates ballots and confuses voters for little or no gain."
>>>   
-snip-

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Correction of false statements by Ossipoff & Schudy about range voting.

2007-07-22 Thread Steve Eppley
I partially agree with Chris Benham (see below).  Warren Smith's 
example, in which a voter has total knowledge of all other votes before 
casting her own vote, is implausible in the elections we're interested 
in reforming.

I don't know which methods Chris had in mind when he wrote "as fair and 
strategy-resistant as possible" but I'll take a moment here to defend 
the social utility of the best majoritarian preference order methods 
(such as MAM). 

Recall the example someone posted here several weeks ago intending to 
undermine the value of the majority rule criterion. Three friends, say 
X, Y and Z, are ordering a pizza. (It doesn't matter if they're friends; 
in the worst case they're not and they expect to never hear from each 
other again.)  Z is terribly allergic to mushrooms so he strongly 
prefers pepperoni, but a mushroom pizza is slightly preferred by X and 
Y.  There was no time to deliberate--which of course is implausible in 
the elections we're interested in reforming--so majority rule picks the 
mushroom pizza.

Or does it?  When X or Y proposes mushroom pizza, what if Z responds by 
proposing "pepperoni pizza plus the transfer of $1 from Z to X."  When Y 
hears this proposal, he thinks to himself that he'd prefer "pepperoni 
plus 50 cents" over mushroom, so Y proposes "pepperoni pizza plus a 
transfer of 50 cents from Z to Y."  Suppose X is even more indifferent 
between pepperoni and mushroom than Y is, and would prefer mushroom over 
pepperoni for just a dime.  X is clever, though, and bids 49 cents 
instead of a dime.  There was no deliberation; Z never admitted the 
allergy.  X and Z, a majority, both prefer X's final proposal over 
mushroom pizza. 

More precisely,
X's order of preference is:
"pepperoni plus $1 to X"
"pepperoni plus 49c to X"
mushroom
"pepperoni plus 50c to Y"  =  pepperoni

Y's order of preference is:
 "pepperoni plus 50c to Y"
 mushroom
 "pepperoni plus $1 to X"  =  "pepperoni plus 49c to X"  =  pepperoni

Z's order of preference is: 
  pepperoni
  "pepperoni plus 49c to X"
  "pepperoni plus 50c to Y"
  "pepperoni plus $1 to X"
  mushroom pizza

The only alternative for which no majority prefers some other 
alternative is "pepperoni plus 49c to X."  In the language some people 
use, it's the only alternative that's "unbeaten" pairwise.

Economists and political scientists call the transfer of 49 cents from Z 
to X a "side payment."  Side payments are a specific case of the more 
general solution: proposals that bundle alternatives.  That can also be 
called vote trading. in the case where the bundling is accomplished by 
trading votes on otherwise unlinked issues. 

A preference order on bundles is one way an individual can express her 
utilities, and is much more meaningful about her utilities--potentially 
allowing interpersonal comparisons of utilities--than the unitless votes 
expressed in Range Voting.  For example, the three friends learned that 
the utility difference for Y between mushroom pizza and pepperoni pizza 
is approximately 50 cents, since Y chose not to bid below the 49 cents 
that X bid.

Candidates wanting to win try to figure out a winning platform.  Given a 
good preference order method, the winning platform will be some 
"centrist" compromises, and competition will not be deterred.  
Candidates are creative; they can bundle together a platform of policies 
on unrelated issues, including side payments from some voters to others, 
and they'd have an incentive to try to figure out a platform (like X's 
proposal of Z's pizza plus 49 cents from Z to X) that minimizes the 
possibility that another candidate will find some platform preferred by 
a majority.  That competition should tend to drive them toward platforms 
that score well for social utility.

If the good preference order method of the previous paragraph also 
permits candidates to withdraw after the votes are cast, there will be 
little incentive for voters to strategically misrepresent their sincere 
orders of preference.  Warren Schudy neglected to consider such 
Condorcetian methods in his paper about Approval. (He also neglected to 
consider that the voting method--and candidates' beliefs about voter 
behavior, given the voting method--affects candidates' decisions on 
whether to run, and on what platforms, and hence will affect the voters' 
preferences.  Many people in this maillist make the same 
mistake--treating the set of alternatives and the voters' preferences as 
constant when comparing wildly different voting methods--and it's a huge 
mistake.)

If the good preference order method also permits each voter on election 
day to begin by selecting a ranking published before election day and 
modifying it if desired--perhaps by drag & drop; see the feature in the 
new NetFlix user interface for an example--before submitting it as her 
vote, then we won't have to worry, when there are many candidates, about 
the possibility that vote

Re: [EM] Intermediate RV rating is never optimal

2007-07-22 Thread Chris Benham



Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:


bits and pieces

At 05:33 AM 7/21/2007, Michael Ossipoff wrote:
 

That's incorrect. It's exactly the same in RV as in Approval. In 
your example, with B at your Approval cutoff, it doesn't matter how you rate B.
   



In what I wrote, B was not at the voters "approval cutoff." I didn't 
give an approval cutoff. Approval cutoff is an artificial insertion; 
it's a device for converting range ratings to approval votes.


This is the situation described:

The voter prefers A>B>C, with the preference strength between A and B 
being the same as the strength between B and C.


There is nothing here about Approval cutoff, there is nothing that 
says that the voter does or does not "approve" of *any* candidate.




I think we safely say that max-rating a candidate is equivalent to 
"approving" that candidate.


Ossipoff confused the fact that the candidate was intermediate 
between A and C in sincere rating, i.e., being midrange, with being 
"at your Approval cutoff."


If the preference strength between A and B is  weaker than that between 
B and C then with
the winning probabilities being equal (or unknown) then the voter's best 
strategy is to max-rate
A and B. If instead the preference strength between B and C is weaker, 
the voter does best to

min-rate B and C (and of course max-rate A).

Since the situation you describe is at the border of these two (max-rate 
B or min-rate B), we can

say that "B is at your approval cutoff".

And, quite clearly, it *does* matter how 
you rate B in some scenarios; for example, if the real pairwise 
election is between A and B, then the optimum vote is to rate B at 
minimum. And if it is between B and C, then the optimum vote is to 
rate B at maximum.




Of  course it can "matter" after the fact, but with both possible "real 
pairwise elections" being
equally likely at the time of voting, in Abd's scenario it 
probabilistically makes no difference what

rating the voter gives B.

Chris Benham



election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Correction of false statements by Ossipff & Schudy about range voting.

2007-07-22 Thread Chris Benham



Warren Smith wrote:


Warren Schudy in a July 2007 draft paper:
"Range voting is a generalisation of approval voting where you can give
each candidate any score
between 0 and 1. Optimal strategies never vote anything other than 0 or
1, so range voting
complicates ballots and confuses voters for little or no gain."

Ossipoff: Warren Schude's statement was correct
   



--CORRECTION: optimal strategies can vote other than 0 and 1, and
voting 0 or 1 can be suboptimal.

Examples include
http://rangevoting.org/RVstrat1.html
http://rangevoting.org/PuzzlePage.html#prob19

Also, just in the following incredibly trivial total knowledge example
TOTAL FROM OTHER VOTERS:  A=85.4  B=85.5
YOUR VOTE:A=?  B=?
the vote A=1 B=0 is equally as optimal as A=0.9 B=0.1.
This also falsifies the statement "Optimal strategies never vote anything other than 
0 or 1".
 



I don't have a "password", so I can't access the given puzzle solution.  
Warren Schudy's "never" I suppose meant "never in a remotely
plausible public political election scenario".  I knew there was the odd 
exception in elections with very few voters and/or the voter has
much more precise information than s/he could ever plausibly have in a 
public election.


Regarding "social utility", I'm of the school that says that to the 
extent that it is a real and wonderful thing it will look after itself 
if we do
our best to ensure that the election method is as fair and 
strategy-resistant as possible.


Chris Benham







election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Social Utility (aka Bayesian regret, aka Voter Satisfaction) methodology

2007-07-22 Thread Warren Smith
My writeup explaining this is
http://rangevoting.org/BayRegDum.html

just so that we no longer (hopefully) heaar any more howlers about how
SU "assumes sincere voters."

My public-source voting simulation program IEVS is available to all, but
with the restriction that is you make any improvements to it, I have to get 
them,
and I have to be credited...   
http://rangevoting.org/IEVS/IEVS.c

This program allows you to measure Bayesian Regret for any voting method under 
any
voter behavior.   However, the voting method you like best, or the voter 
behavior you
like best, may not yet be available inside IEVS.  In that case I suggest you 
add them.
IEVS is designed to make it maximally easy to add new voting methods, new 
probability
models, and new voter behaviors.

Warren D Smith
http://rangevoting.org  <-- add your endorsement by clicking "endorse" & 
filling out form...

election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info