Re: [EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative 2

2008-12-22 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 06:14 PM 12/21/2008, James Gilmour wrote:

Abd ul-Rahman LomaxSent: Sunday, December 21, 2008 1:44 AM
 LNH as an absolute principle, which, as an election criterion, it is,
 is harmful.

That is a value judgement  -  which of course you are perfectly 
entitled to make.


Sure. The desirability of any criterion is generally a value 
judgement. However, there are fundamental values and less fundamental 
ones, consensus values and idiosyncratic ones, ignorant values and 
informed ones. What I've heard from you, James, is that LNH is 
desirable because, without it, some voters (how many? under what 
conditions?) will be inclined to not add additional preferences, 
fearing harm to their favorite. Apparently, hang the outcome!


I said as an absolute principle. There is a political issue. If a 
voting system doesn't satisfy LNH, but the situations where that's 
possible, where that would actually impact the voter's interests, 
it's politically inconvenient. One can't say Never. I've seen, 
however, that LNH has been asserted for a method where, in context, 
it simply wasn't true, it was possible for a later preference, with 
IRV, to harm the favorite's election prospect, because it was IRV 
where a true majority requirement was maintained. *LNH is 
incompatible with a majority requirement, unless the further process 
considers all eliminated candidates permanently eliminated, no matter 
what. It's incompatible with direct democratic process.*


When I wrote absolute, I meant that some forms of LNH protection 
were quite possibly useful.


How, indeed, do we judge voting system criteria? Is there any 
approach that isn't subjective? How much harm is done by those 
alleged truncations because of the theoretical possibility of LNH 
failure. I've never seen any evidence that truncation is less common 
with IRV than it was with Bucklin, and there is some evidence to the 
contrary. Bucklin. Should I say, the American Preferential Voting 
System, as it was called?


It was an Englishman, though, who noted the probable reason for most 
truncation, and it ain't LNH fears. It is a combination of ignorance 
regarding remaining candidates and, on the other hand, strong 
preference for the favorite and relative disinterest in who wins if 
the favorite doesn't win. Preference strength. Don't leave home 
without it. It makes all kinds of voter behavior far more understandable.



 It prevents the system acting as a negotiator seeking
 compromise, because it prevents compromise until and unless the
 favorite is eliminated. Frankly, I doubt that anyone who fully
 understands the implications would prefer an LNH system to one which
 more appropriately negotiates on behalf of the voter, seeking the
 best compromise. LNH means *no compromise unless you eliminate my
 candidate totally!* That kind of position will readily be seen as
 fanatic, intransigent, and selfish, in normal negotiation situations.
 LNH in a system *enforces* this, requiring all voters to be just this
 intransigent.

I would hesitate to describe the electors I have experienced as 
fanatic, intransigent and selfish.


Of course not, but they are voting in a system that makes it 
unnecessary, if they are voting in an STV system. The system does it 
for them, and what I see from Mr. Gilmour is that this is what they 
want. I don't think they would really want it, if they understood the 
implications, and I suspect that he has not explained them to them.


I said that, in direct personal negotiations, this kind of behavior 
would generally be seen that way, not that voters were this way.



  What interests me particularly
is that their insistence on LNH (or at least, their reaction to the 
effects of its presumed absence) is an intuitive response.


Sure. Like lots of intuitive responses, it's less than optimal. There 
is nothing wrong with the response, per se. Bullet voting as an 
initial stage in negotiation is perfectly normal and functional. 
This is what I want, people will say. They don't say, if they have 
a significant preference, This is what I want, but if you don't like 
that, this other option is fine with me. That's giving away the farm 
for a small price. So I expect some kind of reluctance to disclose 
lower preferences. The strongest effect would be with Approval, which 
only allows equal ranking top or bottom. Bucklin fixes that, though, 
without *enforcing* LNH under all circumstances. Voters will know how 
to use it.


Optional Preferential Voting, in Australia, sees massive truncation. 
Truncation is normal, when voters are free to do it. *Most voters* in 
*most public elections* will truncate, they won't use up all the 
ranks even in a 3-rank system.


Other comments made by ordinary electors over the years lead me to 
suspect that this intuitive response reflects the importance

ordinary electors attach to their first preference.


Yes. It's functional, as I wrote above. The problem arises when the 
system *can't* move beyond that, 

Re: [EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative 2

2008-12-22 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 06:39 PM 12/21/2008, James Gilmour wrote:
It MAY be possible to imaging (one day) a President of the USA 
elected by Condorcet who had 32% of the first preferences against 35%
and 33% for the other two candidates.  But I find it completely 
unimaginable, ever, that a candidate with 5% of the first
preferences could be elected to that office as the Condorcet winner 
when the other two candidates had 48% and 47% of the first
preferences.  Condorcet winner  - no doubt.  But effective 
President  -  never!


Depends on the process. What if the process required majority 
approval. I.e., say it was a Range ballot, and first preference is 
expressed with a 100% vote. (Voters *may* express multiple first 
preferences, perhaps but there is little strategic incentive to do 
so, a 99% rating would have almost the same impact. Or a first 
preference marker is required, there could be some reasons for doing 
that.) But 50% rating is defined as Approval. I.e., consent to elect.


If the winner had a majority of ballots showing consent to elect, why 
would you think that this President couldn't be effective? We don't 
require that now! And some very effective Presidents didn't get a 
majority. They got a majority in the electoral college, that's different.


What if the electoral college were actually representative? What if 
it used real deliberative process, instead of voting as obligated? 
So, perhaps, electors, say, represented first preference votes. A 
candidate gets 5% first preference. But this is really the compromise 
candidate, and because of this, eventually gets the votes of a 
majority of electors? Why would this be a bad result?


Low first preference can mean different things. It means, for 
starters, that the candidate isn't the candidate of a major party. 
That could mean ineffective, or not. It would depend on the context. 
I'd assume that the electors representing the major party candidates 
wouldn't compromise on this one unless they though he or she would be 
effective!


But *effective* isn't everything. Sometimes it's enough to Do No 
Harm. In a badly polarized environment, on the verge of a civil war, 
electing the candidate with the most core support can be a total 
disaster, think the Hutus in Ruanda.





James

No virus found in this outgoing message.
Checked by AVG - http://www.avg.com
Version: 8.0.176 / Virus Database: 270.9.19/1860 - Release Date: 
21/12/2008 15:08




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative 2

2008-12-22 Thread Juho Laatu
--- On Mon, 22/12/08, James Gilmour jgilm...@globalnet.co.uk wrote:

 The two situations I had in mind were:
 Democrat candidate D;  Republican candidate R; 
 centrist candidate M
 
 Election 1
 35% DM;  33% RM;  32% M
 
 Election 2
 48% DM;  47% RM;  5% M
 
 M is the Condorcet winner in both elections, but the
 political consequences of the two results would be very
 different.  My own view
 is that the result of the first election would be
 acceptable, but the result of the second election would be
 unacceptable to the
 electorate as well as to the partisan politicians (who
 cannot be ignored completely!).  If such an outcome is
 possible with a
 particular voting system (as it is with Condorcet), that
 voting system will not be adopted for public elections.

Example 1.

In this country there are 10 small parties.
Each party has one candidate. In addition
there is one neutral candidate that has
worked to make the fighting parties agree
with each others. All voters vote
MyPartyCandidate  TheNeutralCandidate  ...
The neutral candidate gets 0% first
preferences but he might be the best
president anyway.

Example 2.

Voters of the large parties think that one
should not elect a president from a 5%
party. The votes are 48% DR; 47% RD; 5% M.
Candidate D will win. If the voters think
that it is better to elect a candidate from
a 5% party than to elect the candidate of
the large competing party then they could
vote as in your example. Maybe they gave M
a mandate although he is from a small 5%
party.

Example 3.

IRV philosophy is to emphasize the
importance of first place preferences
(among the remaining candidates during the
elimination process). First place
preferences could be considered to be a
sincere target in elections where the
elected person will need support of his
first place supporters when in office
(well, the voters could also simply vote
for candidates that have sufficient first
place support among the citizens). One
could do a similar trick also in Condorcet.
Let's say that a pairwise preference has
strength 1.5 if it includes the most
preferred candidate of the ballot. In that
case with preferences 43% DM; 42% RM;
15% M the pairwise comparison results would
be D-R 64.5-63; D-M 64.5-64.5; R-M 63-65.5.
That is a tie between D and M. Would this
be a good balance between the 35% M and
5% M examples?

Juho






  


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative 2

2008-12-22 Thread Dave Ketchum
Disturbing that you would consider clear wins by a majority to be 
objectionable.


In Election 2 Condorcet awarded the win to M.  Who has any business objecting?
 52 of 100 prefer M over D
 53 of 100 prefer M over R
 Neither R nor D got a majority of the votes.

As to my  no first preferences example, surest way to cause such is to be 
unable to respond to them.


DWK

On Mon, 22 Dec 2008 10:18:34 - James Gilmour wrote:

James Gilmour had written:
It MAY be possible to imaging (one day) a President of the USA elected 
by Condorcet who had 32% of the first preferences against 35% and 33% 
for the other two candidates.  But I find it completely unimaginable, 
ever, that a candidate with 5% of the first preferences could be 
elected to that office as the Condorcet winner when the other two 
candidates had 48% and 47% of the first preferences.

Condorcet winner  - no doubt.  But effective President  -  never!




Dave Ketchum   Sent: Monday, December 22, 2008 4:24 AM 


Such a weak Condorcet winner would also be unlikely.

Second preferences?
 That 5% would have to avoid the two strong candidates.
 The other two have to avoid voting for each other - likely, for they 
are likely enemies of each other.
 The other two could elect the 5%er - getting the 5% 
makes this seem possible.
 Could elect a candidate who got no first preference 
votes?  Seems unlikely.


I see the three each as possibles via first and second preferences - and 
acceptable even with only 5% first - likely a compromise candidate.


Any other unlikely to be a winner.

What were you thinking of as weak winner?



I'm afraid I don't understand your examples at all.  The no first preferences 
example is so extreme I would not consider it
realistic.  But, of course, if it were possible to elect a no first 
preferences candidate as the Condorcet winner, such a result
would completely unacceptable politically and the consequences would be 
disastrous.

The two situations I had in mind were:
Democrat candidate D;  Republican candidate R;  centrist candidate M

Election 1
35% DM;  33% RM;  32% M

Election 2
48% DM;  47% RM;  5% M

M is the Condorcet winner in both elections, but the political consequences of 
the two results would be very different.  My own view
is that the result of the first election would be acceptable, but the result of 
the second election would be unacceptable to the
electorate as well as to the partisan politicians (who cannot be ignored 
completely!).  If such an outcome is possible with a
particular voting system (as it is with Condorcet), that voting system will not 
be adopted for public elections.

James

--
 da...@clarityconnect.compeople.clarityconnect.com/webpages3/davek
 Dave Ketchum   108 Halstead Ave, Owego, NY  13827-1708   607-687-5026
   Do to no one what you would not want done to you.
 If you want peace, work for justice.




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative 2

2008-12-22 Thread Terry Bouricius
Dave,

I think you make a common semantic manipulation about the nature of a 
Condorcet winner (particularly in a weak CW example) by using the term 
wins by a majority. In fact, each of the separate and distinct pairwise 
majorities may consist largely of different voters, rather than any 
solid majority. This is why I think the Mutual-Majority Criterion is a 
more useful criterion. In a crowded field, a weak CW may be a 
little-considered candidate that every voter ranks next to last.  The 
phrase wins by a majority creates the image in the reader's mind of a 
happy satisfied group of voters (that is more than half of the electors), 
who would feel gratified by this election outcome. In fact, in a weak CW 
situation, every single voter could feel the outcome was horrible if the 
CW is declared elected. Using a phrase like wins by a majority creates 
the false impression that a majority of voters favor this candidate OVER 
THE FIELD of other candidates AS A WHOLE, whereas NO SUCH MAJORITY 
necessarily exist for there to be a Condorcet winner. The concept of 
Condorcet constructs many distinct majorities, who may be at odds, and 
none of which actually need to like this Condorcet winner. I am not 
arguing that the concept of Condorcet winner is not a legitimate 
criterion, just that its normative value is artificially heightened by 
saying the candidate wins by a majority when no such actual solid 
majority needs to exist.

Terry Bouricius

- Original Message - 
From: Dave Ketchum da...@clarityconnect.com
To: jgilm...@globalnet.co.uk
Cc: election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Sent: Monday, December 22, 2008 7:23 PM
Subject: Re: [EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative 2


Disturbing that you would consider clear wins by a majority to be
objectionable.

In Election 2 Condorcet awarded the win to M.  Who has any business 
objecting?
  52 of 100 prefer M over D
  53 of 100 prefer M over R
  Neither R nor D got a majority of the votes.

As to my  no first preferences example, surest way to cause such is to 
be
unable to respond to them.

DWK

On Mon, 22 Dec 2008 10:18:34 - James Gilmour wrote:
James Gilmour had written:
It MAY be possible to imaging (one day) a President of the USA elected
by Condorcet who had 32% of the first preferences against 35% and 33%
for the other two candidates.  But I find it completely unimaginable,
ever, that a candidate with 5% of the first preferences could be
elected to that office as the Condorcet winner when the other two
candidates had 48% and 47% of the first preferences.
Condorcet winner  - no doubt.  But effective President  -  never!


 Dave Ketchum   Sent: Monday, December 22, 2008 4:24 AM

Such a weak Condorcet winner would also be unlikely.

Second preferences?
  That 5% would have to avoid the two strong candidates.
  The other two have to avoid voting for each other - likely, for 
 they
are likely enemies of each other.
  The other two could elect the 5%er - getting the 5%
makes this seem possible.
  Could elect a candidate who got no first preference
votes?  Seems unlikely.

I see the three each as possibles via first and second preferences - and
acceptable even with only 5% first - likely a compromise candidate.

Any other unlikely to be a winner.

What were you thinking of as weak winner?


 I'm afraid I don't understand your examples at all.  The no first 
 preferences example is so extreme I would not consider it
 realistic.  But, of course, if it were possible to elect a no first 
 preferences candidate as the Condorcet winner, such a result
 would completely unacceptable politically and the consequences would be 
 disastrous.

 The two situations I had in mind were:
 Democrat candidate D;  Republican candidate R;  centrist candidate M

 Election 1
 35% DM;  33% RM;  32% M

 Election 2
 48% DM;  47% RM;  5% M

 M is the Condorcet winner in both elections, but the political 
 consequences of the two results would be very different.  My own view
 is that the result of the first election would be acceptable, but the 
 result of the second election would be unacceptable to the
 electorate as well as to the partisan politicians (who cannot be ignored 
 completely!).  If such an outcome is possible with a
 particular voting system (as it is with Condorcet), that voting system 
 will not be adopted for public elections.

 James
-- 
  da...@clarityconnect.compeople.clarityconnect.com/webpages3/davek
  Dave Ketchum   108 Halstead Ave, Owego, NY  13827-1708   607-687-5026
Do to no one what you would not want done to you.
  If you want peace, work for justice.




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Why I think IRV isn't a serious alternative 2

2008-12-22 Thread Markus Schulze
Hallo,

Terry Bouricius wrote (22 Dec 2008):

 In a crowded field, a weak CW may be a
 little-considered candidate that every
 voter ranks next to last.

As the Borda score of a CW is always
above the average Borda score, it is
not possible that the CW is a
little-considered candidate that
every voter ranks next to last.

Terry Bouricius wrote (22 Dec 2008):

 The phrase wins by a majority creates
 the image in the reader's mind of a happy
 satisfied group of voters (that is more
 than half of the electors), who would feel
 gratified by this election outcome. In
 fact, in a weak CW situation, every single
 voter could feel the outcome was horrible
 if the CW is declared elected. Using a
 phrase like wins by a majority creates
 the false impression that a majority of
 voters favor this candidate OVER THE FIELD
 of other candidates AS A WHOLE, whereas
 NO SUCH MAJORITY necessarily exist for
 there to be a Condorcet winner.

On the other side, IRV supporters usually
use the term majority winner in such
a manner that it could refer to every
candidate, except for a Condorcet loser.

Markus Schulze



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info