Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 10:52 PM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
 wrote:
> In the context of SEC, it would be:
>
> Voter submits two ballots - one is ranked and the other is a Plurality
> ballot. Call the first the fallback ballot, and the second the consensus
> ballot.
>
> If everybody (or some very high percentage, e.g. 99%) votes for the same
> consensus ballot, it wins. Otherwise, construct a Condorcet matrix based on
> the fallback ballots. Pick two candidates at random and the one that
> pairwise beats the other, wins.

How do you pick the random candidates?

For that to be clone independent, there would actually need to be 3 ballots:

- consensus ballot

If more than X% of the ballots pick the same candidate, then that
candidate wins.

- nomination ballot
- fallback ranking

2 nomination ballots are picked to decide the candidate and the
pairwise winner according to the rankings wins.

However, as I said in my last post, the nomination ballot isn't strategy free.

> To my knowledge, Random Pair is strategy-free. It might also be
> proportional, but I'm not sure about that (partly because I'm not sure how
> you'd define "proportional" for ranked ballots).

The problem is picking the 2 candidates.  If 2 are picked at random,
then the method isn't clone independent.

Also, it favours the condorcet winner, so may suffer from tyranny of
the majority.

However, if you had a divided society, then both ethnic groups would
still have some say.

For example, if the split was 55% (A) and 45 (B), and each ethnic
group only voted for their own candidate, then the results would be

2 A's: 30% => ethnic group A wins
A+B:  50% => ethnic group A wins (as they are the majority)
2 B's: 20% => ethnic group B wins

Thus group B gets some power, but not proportional power.

However, once the society starts working better, it would seamlessly
transition to a near condorcet method.

Also, in a divided society condorcet voting might reduce the issue directly.

In both cases, there would be an incentive for politicians from ethnic
group A to try to get support from voters in ethnic group B.

OTOH, a random election method may not be the best plan in a society
where corruption is a problem.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Raph Frank wrote:

On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 8:11 PM, Jobst Heitzig  wrote:

Hello Kristofer,

Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
respect to Random Ballot?

This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
of them? I will think about this...


Presumably, it means that the voter submits 2 ballots, a ranking and a
nomination for the 2nd round?


In the context of SEC, it would be:

Voter submits two ballots - one is ranked and the other is a Plurality 
ballot. Call the first the fallback ballot, and the second the consensus 
ballot.


If everybody (or some very high percentage, e.g. 99%) votes for the same 
consensus ballot, it wins. Otherwise, construct a Condorcet matrix based 
on the fallback ballots. Pick two candidates at random and the one that 
pairwise beats the other, wins.


To my knowledge, Random Pair is strategy-free. It might also be 
proportional, but I'm not sure about that (partly because I'm not sure 
how you'd define "proportional" for ranked ballots).


You seem to be suggesting a more Condorcet way of doing the consensus 
balloting. A possible option would be to look at how e.g. Debian handles 
supermajority issues. On the other hand, grafting Condorcet onto the 
consensus option would make the actual consensus more opaque, and one 
may in any case argue: "if you have a consensus, there's an agreement 
and so you don't need a complex method to determine what the consensus 
actually is".


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 8:11 PM, Jobst Heitzig  wrote:
> Hello Kristofer,
>> Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
>> from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
>> respect to Random Ballot?
>
> This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
> Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
> of them? I will think about this...

Presumably, it means that the voter submits 2 ballots, a ranking and a
nomination for the 2nd round?

Clearly, your rankings should be honest, as it is only looked at once
the 2 candidates have been decided.

However, your nomination would have to be made tactically.

It would require that the voter decide the probability of the
candidate they nominate winning.

If you nominate the condorcet winner, then the odds of your candidate
winning the second round is 100%, as no other candidate can possibly
beat him..

However, if you nominate an extremist, then your nomination is almost
certain to fail, as he will lose to virtually any other candidate.

If the voter distribution is symmetric (and voter utility is
symmetric) around a central point, then the nominated candidate who is
closest to the centre will win.

If each voter nominates their favourite, then you best strategy is to
nominate the the candidate which maximises

f(distance)*utility

f(distance) is the fraction of the nominations that nominate
candidates further away than that distance from the centre.

f(0) is automatically 1 and f(most extremist candidate's distance) is
automatically 0.  Also, f(d) is a monotonic decreasing function.

Thus, when considering 2 candidates of near equal utility, you should
nominate the candidate nearest the centre.

However, if all voters do that, then most of the nominations will
start to be clustered near the centre.  This means that the voters
should nominate candidates even closer to the centre.

I.e. if f(d) = 0.1, then you would have to prefer that candidate at
least 10 times better than the condorcet winner in order to nominate
him.

I think the effect could very easily end up being that the condorcet
winner normally wins.

It could also be implemented in 2 formal rounds.  In the first round,
each voter votes for 1 candidate.  2 candidates are picked at random,
using random ballot.

Those 2 candidates then proceed to the run off.  This might even make
people accept random ballot.  The problem that a candidate with 1%
support could get to be President is eliminated.  (Unless it happens
twice in 1 election.)

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] About non-monotonicity and non-responding to previous posts...

2009-11-10 Thread Dave Ketchum
What I wrote last time is about as simple as you get.  Canceling the  
smallest margin cancels a three-member cycle, leaving the strongest  
member as CW.  Could take more canceling for more complex, and thus  
rarer, cycles.


Dave Ketchum

On Nov 10, 2009, at 7:54 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:


Dave Ketchum wrote:
Trying some fresh thinking for Condorcet, and what anyone should be  
able to see in the X*X array.  I am ignoring labels such as Schulze  
and Ranked Pairs - this is human-doable and minimal effort -  
especially with normally having a CW and most cycles having the  
minimal three members.
1.  Look at any pair of  candidates.  Loser is not the CW  (there  
can be a tie in any comparison here - NOT likely in a normal  
election, but we have to be prepared with responses for such).
2.  If there are other possible CWs, repeat step 1 with latest  
winner and one of them.
3.  If there are other candidates latest winner has not been  
compared with, compare it with each of them.

4.  If winner wins each of these, it is CW.
5.  Winner and each who beat it in step 4 are cycle members.  Also,  
any candidate beating any of these is also a cycle member.
IF there is a CW, it should win - anything else is a complication,  
even if some math makes claims for the something else.
Otherwise a simple cycle resolution should apply.  Simply  
canceling the smallest margin has been thought of - that value  
means minimum difference in vote counts between actual and what is  
assumed.
Note that each cycle member would be CW if remaining cycle  
members were ignored.

As to voting:
Equal ranks permitted.
Write-ins permitted, and such a candidate wins with the same  
vote counts as if nominated.
As to clones, strategy, primaries, and runoffs - all seem best  
ignored, though only a nuisance if some are determined to involve  
such.


Okay, so let's see which *simple* cycle breaker provides as much as  
possible. To do that, we'll need to find out what simplicity means,  
and how to define "as much as possible".


That could be interesting in itself.

Ranked Pairs (or River) seems nice, but even it may be too complex.  
Sports usually employ Copeland (but modified); perhaps that could be  
used - but Copeland is indecisive. One can add Smith compliance by  
checking for a CW among the first n ranked in the output, then n-1,  
then n-2 and so on, but that might also be too complex.


Of course, if simplicity is paramount (i.e. we want very simple) we  
could just go with "break it by whoever beats the Plurality winner  
by the greatest amount" or plain old minmax (candidate with least  
worst defeat wins) or LR (greatest sum of victories wins).





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Hello Kristofer,

you wrote:



You could probably devise a whole class of SEC-type methods. They would
go: if there is a consensus (defined in some fashion), then it wins -
otherwise, a nondeterministic strategy-free method is used to pick the
winner. The advantage of yours is that it uses only Plurality ballots.


The hard point is, I think, to define what actually a potential
consensus option is. And here the idea was to say everything unanimously
preferred to some benchmark outcome qualifies as potential consensus.
The benchmark then cannot be any feasible option but must be a lottery
of some options, otherwise the supporters of the single option would
block the consensus. But which lottery you take as a benchmark could be
discussed. I chose the Random Ballot lottery since it seems the most
fair one and has all nice properties (strategy-freeness, proportional
allocation of power).


I suppose the nondeterministic method would have to be "bad enough" to
provide incentive to pick the right consensus, yet it shouldn't be so
bad as to undermine the process itself if the voters really can't reach
a consensus.


Although I can hardly imagine real-world situations in which no
consensus option can be found (maybe be combining different decisions
into one, or using some kind of compensation scheme if necessary).


That might be true for a consensus in general, but I was referring to 
the SEC method, where all it takes is for a single voter to submit a 
different consensus ballot than the rest.



Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
respect to Random Ballot? 


This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
of them? I will think about this...


Yes. The CW now has a greater chance to win - but note that it's not 
given that the CW will win, because if he's not picked as one of the 
pair candidates, he doesn't come into play at all.



It would lead to a better outcome if the
consensus fails, but so also make it more likely that the consensus does
fail. Or would it? The reasoning from a given participant's point of
view is rather: do I get something *I* would like by refusing to take
part in consensus -- not, does *society* get something acceptable.


I'm not sure I know what you mean here.


Well, I was thinking that the SEC method provides an incentive for 
people to reach a common consensus because the alternative, which is the 
random ballot, isn't very good. Any (random or deterministic) method 
that favors some group would lead to that group having less of an 
incentive to participate in the consensus process because they know 
they'll get something they'll like.


Therefore, I at first thought that even though Random Pair would provide 
a result more people would be happy with, it would make the voters less 
interested in actually finding a consensus because the alternative isn't 
so bad anymore. However, then I realized that any given voter, if he's 
at the point where he doesn't care about the consensus option, will not 
be deterred from such a line of thinking because the alternative is 
suboptimal for society, only if it is suboptimal in his point of view. 
That means that you could replace Random Ballot with Random Pair as long 
as the fairness (what you call proportional allocation of power) remains 
intact, because if the improvement in result lifts all the groups 
equally, there's no more incentive for some group to "cheat" with 
respect to any other.


There's also another way of looking at it, which I just saw now: my 
first idea was that you can't move to a lottery that gives consistently 
good results because that will diminish people's interest in determining 
a consensus. But if the lottery is both fair and provides good results, 
then who cares? The consensus option will only come into play if the 
people can explicitly agree on a choice that's better than the expected 
value of the lottery. If figuring out a consensus is worth it (much 
better than the lottery, relatively speaking), then people will care, 
otherwise they won't. Thus improving the lottery part of the method will 
improve the method in general - it'll make up the amount it no longer 
encourages people to determine the consensus, by just giving better results.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Hello Kristofer,

you wrote:
> However, my point was that Range goes further: a minority that acts
> in a certain way can get what it wants, too; all that's required is that
> the majority does not vote Approval style (either max or min) and that
> the minority does, and that the minority is not too small.
> 
> It is in that respect I mean that Range is more radical, because it
> permits a minority to overrule a majority that otherwise agrees about
> which candidates it prefers. For those who mean that elections have to
> be, at least, majoritarian, Range may contain a surprise.

That's true. Methods in which a group can suppress the rest are
certainly bad, even more so when the group can be small...

> You could probably devise a whole class of SEC-type methods. They would
> go: if there is a consensus (defined in some fashion), then it wins -
> otherwise, a nondeterministic strategy-free method is used to pick the
> winner. The advantage of yours is that it uses only Plurality ballots.

The hard point is, I think, to define what actually a potential
consensus option is. And here the idea was to say everything unanimously
preferred to some benchmark outcome qualifies as potential consensus.
The benchmark then cannot be any feasible option but must be a lottery
of some options, otherwise the supporters of the single option would
block the consensus. But which lottery you take as a benchmark could be
discussed. I chose the Random Ballot lottery since it seems the most
fair one and has all nice properties (strategy-freeness, proportional
allocation of power).

> I suppose the nondeterministic method would have to be "bad enough" to
> provide incentive to pick the right consensus, yet it shouldn't be so
> bad as to undermine the process itself if the voters really can't reach
> a consensus.

Although I can hardly imagine real-world situations in which no
consensus option can be found (maybe be combining different decisions
into one, or using some kind of compensation scheme if necessary).

> Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information
> from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with
> respect to Random Ballot? 

This sounds interesting, but what exactly do you mean by Random Pair?
Pick a randomly chosen pair of candidates and elect the pairwise winner
of them? I will think about this...

> It would lead to a better outcome if the
> consensus fails, but so also make it more likely that the consensus does
> fail. Or would it? The reasoning from a given participant's point of
> view is rather: do I get something *I* would like by refusing to take
> part in consensus -- not, does *society* get something acceptable.

I'm not sure I know what you mean here.

Yours, Jobst

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Dave Ketchum

On Nov 10, 2009, at 7:58 AM, Matthew Welland wrote:

On Tuesday 10 November 2009 03:57:34 am you wrote:

Dear Matthew,

you wrote:
Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet"  
ideals.


  1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
 how they work in one or two sentences.


Well, here's a very simple "Condorcet" system which can easily be
explained in two sentences:

1. Let voters vote on candidate pairs, successively replacing the  
loser

with a different candidate, in a random order of candidates.
2. As soon as all candidates have been included, the winner of the  
last

pair is declared the overall winner.

This system is arguably the earliest example of a "Condorcet"  
system. It
was devised by Ramon Llull in the 13th century and was successfully  
used
for elections in monastaries. It is easily understood by the common  
man

since it resembles a procedure frequently used in child play.


That is an excellent description. Thanks.


Gives a feel for something good enough for their purposes - if there  
is a CW the CW wins.


BUT, if there is a cycle, the best candidate can lose to another cycle  
member - so better make sure the apparent CW gets compared with every  
other candidate.


I've always liked that specific system and think being Condorcet  
compliant

makes great sense in smaller elections or where a perfect choice is
critical.

Implementing it on a large scale seems tough and actually voting in  
it seems
tedious. If there are N candidates am I forced to make N-1  
decisions? If

there is a short circuit way to do the vote then it might be workable.


In voting you could start with thinking who you would approve of.   
Then vote for them, while ignoring the others that you like less.  Do  
any of:

 Approve them by giving them the same rank.
 Vote for the best as in FPTP.
 Rank them to show your preference for better vs lesser.



The improvement over approval still seems marginal, especially in  
large
elections and I think the cost for implementing, tabulating and  
voting is

much higher,


Agreed the implementing costs - mostly in being able to do this.  With  
the ability you get a big help in some elections and less or little in  
others (like 0 when only two candidates).


Tabulating a ballot gets to be labor when a voter ranks many candidates.

Being able to determine winner from the N*N array was an implementing  
cost, but then easy to do via computer (assuming use of an easy  
variant of Condorcet).


Voters who were happy with FPTP will see no benefit - but no cost once  
they see they can vote as they have before.


Voters who have studied range/score will make two groups:  sad to be  
unable to express the exact size of their likes/dislikes; thankful for  
the easier decisions involved here.


Voters who want to rank higher those they like best will be thankful  
to get past approval.


Dave Ketchum



Yours, Jobst




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] NESD and NESD* properties of a single-winner voting method

2009-11-10 Thread Warren Smith
Let me clarify my thinking a bit (I hope) behind NESD and NESD*.

NESD stands for "Naive Exaggeration Strategy ==> Duopoly."

NES means the voter strategy of
1) identify the "top two" candidates most likely to win.
2) Exaggerate your (otherwise honest) vote to rank one top
and the other bottom.  (With NESD*, unique-top; with NESD, permitted to be
co-equal top.)It appears that, in the real world, this is a pretty
close approximation of
what a very large percentage of voters in large well publicized+polled
elections actually do (it does not necessarily always make complete
sense that they do that, but the data indicates they do it anyway).

The D part means: if all (or a very large percentage) of voters
exhibit NES behavior, then
one of the top-two will always win (except in exceedingly unlikely
"perfect-tie" scenarios).
And in fact, the same winner will arise as in strategic plurality
voting, so any system
failing NESD or NESD* can be accused (perhaps not with full
justification, but certainly
with some) of being "equivalent in the real world" to plain plurality
voting, and presumably
leading of historical time to "duopoly" where voters effectively only
get one of two choices every election.  This severely diminishes voter
choice and "democracy" if it happens (versus some system with more
than 2 choices).

It's an interesting property (or two properties) and I think worth
consideration.
You can now ask yourself other interesting questions, like "how can I
design good voting
systems passing NESD or NESD*?" etc.


-- 
Warren D. Smith
http://RangeVoting.org  <-- add your endorsement (by clicking
"endorse" as 1st step)
and
math.temple.edu/~wds/homepage/works.html

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] NESD and NESD* properties of a single-winner voting method

2009-11-10 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Nov 10, 2009, at 5:07 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:

> Jobst Heitzig wrote:
>> Dear Warren,
>> I don't seem to understand the definition:
>>> A single-winner voting system "fails the NESD property" if, when every
>>> honest voter
>>> changes their vote to rank A top and B bottom (or B top and A bottom;
>>> depends on the voter which way she goes), leaving it otherwise
>>> unaltered, that always (except in very rare "exact tie" situations)
>>> causes A or B to win.
>> So, when all voters vote strategic (i.e. no voter is honest) and all
>> leave their ballots unchanged, then by definition "every honest voter
>> changes their vote to rank A top and B bottom" but of course no system
>> changes the result since no ballot is changed. Hence no system fails NESD.
>> What is the misunderstanding here?
> 
> I think he means:
> 
> Call the first group of ballots, X, consisting of ranked ballots made by 
> honest voters. Now take every ballot in X and, for each ballot y, if y votes 
> A > B, put A first and B last, or if y votes B > A, put B first and A last, 
> leavin the ballot otherwise unchanged. Call the modified bundle, consisting 
> of these modified y-ballots, X'.
> 
> If there exists such a group of ballots X so that the method in question 
> gives a different victor when fed X and when fed X', and gives either A or B 
> as the victor for group X', then it fails the NESD property.
> 
> In other words: if the entire electorate decides that the dangerous contest 
> is A vs B and so maximally buries the one they like the least, and this 
> strategy pays off, then it fails this property.

That's the way I read it. In other words, interpret Majority failure as a 
virtue.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting?

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Dear Kristofer,

both Approval Voting and Range Voting *are* majoritarian: A majority
can always get their will and suppress the minority by simply bullet-voting.

So, a more interesting version of your question could be: Which
*democratic* method (that does not allow any sub-group to suppress the
rest) has (usually or on average or in the worst case) the least
Bayesian Regret.


Yes. A majority that acts in a certain way can get what it wants. That's 
true for Range and Approval, and it's true for Condorcet, Plurality, 
etc. However, my point was that Range goes further: a minority that acts 
in a certain way can get what it wants, too; all that's required is that 
the majority does not vote Approval style (either max or min) and that 
the minority does, and that the minority is not too small.


It is in that respect I mean that Range is more radical, because it 
permits a minority to overrule a majority that otherwise agrees about 
which candidates it prefers. For those who mean that elections have to 
be, at least, majoritarian, Range may contain a surprise.



I conjecture that at least when the nomination of additional options
is allowed, the method SEC described recently is a hot candidate for
this award, since it seems that SEC will lead to the election of the
option at the *mean* (instead of the median) voter position, and I guess
that in most spacial utility models the mean position is in many senses
"better" and will in particular have less Bayesian Regret than the
median position. (Recall that in a one-dimensional spacial model where
additional options can be nominated, all majoritarian methods likely
lead to median positions being realized and are thus basically all
equivalent.)


You could probably devise a whole class of SEC-type methods. They would 
go: if there is a consensus (defined in some fashion), then it wins - 
otherwise, a nondeterministic strategy-free method is used to pick the 
winner. The advantage of yours is that it uses only Plurality ballots.


I suppose the nondeterministic method would have to be "bad enough" to 
provide incentive to pick the right consensus, yet it shouldn't be so 
bad as to undermine the process itself if the voters really can't reach 
a consensus.


Assume (for the sake of simplicity) that we can get ranked information 
from the voters. What difference would a SEC with Random Pair make, with 
respect to Random Ballot? It would lead to a better outcome if the 
consensus fails, but so also make it more likely that the consensus does 
fail. Or would it? The reasoning from a given participant's point of 
view is rather: do I get something *I* would like by refusing to take 
part in consensus -- not, does *society* get something acceptable.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] NESD and NESD* properties of a single-winner voting method

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Jobst Heitzig wrote:

Dear Warren,

I don't seem to understand the definition:

A single-winner voting system "fails the NESD property" if, when every
honest voter
changes their vote to rank A top and B bottom (or B top and A bottom;
depends on the voter which way she goes), leaving it otherwise
unaltered, that always (except in very rare "exact tie" situations)
causes A or B to win.


So, when all voters vote strategic (i.e. no voter is honest) and all
leave their ballots unchanged, then by definition "every honest voter
changes their vote to rank A top and B bottom" but of course no system
changes the result since no ballot is changed. Hence no system fails NESD.

What is the misunderstanding here?


I think he means:

Call the first group of ballots, X, consisting of ranked ballots made by 
honest voters. Now take every ballot in X and, for each ballot y, if y 
votes A > B, put A first and B last, or if y votes B > A, put B first 
and A last, leavin the ballot otherwise unchanged. Call the modified 
bundle, consisting of these modified y-ballots, X'.


If there exists such a group of ballots X so that the method in question 
gives a different victor when fed X and when fed X', and gives either A 
or B as the victor for group X', then it fails the NESD property.


In other words: if the entire electorate decides that the dangerous 
contest is A vs B and so maximally buries the one they like the least, 
and this strategy pays off, then it fails this property.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Matthew Welland
On Tuesday 10 November 2009 03:57:34 am you wrote:
> Dear Matthew,
>
> you wrote:
> > Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
> >
> >1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
> >   how they work in one or two sentences.
>
> Well, here's a very simple "Condorcet" system which can easily be
> explained in two sentences:
>
> 1. Let voters vote on candidate pairs, successively replacing the loser
> with a different candidate, in a random order of candidates.
> 2. As soon as all candidates have been included, the winner of the last
> pair is declared the overall winner.
>
> This system is arguably the earliest example of a "Condorcet" system. It
> was devised by Ramon Llull in the 13th century and was successfully used
> for elections in monastaries. It is easily understood by the common man
> since it resembles a procedure frequently used in child play.

That is an excellent description. Thanks.

I've always liked that specific system and think being Condorcet compliant 
makes great sense in smaller elections or where a perfect choice is 
critical.

Implementing it on a large scale seems tough and actually voting in it seems 
tedious. If there are N candidates am I forced to make N-1 decisions? If 
there is a short circuit way to do the vote then it might be workable. 

The improvement over approval still seems marginal, especially in large 
elections and I think the cost for implementing, tabulating and voting is 
much higher,


> Yours, Jobst
>
> Matthew Welland schrieb:
> > Thanks all for the discussion and pointers. I still can't concretely
> > conclude anything yet but here are some rambling and random thoughts
> > based on what was said and my prior experiences.
> >
> > Plurality
> >
> >1. Leads to two lowest common denominator parties which are not
> >   accountable to the voters. This conclusion supported by real
> > world observation.
> >2. Feels right to the non-critical mind, "one man, one vote"
> >3. Very fast at the polls
> >
> > Approval
> >
> >1. Encourages participation of minor parties and thus should keep
> > the big guys paying attention to a wider base.
> >2. Almost zero marginal implementation cost. Hanging chads count
> > just fine :)
> >3. Understandable by anyone but feels wrong at first "not fair, you
> >   get more than one vote".
> >4. Apparently has a terrible flaw but no one seems to be able to
> >   articulate it in layman terms. No real world experience available
> >   to illustrate the problem. Here is where I need to learn more.
> >   Data provided to date is unconvincing to me.
> >5. Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate
> >   between "I like", "I like a lot" etc. (note: this seems like
> >   perfectionism to me. Large numbers of voters and opinions all
> > over the bell curve should make individual expression at the greater
> > level of granularity irrelevant.)
> >6. Very fast at the polls. Pick yer favorites and head home for beer
> >   and telly.
> >
> > Range
> >
> >1. Can break the vicious cycle of plurality
> >2. Not voting for someone at all can have a strong influence on
> >   election outcome. This is very non-intuitive and would take some
> >   getting used to.
> >3. Allows for nuanced voting.
> >4. Pain in the ass at the polls (relatively speaking). You can't
> >   safely disregard the candidates you don't care about so you
> > *have* to assign everyone a ranking, possibly addressable by defaulting
> > to zero for all candidates? This is considered a feature and I agree it
> > has merit. But in reality it is a deal breaker for joe six pack and co.
> > (and for lazy sobs like me).
> >
> > IRV
> >
> >1. Demonstrably broken. 'nuff said.
> >
> > Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
> >
> >1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
> >   how they work in one or two sentences.
> >2. Technically superior to other systems.
> >3. Not clear what problem with approval they would solve. Unless you
> >   are a perfectionist and insist that individuals express nuances
> > of opinion...
> >
> > Some time ago I put together a site (primitive and unfinished[i]) to
> > promote approval voting and in the process I spent a lot of time trying
> > different systems on the web and repeatedly testing my own site. I
> > noticed some interesting things from all that playing around.
> >
> >1. It was very uncomfortable to go back to plurality after trying
> >   other systems. It "feels" unfair and broken.
> >2. It was very tedious voting in any of the ranking systems.
> >3. Approval felt boring but good.
> >
> > I have checked in on this list now and then and I admit I don't have
> > the time or skills to follow all the arguments but it strikes me that
> > approval voting is good enough to break the deadlock, at least i

Re: [EM] About non-monotonicity and non-responding to previous posts...

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Dave Ketchum wrote:
Trying some fresh thinking for Condorcet, and what anyone should be able 
to see in the X*X array.  I am ignoring labels such as Schulze and 
Ranked Pairs - this is human-doable and minimal effort - especially with 
normally having a CW and most cycles having the minimal three members.


1.  Look at any pair of  candidates.  Loser is not the CW  (there can be 
a tie in any comparison here - NOT likely in a normal election, but we 
have to be prepared with responses for such).
2.  If there are other possible CWs, repeat step 1 with latest winner 
and one of them.
3.  If there are other candidates latest winner has not been compared 
with, compare it with each of them.

4.  If winner wins each of these, it is CW.
5.  Winner and each who beat it in step 4 are cycle members.  Also, any 
candidate beating any of these is also a cycle member.


IF there is a CW, it should win - anything else is a complication, even 
if some math makes claims for the something else.
 Otherwise a simple cycle resolution should apply.  Simply canceling 
the smallest margin has been thought of - that value means minimum 
difference in vote counts between actual and what is assumed.
 Note that each cycle member would be CW if remaining cycle members 
were ignored.


As to voting:
 Equal ranks permitted.
 Write-ins permitted, and such a candidate wins with the same vote 
counts as if nominated.


As to clones, strategy, primaries, and runoffs - all seem best ignored, 
though only a nuisance if some are determined to involve such.


Okay, so let's see which *simple* cycle breaker provides as much as 
possible. To do that, we'll need to find out what simplicity means, and 
how to define "as much as possible".


That could be interesting in itself.

Ranked Pairs (or River) seems nice, but even it may be too complex. 
Sports usually employ Copeland (but modified); perhaps that could be 
used - but Copeland is indecisive. One can add Smith compliance by 
checking for a CW among the first n ranked in the output, then n-1, then 
n-2 and so on, but that might also be too complex.


Of course, if simplicity is paramount (i.e. we want very simple) we 
could just go with "break it by whoever beats the Plurality winner by 
the greatest amount" or plain old minmax (candidate with least worst 
defeat wins) or LR (greatest sum of victories wins).


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Matthew Welland
On Tuesday 10 November 2009 03:37:56 am Kristofer Munsterhjelm wrote:
> Matthew Welland wrote:
> > So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval? I'm
> > not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect results. I'm
> > interested in flaws that result in big problems such as those we see
> > with plurality and IRV.
>
> IMHO, it is that you need concurrent polling in order to consistently
> elect a good winner. If you don't have polling and thus don't know where
> to put the cutoff (between approve and not-approve), you'll face the
> Burr dilemma: If you prefer A > B > C, if you "approve" both A and B,
> you might get B instead of A, but if you "approve" only A, you might get
> C!

This seems to me to be a minor, not major, flaw.  Having to vote A & B to 
hedge your bets is not ideal but you might even be able to argue some 
benefits to it. A will see B as a serious threat and vice versa. They may 
make adjustments to their stands on issues to accommodate voters like you. 
Approval voting is enough to bring competition for votes back into the arena 
and I think it makes negative campaigning a very risky strategy. 

Also, again, your single vote is irrelevant. It is the aggregate of 
thousands or millions of votes that will make or break A vs. B. How many 
feel so strongly against A that they cannot vote for him or her?

The binary nature of approval is washed out by large numbers just as a class 
D amplifier can directly produce smooth analog waveforms out of a pure 1 or 0 
signal.

> Thus the kind of Approval that homes in on a good winner employs
> feedback. The method is no longer Approval alone, but Approval plus
> polling. That /can/ work (people approve {Nader, Gore} if Nader has
> fewer votes than Gore, so that Bush doesn't win from the split, but only
> approve either Nader or Gore if both are large), but why should we need
> to be burdened with the feedback?

Sure, in any real election there will be many dynamics at work. Feedback 
polls, debates etc. will all improve an election. Approval might benefit from 
feedback but I don't see why it becomes fatally flawed without it, only 
mildly flawed.

> Some, like Abd, argue that we always reason based on others' positions
> to know how much we can demand, and so that this is a feature rather
> than a bug. That doesn't quite sound right to me. In any event, if you
> want Approval + bargaining (which the feedback resolves to), make that
> claim. Approval alone, without feedback, will be subject to the flaws
> mentioned earlier, however.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 10:37 AM, Kristofer Munsterhjelm
 wrote:
> IMHO, it is that you need concurrent polling in order to consistently elect
> a good winner. If you don't have polling and thus don't know where to put
> the cutoff (between approve and not-approve), you'll face the Burr dilemma:
> If you prefer A > B > C, if you "approve" both A and B, you might get B
> instead of A, but if you "approve" only A, you might get C!

However, the same logic can be applied to plurality voting.  If people
had to vote blind, then the results would be even worse.

History with plurality has shown that it is reasonable to expect
people to know who the top-2 candidates are.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Juho
This method is also quite hand countable (unlike many other Condorcet  
methods). That was certainly an important feature in those days :-).  
It has some randomness in the results (when no Condorcet winner exists).


Here's another one. Elect the candidate that wins all others in  
pairwise comparisons. If there is no such candidate, elect the one  
that needs least number of additional votes to win all others.  (This  
is of course the famous minmax(margins) that I have promoted quite  
often.)


Juho


On Nov 10, 2009, at 12:57 PM, Jobst Heitzig wrote:


Dear Matthew,

you wrote:

Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.

  1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
 how they work in one or two sentences.


Well, here's a very simple "Condorcet" system which can easily be
explained in two sentences:

1. Let voters vote on candidate pairs, successively replacing the  
loser

with a different candidate, in a random order of candidates.
2. As soon as all candidates have been included, the winner of the  
last

pair is declared the overall winner.

This system is arguably the earliest example of a "Condorcet"  
system. It
was devised by Ramon Llull in the 13th century and was successfully  
used
for elections in monastaries. It is easily understood by the common  
man

since it resembles a procedure frequently used in child play.

Yours, Jobst


Matthew Welland schrieb:

Thanks all for the discussion and pointers. I still can't concretely
conclude anything yet but here are some rambling and random thoughts
based on what was said and my prior experiences.

Plurality

  1. Leads to two lowest common denominator parties which are not
 accountable to the voters. This conclusion supported by real  
world

 observation.
  2. Feels right to the non-critical mind, "one man, one vote"
  3. Very fast at the polls

Approval

  1. Encourages participation of minor parties and thus should keep  
the

 big guys paying attention to a wider base.
  2. Almost zero marginal implementation cost. Hanging chads count  
just

 fine :)
  3. Understandable by anyone but feels wrong at first "not fair, you
 get more than one vote".
  4. Apparently has a terrible flaw but no one seems to be able to
 articulate it in layman terms. No real world experience  
available

 to illustrate the problem. Here is where I need to learn more.
 Data provided to date is unconvincing to me.
  5. Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate
 between "I like", "I like a lot" etc. (note: this seems like
 perfectionism to me. Large numbers of voters and opinions all  
over

 the bell curve should make individual expression at the greater
 level of granularity irrelevant.)
  6. Very fast at the polls. Pick yer favorites and head home for  
beer

 and telly.

Range

  1. Can break the vicious cycle of plurality
  2. Not voting for someone at all can have a strong influence on
 election outcome. This is very non-intuitive and would take some
 getting used to.
  3. Allows for nuanced voting.
  4. Pain in the ass at the polls (relatively speaking). You can't
 safely disregard the candidates you don't care about so you  
*have*

 to assign everyone a ranking, possibly addressable by defaulting
 to zero for all candidates? This is considered a feature and I
 agree it has merit. But in reality it is a deal breaker for joe
 six pack and co. (and for lazy sobs like me).

IRV

  1. Demonstrably broken. 'nuff said.

Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.

  1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
 how they work in one or two sentences.
  2. Technically superior to other systems.
  3. Not clear what problem with approval they would solve. Unless  
you
 are a perfectionist and insist that individuals express  
nuances of

 opinion...

Some time ago I put together a site (primitive and unfinished[i]) to
promote approval voting and in the process I spent a lot of time  
trying

different systems on the web and repeatedly testing my own site. I
noticed some interesting things from all that playing around.

  1. It was very uncomfortable to go back to plurality after trying
 other systems. It "feels" unfair and broken.
  2. It was very tedious voting in any of the ranking systems.
  3. Approval felt boring but good.

I have checked in on this list now and then and I admit I don't  
have the

time or skills to follow all the arguments but it strikes me that
approval voting is good enough to break the deadlock, at least in US
politics and that it doesn't have any major flaws. The very
understandable desire to be able to articulate in a finer grained  
way in
your vote is perfectionism. With millions of voters, for every  
person on
the fence about a particular candidate there will be some to either  
side

who will essentially make or break the vote

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Robert,

you wrote:
> Round Robin tournament, Ranked Ballot:  The contestant who wins in a
> single match is the candidate who is preferred over the other in more
> ballots.  The candidate who is elected to office is the contestant who
> loses to no one in the round robin tournament.
> 
> that's two sentences and two labels.

But it's incomplete as well...

Yours, Jobst

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Matthew,

you wrote:
> Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
>
>1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
>   how they work in one or two sentences.

Well, here's a very simple "Condorcet" system which can easily be
explained in two sentences:

1. Let voters vote on candidate pairs, successively replacing the loser
with a different candidate, in a random order of candidates.
2. As soon as all candidates have been included, the winner of the last
pair is declared the overall winner.

This system is arguably the earliest example of a "Condorcet" system. It
was devised by Ramon Llull in the 13th century and was successfully used
for elections in monastaries. It is easily understood by the common man
since it resembles a procedure frequently used in child play.

Yours, Jobst


Matthew Welland schrieb:
> Thanks all for the discussion and pointers. I still can't concretely
> conclude anything yet but here are some rambling and random thoughts
> based on what was said and my prior experiences.
> 
> Plurality
> 
>1. Leads to two lowest common denominator parties which are not
>   accountable to the voters. This conclusion supported by real world
>   observation.
>2. Feels right to the non-critical mind, "one man, one vote"
>3. Very fast at the polls
> 
> Approval
> 
>1. Encourages participation of minor parties and thus should keep the
>   big guys paying attention to a wider base.
>2. Almost zero marginal implementation cost. Hanging chads count just
>   fine :)
>3. Understandable by anyone but feels wrong at first "not fair, you
>   get more than one vote".
>4. Apparently has a terrible flaw but no one seems to be able to
>   articulate it in layman terms. No real world experience available
>   to illustrate the problem. Here is where I need to learn more.
>   Data provided to date is unconvincing to me.
>5. Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate
>   between "I like", "I like a lot" etc. (note: this seems like
>   perfectionism to me. Large numbers of voters and opinions all over
>   the bell curve should make individual expression at the greater
>   level of granularity irrelevant.)
>6. Very fast at the polls. Pick yer favorites and head home for beer
>   and telly.
> 
> Range
> 
>1. Can break the vicious cycle of plurality
>2. Not voting for someone at all can have a strong influence on
>   election outcome. This is very non-intuitive and would take some
>   getting used to.
>3. Allows for nuanced voting.
>4. Pain in the ass at the polls (relatively speaking). You can't
>   safely disregard the candidates you don't care about so you *have*
>   to assign everyone a ranking, possibly addressable by defaulting
>   to zero for all candidates? This is considered a feature and I
>   agree it has merit. But in reality it is a deal breaker for joe
>   six pack and co. (and for lazy sobs like me).
> 
> IRV
> 
>1. Demonstrably broken. 'nuff said.
> 
> Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
> 
>1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
>   how they work in one or two sentences.
>2. Technically superior to other systems.
>3. Not clear what problem with approval they would solve. Unless you
>   are a perfectionist and insist that individuals express nuances of
>   opinion... 
> 
> Some time ago I put together a site (primitive and unfinished[i]) to
> promote approval voting and in the process I spent a lot of time trying
> different systems on the web and repeatedly testing my own site. I
> noticed some interesting things from all that playing around.
> 
>1. It was very uncomfortable to go back to plurality after trying
>   other systems. It "feels" unfair and broken.
>2. It was very tedious voting in any of the ranking systems.
>3. Approval felt boring but good. 
> 
> I have checked in on this list now and then and I admit I don't have the
> time or skills to follow all the arguments but it strikes me that
> approval voting is good enough to break the deadlock, at least in US
> politics and that it doesn't have any major flaws. The very
> understandable desire to be able to articulate in a finer grained way in
> your vote is perfectionism. With millions of voters, for every person on
> the fence about a particular candidate there will be some to either side
> who will essentially make or break the vote. If you are on the fence,
> approve or disapprove, it won't matter.
> 
> So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval? I'm
> not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect results. I'm
> interested in flaws that result in big problems such as those we see
> with plurality and IRV.
> 
> 
> [i] www.approvalvote.org
> 
> 
> 
> -

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval and range voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Kristofer Munsterhjelm

Matthew Welland wrote:

So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval? I'm 
not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect results. I'm 
interested in flaws that result in big problems such as those we see 
with plurality and IRV.


IMHO, it is that you need concurrent polling in order to consistently 
elect a good winner. If you don't have polling and thus don't know where 
to put the cutoff (between approve and not-approve), you'll face the 
Burr dilemma: If you prefer A > B > C, if you "approve" both A and B, 
you might get B instead of A, but if you "approve" only A, you might get C!


Thus the kind of Approval that homes in on a good winner employs 
feedback. The method is no longer Approval alone, but Approval plus 
polling. That /can/ work (people approve {Nader, Gore} if Nader has 
fewer votes than Gore, so that Bush doesn't win from the split, but only 
approve either Nader or Gore if both are large), but why should we need 
to be burdened with the feedback?


Some, like Abd, argue that we always reason based on others' positions 
to know how much we can demand, and so that this is a feature rather 
than a bug. That doesn't quite sound right to me. In any event, if you 
want Approval + bargaining (which the feedback resolves to), make that 
claim. Approval alone, without feedback, will be subject to the flaws 
mentioned earlier, however.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 8:18 AM, robert bristow-johnson
 wrote:
> i will say this: even though it is prohibited in the present IRV that
> Burlington VT has, there is no reason that ties should not be allowed in any
> ranked ballot.

It is unclear how this should work with IRV.

My personal preference is that both votes would count at full
strength.  The other possibility is that they are divided equally
between all remaining candidates.

In both cases, the count is more difficult.

> is that putting it in an accessible context?  so then with Approval voting,
> for sure this grandma marks "X" by her grandson's name.  but does she or
> doesn't she Approve her good ol' incumbent?  Approval doesn't let you mark
> it "Approve except in the race with my top choice."

However, if you know who the top-2 are, then this isn't a major problem.

The point with approval is that it tends to converge to a condorcet
winner, or a candidate who is almost as good.

It might even be better at finding honest condorcet winners than an
actual condorcet method, assuming that the voters vote tactically in
both cases.

> i mean isn't that the essential flaw?  e.g. the flaw with the Electoral
> College is that sometimes it elects the wrong candidate.  it does pretty
> good when it selects the same winner as the popular vote, but when it
> disagrees with the popular vote it *never* creates more legitimacy or
> confidence in the election results.  so then why have it?  what good is it?

It would have probably been better if they set it up so the college
actually meets, but then add a requirement that the majority of the
electors must agree.

If combined with PR at the state level when electing electors, then a
candidate who has the support of the majority of the population should
end up winnng.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Juho

On Nov 10, 2009, at 6:48 AM, Matthew Welland wrote:

Thanks all for the discussion and pointers. I still can't concretely  
conclude anything yet but here are some rambling and random thoughts  
based on what was said and my prior experiences.


Plurality
Leads to two lowest common denominator parties which are not  
accountable to the voters. This conclusion supported by real world  
observation.
Use of single winner districts has this tendency in general. The other  
single winner methods below give some more space to third parties but  
if you want to get rid of favouring the major parties and get  
proportional representation of all the parties/interest groups then  
some proportional multi winner methods method could be used.



Feels right to the non-critical mind, "one man, one vote"
Very fast at the polls
Approval
Encourages participation of minor parties and thus should keep the  
big guys paying attention to a wider base.
Almost zero marginal implementation cost. Hanging chads count just  
fine :)
Understandable by anyone but feels wrong at first "not fair, you get  
more than one vote".
Apparently has a terrible flaw but no one seems to be able to  
articulate it in layman terms. No real world experience available to  
illustrate the problem. Here is where I need to learn more. Data  
provided to date is unconvincing to me.
Here's one example. We have left and right wings with approximately  
50%-50% support. Left wing has two candidates (L1, L2). Most right  
wing voters approve only the right wing candidate (R). Some left wing  
candidates approve both leftist candidates but some approve only one  
of them. Right wing candidate wins.


In order to avoid this problem left wing might recommend all its  
supporters to approve both left wing candidates. If they do so left  
wing will not have the above mentioned problem of vote splitting but  
on the other hand L1 and L2 will get the same number of votes since  
nobody can indicate if L1 is better than L2 or the other way around.  
Choice between L1 and L2 is quite random since the decision will be  
left to those left wing voters who don't follow the recommended  
strategy and to those right wing voters who approve also one of the  
left wing candidates.


In this example the problem thus is that voters can not express at the  
same time both that left/right wing is better and that one of the  
candidates of that wing is better than some others of them. This  
problem may lead to interest within the left wing to nominate only one  
candidate (=no spoilers, no leftist third parties) and we might be  
close to the plurality related problems again. Approval may work in  
this case quite well as long as the third party is small and all its  
voters understand that they should approve also one of the major  
parties (left), but when the support of that third candidate grows  
things become more complicated.


Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate between  
"I like", "I like a lot" etc.  (note: this seems like perfectionism  
to me. Large numbers of  voters and opinions all over the bell curve  
should make individual expression at the greater level of  
granularity irrelevant.)
Out of the discussed methods Range is the only one that can express  
"like"/"like a lot". But it has its own problems (partly due to this  
property).


The example above tries to demonstrate that while large number of  
sincere Approval votes might statistically lead to a good result there  
is the risk that the votes will be not as well in balance (for  
strategy and candidate positioning related reasons). I think it is a  
general assumption that in Approval voters would not vote sincerely in  
th sense that they would approve those candidates that they consider  
"approvable" but they would follow strategy "approve part of the  
leaders (likely winners) and candidates that you prefer to them".


Very fast at the polls. Pick yer favorites and head home for beer  
and telly.

Range
Can break the vicious cycle of plurality
I didn't understand this. (If this is about the two party dominance I  
commented already above.)


Not voting for someone at all can have a strong influence on  
election outcome. This is very non-intuitive and would take some  
getting used to.

Allows for nuanced voting.
This is the benefit of Range. The related problem is that while this  
works well in non-competitive elections (e.g. polls, olympics with  
neutral judges) in competitive ones (e.g. political elections) voters  
have an incentive to exaggerate. This may lead to Approval-like  
behaviour where most voters give min and max points to most  
candidates. In that case Range would be very much like Approval.)


Pain in the ass at the polls (relatively speaking). You can't safely  
disregard the candidates you don't care about so you *have* to  
assign everyone a ranking, possibly addressable by defaulting to  
zero for all candidates? This is considered a feature and I a

Re: [EM] NESD and NESD* properties of a single-winner voting method

2009-11-10 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Warren,

I don't seem to understand the definition:
> A single-winner voting system "fails the NESD property" if, when every
> honest voter
> changes their vote to rank A top and B bottom (or B top and A bottom;
> depends on the voter which way she goes), leaving it otherwise
> unaltered, that always (except in very rare "exact tie" situations)
> causes A or B to win.

So, when all voters vote strategic (i.e. no voter is honest) and all
leave their ballots unchanged, then by definition "every honest voter
changes their vote to rank A top and B bottom" but of course no system
changes the result since no ballot is changed. Hence no system fails NESD.

What is the misunderstanding here?

Yours, Jobst

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 9, 2009, at 11:48 PM, Matthew Welland wrote:


Approval
Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate  
between "I like", "I like a lot" etc. (note: this seems like  
perfectionism to me. Large numbers of voters and opinions all over  
the bell curve should make individual expression at the greater  
level of granularity irrelevant.)


we should be able to express our preferences.  Approval reduces our  
metric of preference to a 1-bit number, a dichotomy.  i would like to  
have more bits in that number.



Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain how  
they work in one or two sentences.


Round Robin tournament, Ranked Ballot:  The contestant who wins in a  
single match is the candidate who is preferred over the other in more  
ballots.  The candidate who is elected to office is the contestant  
who loses to no one in the round robin tournament.


that's two sentences and two labels.


Technically superior to other systems.
Not clear what problem with approval they would solve. Unless you  
are a perfectionist and insist that individuals express nuances of  
opinion...


like which candidate they like better than the other candidate?


It was very tedious voting in any of the ranking systems.


it's tedious to decide who you like better?  who you would prefer if  
any two candidates are presented?


i will say this: even though it is prohibited in the present IRV that  
Burlington VT has, there is no reason that ties should not be allowed  
in any ranked ballot.


but i would agree it would be tedious to allocate preference points  
in Range.



So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval?


it's essentially like Plurality except you get to mark "X" on more  
than one candidate (like you do in multi-seat races).  i don't like  
it for multi-seat (in the state senate for the county i am in, all of  
our senators are elected from the county at large and there are 6 for  
my county) i always think i'm hurting a candidate i actively support  
by voting for another candidate from the same party that i approve  
of.  so then i mark "X" on only one candidate and, if enough people  
vote tactically like that, the election works like Plurality.  we  
want an improvement to Plurality because we might like a three or  
four party system (or 3 parties and viable independents).  we want to  
not have to consider the likelihood of wasting our vote by deciding  
who to Approve of.  we know we approve of the candidate we support,  
but it is a tactical decision to decide if you approve of a candidate  
you would normally approve of but is not the candidate that you have  
actively supported.


like what if you're a little old lady and you like and support you  
representative legislator for re-election.  and you support him over  
any likely candidate from the other party, and it might be close so  
you wanna feel like you helped him.  but your grandson that you  
cherish and are proud is running as an independent.  in fact you gave  
money to your grandson's campaign.  you support your grandson.  you  
don't know if he'll win or not, but you do not want to harm his  
chances.  you also don't want your good ol' incumbent you've always  
supported.  you want to make sure he doesn't lose to the other major  
party candidate.  but you wouldn't mind harming his chances if the  
race ended up between him and your grandson.


is that putting it in an accessible context?  so then with Approval  
voting, for sure this grandma marks "X" by her grandson's name.  but  
does she or doesn't she Approve her good ol' incumbent?  Approval  
doesn't let you mark it "Approve except in the race with my top choice."


I'm not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect  
results. I'm interested in flaws that result in big problems such  
as those we see with plurality and IRV.


how 'bout electing the wrong candidate?

i mean isn't that the essential flaw?  e.g. the flaw with the  
Electoral College is that sometimes it elects the wrong candidate.   
it does pretty good when it selects the same winner as the popular  
vote, but when it disagrees with the popular vote it *never* creates  
more legitimacy or confidence in the election results.  so then why  
have it?  what good is it?  it's either ineffective in "filtering"  
the popular vote or, when it *is* effective it makes matters worse.   
such a useful device!


with Condorcet you elect the candidate that, from the set of voters  
who have an opinion, is preferred by a majority of that set over any  
other candidate that you pick.


any winner of an election system that elects a candidate who is not  
the Condercet winner, has elected someone whom was rejected by the  
voting majority in favor of the Condorcet winner who wasn't elected.   
how is that congruent to the principle of democracy?  do we have  
elections and explicitly give it t