Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-13 Thread Terry Bouricius
Juho,

That was a good summary of IRV and Condorcet dynamics, and how their 
different weaknesses might be perceived by a citizenry.  I would like to 
add one more to your list. Different voting systems provide different 
incentives for candidate behavior and campaigns and thus voter 
information.

It has been argued that IRV tends to reduce negative campaigning, or makes 
campaigns overly bland (depending on your stance), because in addition to 
seeking first choices, candidates want to reach out to the supporters of 
other candidates. However, with Condorcet rules, it is possible for a 
candidate to win in a crowded field while receiving no first choices at 
all. There haven't been any real-world high-stakes elections to know for 
certain what effect this might have, but it would seem reasonable to 
expect candidates to avoid taking stands on controversial issues. 
Candidates would have an incentive to campaign just using a vacant theme 
of I promise to listen to YOU.

IRV seems to strike a reasonable balance between appealing for a strong 
core of supporters (the only requirement  in a plurality election with 
many candidates) and also developing broad appeal as an alternate choice. 
Condorcet tips towards the broad appeal alone. Condorcet would seem to 
encourage candidates to simply avoid alienating anybody, with little need 
to develop strong core support.

Thus, I wonder if Condorcet would dumb down campaigns to the point that 
voters would have even less information to evaluate candidates by.

A candidate who flew below the radar, such that no voters had any negative 
opinions of the person, just might win, even if finishing in last place in 
terms of first choices. I suspect the voters wouldn't be happy, even 
though that was the logical result of their ballots.

Terry Bouricius


- Original Message - 
From: Juho juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
To: EM Methods election-methods@lists.electorama.com
Sent: Wednesday, January 13, 2010 4:49 AM
Subject: Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality


On Jan 13, 2010, at 9:14 AM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

 it still is a curiosity to me how, historically, some leaders and
 proponents of election reform thunked up the idea to have a ranked-
 order ballot and then took that good idea and married it to the IRV
 protocol.  with the 200 year old Condorcet idea in existence, why
 would they do that?

1) The basic idea of IRV is in some sense natural. It is like a street
fight. The weakest players are regularly kicked out and they must give
up. I'm not saying that this would lead to good results but at least
this game is understandable to most people. Condorcet on the other
hand is more like a mathematical equation, and the details of the most
complex Condorcet variants may be too much for most voters. Here I'm
not saying that each voter (and not even each legislator) should
understand all the details of their voting system. The basic Condorcet
winner rule is however a simple enough principle to be explained to
all. But it may be that IRV is easier to market (to the legislators
and voters) from this point of view.

2) IRV is easier to count manually. Condorcet gets quite tedious to
count manually when the number of candidates and voters goes up. One
can use some tricks and shortcuts to speed up manual Condorcet
counting but IRV probably still beats it from this point of view.
Manual counting was the only way to count for a long time. Nowadays we
have computers and Condorcet tabulation should thus be no problem at
all (at least in places where computers are available). But this is
one reason why IRV has taken an early lead.

3) Large parties are typically in a key role when electoral reforms
are made. Election method experts within those parties may well have
found out that IRV tends to favour large parties. In addition to
trying to improve the society the best way they can, political parties
and people within them also tend to think that they are the ones who
are right and therefore the society would benefit of just them being
in power and getting more votes and more seats. The parties and their
representatives may also have other more selfish drivers behind their
interest to grab as large share of the power as possible :-). IRV thus
seems to maintain the power of the current strongest players better
than Condorcet does, and that may mean some bias towards IRV.

4) The problems of different election methods may appear only later. A
superficial understanding of IRV reveals first its positive features.
Like in Burlington the negative features may be understood only after
something negative happens in real elections. This applies also to
Condorcet. On that side one may however live in the hope that the
problems are rare enough and not easy to take advantage of so that
sincere voting and good results would be dominant. The point is that
IRV may be taken into use first (see other points above and below)
without understanding what problems might emerge later. And once it
has been taken 

Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-13 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 09:30 AM 1/13/2010, Terry Bouricius wrote:

Juho,

That was a good summary of IRV and Condorcet dynamics, and how their
different weaknesses might be perceived by a citizenry.  I would like to
add one more to your list. Different voting systems provide different
incentives for candidate behavior and campaigns and thus voter
information.


Indeed. And, in fact, this is one reason why Plurality *often* works 
much better than voting systems theorists would expect. And why 
Top-Two runoff does likewise (and even better).



It has been argued that IRV tends to reduce negative campaigning, or makes
campaigns overly bland (depending on your stance), because in addition to
seeking first choices, candidates want to reach out to the supporters of
other candidates.


It's been argued, for sure, but it's never been shown. What happens 
is that minor candidates with no hope do cooperate, but this 
incentive actually operates in the other direction for frontrunners, it seems.



However, with Condorcet rules, it is possible for a
candidate to win in a crowded field while receiving no first choices at
all.


Horrors! The candidate must really be bad, not even his or her mother 
votes for him, nor, indeed, does the candidate vote for himself or 
herself. I love these objections to voting methods that are based on 
utterly preposterous scenarios and expected knee-jerk responses to 
them. However, there is a legitimate point here, let's look at it.



There haven't been any real-world high-stakes elections to know for
certain what effect this might have, but it would seem reasonable to
expect candidates to avoid taking stands on controversial issues.


No, actually, at least not more than happens at present, where 
candidates try to avoid opposing the positions of large blocks of the 
public, and will attempt to present themselves differently to 
different interest groups, whenever they think they can get away with it.


The problem is that if you make yourself as bland as possible, you 
will lose your support base, those highly motivated to turn out and 
vote for you, work for your election as a volunteer, contribute funds 
to help you gain name recognition, etc. Fatal under most realistic 
voting systems, including Range, IRV, etc.



Candidates would have an incentive to campaign just using a vacant theme
of I promise to listen to YOU.


This is supposed to be new and only hypothetical? Sorry, Terry, I 
vote against candidates like that, and I think I'm not alone. I'll 
vote for a candidate whom I *actually trust* to listen to the 
constiuents, but not one who will not disclose his or her own 
position, because I can't trust the latter to vote intelligently and 
honestly. I don't want a rubber stamp in a legislature or office, I 
want someone who will not only listen, but make reasonably decent 
decisions as well, *after* having listened. Someone who won't tell me 
what they think, who avoids revealing personal positions, that's a 
very big negative for me.


Unfortunately, the present systems encourage exactly this.


IRV seems to strike a reasonable balance between appealing for a strong
core of supporters (the only requirement  in a plurality election with
many candidates) and also developing broad appeal as an alternate choice.


The problem is that a political expedient is mistaken for a desirable 
quality. And it's just plain bullshit. IRV favors extremists, not 
centrists. And not *real* centrists. I'm afraid that Terry is 
reasoning backwards. He's long worked for IRV, so he is making up 
reasons why it's a good method, a reasonable balance, even though 
anyone who has studied voting systems without this kind of activist 
bias knows that IRV performs far from reasonably.


To be clear, IRV does not favor serious extremists, but rather it is 
known to foster a two-party system, where any minor parties are mere 
appendages to a major party, and tend not to last. Terry focuses, in 
his comment, on individual candidates and how they will comport 
themselves, but probably most voters where parties are involved vote 
based on general party affiliation as as strong a factor as 
individual promises. As has been amply explained in this excellent 
video, http://www.teach12.com/ttcx/VotingFreeLecture.aspx, when there 
are two parties, they are strongly motivated to position themselves 
near the median voter, i.e., such that their range of supporters are 
to one side or the other of the median. Candidates, in primary 
elections or other internal party process, will be motivated to 
position themselves at the median of the party, so, thinking of this 
as a linear spectrum, at 25%; but this is modified by considerations 
of electability, so the push will be up, toward the middle. Then, 
once nominated, they will attempt to present themselves as even 
closer to the median.


A third party attempting to rise up in the middle gets slaughtered 
under IRV, through center squeeze, so that's next to impossible. IRV 
is only 

Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-13 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 01:19 PM 1/11/2010, Dave Ketchum wrote:

Plurality does that only when you vote for one who has a possibility
of winning.  Sometimes doing that prevents voting for the one you
prefer but expect to lose.


There is an aspect of this which is often overlooked, amidst 
assumptions about what voters prefer, and the 2000 presidential 
elector election in Florida showed this, in fact.


Everybody assumes that the Nader voters preferred Gore. But our study 
of Range voting, if it's shown us anything, it should show us that 
preference strength matters.


There is something that is quite obvious: the Nader voters didn't 
have enough preference strength between Gore and Bush to 
counterbalance their desire to express their preference for Nader.


Gore did not own those votes. I know of another interest group that 
also, I'm sure, shifted that election (it was so close that this 
could be said about many groups.) Muslims. There was a political 
action group that became active in 2000, for that election, and it 
approached the Gore campaign and asked to meet. They were blown off. 
The Bush campaign agreed to meet with them, and did. Now, which 
candidate did they support?


Lucky guess.

And it is a near certainty that this shifted enough votes to cause 
Gore to lose.


Preference strength. Very important to consider, much about voting 
systems makes no sense if all we think about is raw preference. Sure, 
in a head-on election, no other candidates, Gore would probably have 
won. Or not. Because the Nader message was that the choice between 
Gore and Bush did not matter. The Nader votes presumably agreed with 
that, and so we can't assume that they were prevented from voting 
for the one they preferred. They did so vote, and the result was 
presumably not unsatisfactory to them, not immediately anyway. Later, 
they found out whether Nader was right or not.


What would make us think that, with Range Voting, these voters 
wouldn't have bottom ranked both Gore and Bush?


Well, here's what: voters don't believe everything that their 
candidates tell them! But, still, each one of them made that choice 
on election day, as to which benefit was more important: showing 
support for Nader or the Green Party, or electing the preferred frontrunner.



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-13 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Jan 13, 2010, at 4:13 PM, Dave Ketchum wrote:

 On Jan 13, 2010, at 4:49 AM, Juho wrote:
 On Jan 13, 2010, at 9:14 AM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:
 
 it still is a curiosity to me how, historically, some leaders and 
 proponents of election reform thunked up the idea to have a ranked-order 
 ballot and then took that good idea and married it to the IRV protocol.  
 with the 200 year old Condorcet idea in existence, why would they do that?
 
 1) The basic idea of IRV is in some sense natural. It is like a street 
 fight. The weakest players are regularly kicked out and they must give up. 
 I'm not saying that this would lead to good results but at least this game 
 is understandable to most people. Condorcet on the other hand is more like a 
 mathematical equation, and the details of the most complex Condorcet 
 variants may be too much for most voters. Here I'm not saying that each 
 voter (and not even each legislator) should understand all the details of 
 their voting system. The basic Condorcet winner rule is however a simple 
 enough principle to be explained to all. But it may be that IRV is easier to 
 market (to the legislators and voters) from this point of view.
 
 When there is a CW in Condorcet, the CW has won in comparison with each other 
 candidate.  While a few may like X or Z enough better to have given such top 
 ranking, the fact that all the voters together prefer the CW over each other 
 should count, and does with Condorcet.

This seems to me to be a claim that is at best not self-evident (in the sense 
that Pareto or anti-dictatorship, say, are). While I'm not a fan of 
cardinal-utility voting systems, it seems entirely possible to make a utility 
argument or rationale against the *necessity* of electing the CW in all cases. 

That is, as a thought experiment, if we could somehow divine a workable 
electorate-wide utility function, it's at least arguable that the utility 
winner would legitimately trump the Condorcet winner, if different, while you 
couldn't make a similar argument wrt Pareto or dictatorship.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-13 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Jan 13, 2010, at 7:57 PM, Jonathan Lundell wrote:


On Jan 13, 2010, at 4:13 PM, Dave Ketchum wrote:


On Jan 13, 2010, at 4:49 AM, Juho wrote:

On Jan 13, 2010, at 9:14 AM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

it still is a curiosity to me how, historically, some leaders  
and proponents of election reform thunked up the idea to have a  
ranked-order ballot and then took that good idea and married it  
to the IRV protocol.  with the 200 year old Condorcet idea in  
existence, why would they do that?


1) The basic idea of IRV is in some sense natural. It is like a  
street fight. The weakest players are regularly kicked out and  
they must give up. I'm not saying that this would lead to good  
results but at least this game is understandable to most people.  
Condorcet on the other hand is more like a mathematical equation,  
and the details of the most complex Condorcet variants may be too  
much for most voters. Here I'm not saying that each voter (and  
not even each legislator) should understand all the details of  
their voting system. The basic Condorcet winner rule is however a  
simple enough principle to be explained to all. But it may be  
that IRV is easier to market (to the legislators and voters) from  
this point of view.


When there is a CW in Condorcet, the CW has won in comparison with  
each other candidate.  While a few may like X or Z enough better  
to have given such top ranking, the fact that all the voters  
together prefer the CW over each other should count, and does with  
Condorcet.


This seems to me to be a claim that is at best not self-evident (in  
the sense that Pareto or anti-dictatorship, say, are). While I'm  
not a fan of cardinal-utility voting systems, it seems entirely  
possible to make a utility argument or rationale against the  
*necessity* of electing the CW in all cases.


That is, as a thought experiment, if we could somehow divine a  
workable electorate-wide utility function, it's at least arguable  
that the utility winner would legitimately trump the Condorcet  
winner, if different, while you couldn't make a similar argument  
wrt Pareto or dictatorship.


how would you define that utility function metric in a democracy?   
would the candidates arm-wrestle?  take a written exam? flip a coin?   
what, other than majority preference of the electorate, can be such a  
metric in a democracy?


--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Two simple alternative voting methods that are fairer than IRV/STV and lack most IRV/STV flaws

2010-01-13 Thread Kathy Dopp
For those who need a system for substituting for a top-two runoff
election, I devised two fair methods to suggest to her that do not
have all the flaws of IRV/STV. (They both may've been devised by
others before me. My goal was to create a fair method without
IRV/STV's flaws which solve the problem of one person/one vote which
is necessary to get a voting method approved by US courts.
--

I believe that these
alternative systems (below) are also susceptible to the spoiler effect
of a nonwinning candidate changing who wins the election, although I
believe that there is a significant difference between the alternative
methods below and plurality and IRV where a majority opposed candidate
may win the election. In other words, I believe that the winner due to
a spoiler in the alternative method below is more likely to be a majority
favorite.

Both methods below solve the problem of every voter having a vote of
value one and, unlike IRV, treat all voters alike by counting all
their choices

So, here are two possible methods that are fairer than IRV/STV and
which are monotonic (unlike IRV/STV):

1. A rank choice ballot method:

Any number of candidates may be running for office and any number
allowed to be ranked on the ballot.

Voter ranks one candidate vote =1

Voter ranks two candidates, denominator is 1+2 = 3
votes are worth 2/3 and 1/3 for first and second ranked candidates

Voter ranks three candidates, denominator is 1+2+3=6
votes are worth 3/6 and 2/6 and 1/6 for 1st, 2nd, and 3rd choice respectively

Voter ranks four candidates, denominator is 1+2+3+4=10
votes are worth 4/10, 3/10, 2/10, and 1/10 for 1st, 2nd, and 3rd and
4th choice respectively

ETC. Just follow the same pattern



2. A point system where a total number of points per voter per contest
may be allocated by the voter to any of the candidates running for
office:

Two candidates running for office, give all voters 2+1=3 votes to
cast.  They may cast all three votes for one candidate or split the
votes any way between the two.

Three candidates running for office, give all voters 3+2+1=6 votes to
cast. They may cast all six votes for one candidate or split the votes
any way they like between the three.

Four candidates running for office, give all voters 4+3+2+1=10 votes
to cast. They may cast all ten votes for one candidate or split the
votes any way they like between the four.

Five candidates running for office, give all voters 5+4+3+2+1=15 votes
to cast. They may cast all 15 votes for one candidate or split the
votes any way they like.

The benefits of this system are that it:

a. gives the voters more flexibility than plan #1 above as far as
weighting the individual candidates

b. is easy to assure that all voters contribute 1 total vote during
the process by dividing each vote by the total number of votes allowed
for each voter for each contest.

It would, however, require educating each voter to make sure to use
all the points available in any one contest though.

The advantage of these two methods over IRV/STV include:

1. easy to count, precinct-summable (unlike IRV)

2. fair, treats all voters' votes equally by counting all choices of
each voter (unlike IRV)

3. gives each voter a total of one vote total over the entire vote
counting process satisfying the US courts (unlike IRV)

4. is monotonic -- preserves the right to cast a vote that has a
positive affect on a candidate's chances of winning (unlike IRV.)

5. Allows all voters to participate in all the rounds since these
methods require only one (1) round (unlike IRV)

6. can begin the counting immediately without waiting for all the
late-counted provisional and absentee ballots to be ready to count
(without fear of having to restart the entire process again from the
beginning unlike with IRV/STV)


--

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

-- 

Kathy Dopp

Town of Colonie, NY 12304
phone 518-952-4030
cell 518-505-0220

http://utahcountvotes.org
http://electionmathematics.org
http://kathydopp.com/serendipity/

Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting
http://electionmathematics.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf

Voters Have Reason to Worry
http://utahcountvotes.org/UT/UtahCountVotes-ThadHall-Response.pdf

Checking election outcome accuracy --- Post-election audit sampling
http://electionmathematics.org/em-audits/US/PEAuditSamplingMethods.pdf

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-13 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Jan 13, 2010, at 5:02 PM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:

 On Jan 13, 2010, at 7:57 PM, Jonathan Lundell wrote:
 
 On Jan 13, 2010, at 4:13 PM, Dave Ketchum wrote:
 
 On Jan 13, 2010, at 4:49 AM, Juho wrote:
 On Jan 13, 2010, at 9:14 AM, robert bristow-johnson wrote:
 
 it still is a curiosity to me how, historically, some leaders and 
 proponents of election reform thunked up the idea to have a ranked-order 
 ballot and then took that good idea and married it to the IRV protocol.  
 with the 200 year old Condorcet idea in existence, why would they do that?
 
 1) The basic idea of IRV is in some sense natural. It is like a street 
 fight. The weakest players are regularly kicked out and they must give up. 
 I'm not saying that this would lead to good results but at least this game 
 is understandable to most people. Condorcet on the other hand is more like 
 a mathematical equation, and the details of the most complex Condorcet 
 variants may be too much for most voters. Here I'm not saying that each 
 voter (and not even each legislator) should understand all the details of 
 their voting system. The basic Condorcet winner rule is however a simple 
 enough principle to be explained to all. But it may be that IRV is easier 
 to market (to the legislators and voters) from this point of view.
 
 When there is a CW in Condorcet, the CW has won in comparison with each 
 other candidate.  While a few may like X or Z enough better to have given 
 such top ranking, the fact that all the voters together prefer the CW over 
 each other should count, and does with Condorcet.
 
 This seems to me to be a claim that is at best not self-evident (in the 
 sense that Pareto or anti-dictatorship, say, are). While I'm not a fan of 
 cardinal-utility voting systems, it seems entirely possible to make a 
 utility argument or rationale against the *necessity* of electing the CW in 
 all cases.
 
 That is, as a thought experiment, if we could somehow divine a workable 
 electorate-wide utility function, it's at least arguable that the utility 
 winner would legitimately trump the Condorcet winner, if different, while 
 you couldn't make a similar argument wrt Pareto or dictatorship.
 
 how would you define that utility function metric in a democracy?  would 
 the candidates arm-wrestle?  take a written exam? flip a coin?  what, other 
 than majority preference of the electorate, can be such a metric in a 
 democracy?

I don't think you can, and that's a big problem for Range, it seem to me.

But we're talking about utility for the voter, not arm-strength of the 
candidates.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Two simple alternative voting methods that are fairer than IRV/STV and lack most IRV/STV flaws

2010-01-13 Thread Brian Olson
On Jan 13, 2010, at 8:06 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:
 1. A rank choice ballot method:
 
 Any number of candidates may be running for office and any number
 allowed to be ranked on the ballot.
 
 Voter ranks one candidate vote =1
 
 Voter ranks two candidates, denominator is 1+2 = 3
 votes are worth 2/3 and 1/3 for first and second ranked candidates
 
 Voter ranks three candidates, denominator is 1+2+3=6
 votes are worth 3/6 and 2/6 and 1/6 for 1st, 2nd, and 3rd choice respectively
 
 Voter ranks four candidates, denominator is 1+2+3+4=10
 votes are worth 4/10, 3/10, 2/10, and 1/10 for 1st, 2nd, and 3rd and
 4th choice respectively
 
 ETC. Just follow the same pattern

This sounds like a variation on Borda count, but with an incentive to vote on 
fewer candidates. With smaller and smaller votes as I give more information, I 
should vote for one _maybe_ two choices. Why would I want to give my favorite a 
4/10 vote when I could give them a 2/3 vote or a 1.0 vote? This is the wrong 
incentive. Giving more information on the ballot should be encouraged.

 2. A point system where a total number of points per voter per contest
 may be allocated by the voter to any of the candidates running for
 office:
 
 Two candidates running for office, give all voters 2+1=3 votes to
 cast.  They may cast all three votes for one candidate or split the
 votes any way between the two.
 
 Three candidates running for office, give all voters 3+2+1=6 votes to
 cast. They may cast all six votes for one candidate or split the votes
 any way they like between the three.
 
 Four candidates running for office, give all voters 4+3+2+1=10 votes
 to cast. They may cast all ten votes for one candidate or split the
 votes any way they like between the four.
 
 Five candidates running for office, give all voters 5+4+3+2+1=15 votes
 to cast. They may cast all 15 votes for one candidate or split the
 votes any way they like.

This is equivalent to any other normalized ratings ballot. People vote ratings, 
but they all have the same voting power, either by straight sum of ratings or 
by geometric distance or something.
In any system where the voter has to allocate the points themselves, there will 
be nasty strategic thinking going on to try and allocate the points best.
If I vote simply and honestly, allocating points in alignment with how I feel 
about candidates, points not in differential between the top two candidates are 
wasted.

Kathy, in my investigations of election methods, I started with straight rating 
summation as optimal, but normalized ratings as more fair, but then ran into 
the wasted-vote problem and settled on Instant Runoff Normalized Ratings ( 
http://bolson.org/voting/methods.html#IRNR ). Over the course of rounds of 
counting it reallocates your vote based on your original ballot to always be 
optimally applied to the choices available. Never mind the Instant Runoff 
part of the name, by using ratings ballots and considering the whole ballot at 
once, it's much better than the simplistic IRV. It's much less non-monotonic 
than IRV, and gets better answers in my simulations.

You can compare the relative non-monotonic areas in these election space plots:
http://bolson.org/voting/sim_one_seat/www/

http://bolson.org/voting/sim_one_seat/www/4a_IRV.png
http://bolson.org/voting/sim_one_seat/www/4a_IRNR.png
http://bolson.org/voting/sim_one_seat/www/4a_Condorcet.png


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-13 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 07:10 PM 1/11/2010, Dave Ketchum wrote:

The possible excitement tangles with the secrecy laws - reporting in a
manner that identifies how ANY ONE voter voted needs preventing
(needed protection of voters).


There is a problem with ranked ballots and true write-in votes: a 
voter may identify the ballot specifically and clearly. The voter 
writes in their own name. In last rank, that has practically no 
effect. With plurality, the write-in shows, but it then makes the 
ballot moot, generally. (If it's unique, it's moot!) Vote-coercers 
don't want the person to vote for themselves! And a mark in any other 
place than the write-in place invalidates the ballot, and any writing 
in the write-in -- any at all -- generally invalidates a vote for any 
other candidate.


Because Asset Voting shares this problem in a different way, my 
solution was to consider that true write-ins are not allowed. Rather, 
there is a candidate pamphlet that is printed with the name of all 
registered candidates. The registration fee is nominal, just enough 
to pay for a listing in the pamphlet with a unique name and a code to 
be used to vote for the candidate. There are no names on the ballot. 
The voter has to find the name (unless the voter is assisted, which 
is allowed often for people with physical difficulties). The ballot 
only has a number on it, marked in a way that would be difficult to 
specifically identify. With computer ballots, it's even easier. And 
there could be a look-up for the number so that the actual name of 
the candidate was displayed.


But it's still possible to identify ballots with very high 
probability. Perfect secrecy in voting is not possible to guarantee, 
for, usually, the risk comes from those with special access to 
ballots. I.e., incumbents. They can set up means to identify voters, 
easily, with that control. I'll note that in some democracies, each 
ballot is serialized on the back and this serial number is recorded 
with the original voting record. You can't tell who voted just by 
looking at the ballot, you'd have to also have list to the registry 
of votes made at the voting place. And when ballots are counted, this 
side is normally kept down.


So the protection that is practical and perhaps necessary is that it 
is kept *difficult* to identify a vote from a voter who does not want 
to be identified.


With fully-ranked ballots with enough candidates, it is also possible 
for a voter to vote, say, for a candidate in first preference and 
then use the remaining preferences to create a unique code, even if 
write-ins are not allowed. In San Francisco, one supervisor race had, 
what, 23 candidates on the ballot? Overvoting in lower ranks is moot 
in first rank and doesn't affect the first preference vote at all 
with IRV. So that's a code with 22 possibilities, even neglecting 
write-ins, for each of the ranking slots, and blanks can be used as 
well as part of the code. So there would be 23^22 possible codes. It 
would definitely be suspicious if many voters used more than a few 
double-votes. Still, what could they do about it? As it is, write-ins 
*must* be allowed in every election by the California constitution, 
and the exception for some runoff elections was a result of an 
argument that the runoff wasn't a separate election, it was merely 
part of the first one.


But that argument was totally stupid! Remember, the argument was that 
the winner *must* get a majority. A majority of votes! A majority of 
*what* votes? If the whole process is one election, it would have to 
be a majority of all the votes cast in the primary and runoff. But 
obviously, that's not it. Rather, it's a majority of votes in the 
runoff. It's a separate election, the only one that counts, if the 
first one didn't find a majority. All the votes cast in the first 
election are moot except for determining who is on the ballot. And 
thus the allowance for write-ins should have remained, and, if the 
method remained plurality, a plurality winner would have been allowed 
in the runoff. Simple. Don't run in a plurality runoff election 
unless as a write-in unless you are willing to risk a spoiler effect. 
You already know, probably, how you stand with the voters. And if I 
were a voter seeing a write-in candidacy, I'd want to know that not 
only do I prefer this write-in candidate, by a substantial margin, 
but also a plurality of voters prefer this candidate. I'd want to 
know, clearly, that there was a center squeeze effect in the primary.


Runoff voting is quite cool for minor parties, it allows them to 
express that first preference with reasonable sincerity, usually.


Give voters a better method in the primary, and there will be fewer 
runoffs and better results with sincere voting.




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Two simple alternative voting methods that are fairer than IRV/STV and lack most IRV/STV flaws

2010-01-13 Thread Kathy Dopp
On Wed, Jan 13, 2010 at 8:55 PM,
election-methods-requ...@lists.electorama.com wrote:
 Send Election-Methods mailing list submissions to
        election-meth...@lists.electorama.com

 To subscribe or unsubscribe via the World Wide Web, visit
        
 http://lists.electorama.com/listinfo.cgi/election-methods-electorama.com

 or, via email, send a message with subject or body 'help' to
        election-methods-requ...@lists.electorama.com
 Date: Wed, 13 Jan 2010 20:30:26 -0500
 From: Brian Olson b...@bolson.org
 To: Election Methods Mailing List election-meth...@electorama.com
 Subject: Re: [EM] Two simple alternative voting methods that are
        fairer than     IRV/STV and lack most IRV/STV flaws
 On Jan 13, 2010, at 8:06 PM, Kathy Dopp wrote:
 1. A rank choice ballot method:

 Any number of candidates may be running for office and any number
 allowed to be ranked on the ballot.

 Voter ranks one candidate vote =1

 Voter ranks two candidates, denominator is 1+2 = 3
 votes are worth 2/3 and 1/3 for first and second ranked candidates

 Voter ranks three candidates, denominator is 1+2+3=6
 votes are worth 3/6 and 2/6 and 1/6 for 1st, 2nd, and 3rd choice respectively

 Voter ranks four candidates, denominator is 1+2+3+4=10
 votes are worth 4/10, 3/10, 2/10, and 1/10 for 1st, 2nd, and 3rd and
 4th choice respectively

 ETC. Just follow the same pattern

 This sounds like a variation on Borda count, but with an incentive to vote on 
 fewer candidates.

Yes perhaps, but normalized to give a value of one in total to all
ballots since Borda was rejected by the MN Supreme court as violating
one-person/one-vote.

 With smaller and smaller votes as I give more information, I should vote for 
 one _maybe_ two choices. Why would I want to give my favorite a 4/10 vote 
 when I could give them a 2/3 vote or a 1.0 vote? This is the wrong incentive. 
 Giving more information on the ballot should be encouraged.

Yes. Probably. It depends on how attached to your first choice you are.


 2. A point system where a total number of points per voter per contest
 may be allocated by the voter to any of the candidates running for
 office:

 Two candidates running for office, give all voters 2+1=3 votes to
 cast.  They may cast all three votes for one candidate or split the
 votes any way between the two.

 Three candidates running for office, give all voters 3+2+1=6 votes to
 cast. They may cast all six votes for one candidate or split the votes
 any way they like between the three.

 Four candidates running for office, give all voters 4+3+2+1=10 votes
 to cast. They may cast all ten votes for one candidate or split the
 votes any way they like between the four.

 Five candidates running for office, give all voters 5+4+3+2+1=15 votes
 to cast. They may cast all 15 votes for one candidate or split the
 votes any way they like.


 This is equivalent to any other normalized ratings ballot. People vote 
 ratings, but they all have the same voting power, either by straight sum of 
 ratings or by geometric distance or something.

Yes. It just standardizes the number of points and makes it seem fair
(an equal number of points) to voters who would not understand the
normalization process if all voters were allowed to cast a different
number of votes initially.  It also simplifies the calculation and
makes it much easier for the public to check.

 In any system where the voter has to allocate the points themselves, there 
 will be nasty strategic thinking going on to try and allocate the points best.
 If I vote simply and honestly, allocating points in alignment with how I feel 
 about candidates, points not in differential between the top two candidates 
 are wasted.

That's a good argument for the first method I suggested since all the
voter has to do is rank as many candidates as they feel like ranking,
but knowing that the 2nd and 3rd, etc. choices will add points that
count against the voter's 1st choice, and may therefore cause the 2nd
or 3rd choice to win instead being more popular with other voters.


 Kathy, in my investigations of election methods, I started with straight 
 rating summation as optimal, but normalized ratings as more fair, but then 
 ran into the wasted-vote problem and settled on Instant Runoff Normalized 
 Ratings ( http://bolson.org/voting/methods.html#IRNR ).

I agree that that method is much fairer than IRV/STV but it is too
complex to count and is not precinct-summable which raises other
election administration problems and also auditability problems, so it
is not a method I'd choose even though it is far better than the
typical IRV/STV.

 Over the course of rounds of counting it reallocates your vote based on your 
 original ballot to always be optimally applied to the choices available. 
 Never mind the Instant Runoff part of the name, by using ratings ballots 
 and considering the whole ballot at once, it's much better than the 
 simplistic IRV. It's much less non-monotonic than IRV, and gets better 
 

Re: [EM] IRV vs Plurality

2010-01-13 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 02:14 AM 1/13/2010, robert bristow-johnson wrote:


For instance in Aspen CO's most recent
IRV election, if 75 *fewer* voters had voted for one candidate that
candidate would have won.


that's a pathology (and sounds like a worse one than Burlington VT in
2009).  so let's get rid of it.  but *throwing* *away* information by
reverting to the single-vote ballot from the ranked ballot doesn't
make things better.  it makes it worse for the majority.


The alternative generally is not pure plurality, it's some kind of 
runoff voting. The candidate must gain a certain plurality or a 
majority in the primary, or a runoff is held. The method for 
determining who gets on the runoff ballot is not necessarily the 
best; IRV flops because it's possible that the majority preference 
(pairwise) is third or even lower in first rank, and is eliminated.


In the real examples I've seen, by the way, the majority preference 
was only a little behind the runner-up when eliminated. FairVote, in 
defending IRV against the center squeeze objection, makes it seem 
like the majority preference doesn't have core support. Really, and 
usually, the core support is roughly equivalent to the runner-up. 
And core support and Later-No-Harm are a Bad Idea, for they reward 
partisan thinking, allowing compromise only after the first choice is 
dead, eliminated, impossible.


Now, suppose I have two choices: I can run my ballot as IRV, in which 
case my second choice doesn't count until my first choice is actually 
taken out back and shot, er, my first choice is eliminated, or I can 
run by ballot as Bucklin, in which case my first choice is the only 
one counted in the first round, but my lower ranked choices are 
counted in the round I've indicated. I could even leave an 
intermediate rank empty, so my second choice is only counted in the 
final round. Or second choices, plural. (Traditional Duluth Bucklin 
allowed multiple votes in the last rank but not in earlier ones; I'd 
allow them in all ranks, no reason not to, and it makes the method 
more flexible, my guess it would slightly improve result quality, but 
it would definitely decrease spoiled ballots.)


The voter wanting Later No Harm protection would indicate on the 
ballot that it's an IRV ballot. This means that lower-ranked votes on 
that ballot would never count against the election of a higher-ranked 
candidate. They would not be counted until the candidate were 
eliminated. So the ballot would be run as a Bucklin ballot, with only 
one vote on it, the first rank. Then, if no Bucklin majority appeared 
(which is a true majority), there would be an instant runoff. The 
votes from all ranks on Bucklin ballots would stand. They would not 
be eliminated. But the ballots from the IRV voters would be treated 
as IRV ballots, and the candidate in first preference on them, with 
the lowest vote count so far, would have those votes struck, in 
effect, and the highest ranked votes standing would be counted. Note 
that if all voters vote IRV ballots, the election becomes pure IRV 
and if all voters vote Bucklin ballots, the election becomes pure Bucklin.


In all cases, single winner election, the only vote on a ballot that 
actually counts is a vote for the winner. All other votes are moot, 
in the end, they could be struck and the result would not change.


If the Later No Harm argument were truly valid, surely most voters 
would want to vote that way. But I sure wouldn't, because preventing 
harm to my candidate from my second rank vote also prevents help 
for my candidate from other voters who would vote for my favorite in 
second rank.


Rather, to understand the situation, we should encourage people to 
look at repeated balloting as a very old and justly respected voting 
method. This is repeated balloting with no eliminations, it provides 
complete freedom to the voters, they can vote for their favorite 
without regard for what others think as long as they want. But if 
they keep doing that, and many keep doing that, the election won't 
resolve and they have to keep casting ballots, it's a form of 
selfishness that reaches a natural boundary. So what happens, in 
effect, is that voters lower their expectations and accept a result 
that they personally consider less than idea, but adequate and 
necessary in order to complete the election with a majority.


It's totally obvious that this method could be made a bit more 
efficient by allowing multiple approvals. Repeated approval elections 
with no eliminations is probably somewhat more efficient than 
repeated elections allowing only a vote for one candidate, as voters 
will begin, perhaps, with some level of minor compromise, and they 
can then lower the approval cutoff as necessary. Or if they have a 
clear favorite, that's how they start until they have more 
information about what is practical.


Bucklin simulates repeated balloting with a declining approval 
cutoff. An initial single preference vote is complemented by an