[EM] Most Tolerable or Better

2011-06-29 Thread fsimmons
This is a three slot method. The two non-blank choices are tolerable and
better. 

Elect the alternative that is marked tolerable or better on the greatest number
of ballots.

If there is a tie, then elect the tied alternative that is marked better on the
greatest number of ballots.

If a tie persists after this step, then break it by random ballot.

This method should be understood as a good faith attempt to minimize the number
of voters that have to live with an outcome that is intolerable for them, so
that other preference considerations are secondary.

Of course, a statistically confident, determined majority of 51% can still force
its will on the rest of the voters by bullet voting instead of admitting that
some other alternatives would be tolerable; this method is not a fool proof
solution of tyranny of the majority.

You might consider this as a cross-walk version of Approval, because most of the
time there won't be a tie to be broken, just like most of the time pushing the
walk button is just for psychological benefit; it doesn't make the light change
any faster.

Beyond the psychological value the tolerable versus better distinction can
reveal valuable information after the election.

But there is also a more important (but subtle) benefit of having a separate tie
breaker level; from an instrumental point of view, your vote has only symbolic
value anyway when there is no chance of a tie.  

Voting power is defined as the probability that your vote will be pivotal in the
outcome.  It is pivotal precisely when it either makes or breaks a tie.  If a
tie is made or broken by one vote, then everybody who voted is glad that they
did (unless their vote broke the tie in an unintended direction as it could
under a non-monotonic method).  Otherwise, most people recognize that no
individual vote, including theirs, made any difference other than symbolic, for
example as a mandate for the winner or show of support for a loser.

The best case would be when there are two or more alternatives that are
tolerable (or better) to everybody, which is not out of the question in
situations where the voters are sufficiently like minded.  In that case the tie
breaker chooses from among these consensus candidates.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] Further SODA refinement

2011-06-29 Thread Jameson Quinn
Problem: Near-clones A1 and A2 have both put each other at the top of
their delegation order. Their totals, combined, constitute a majority, but
either one alone would be beaten by B. Both insist that the other one
delegate, threatening to refuse to delegate. It's a game of chicken, and
the more symmetrical the situation is, the more likely that negotiations
fail. Even if they succeed, the winner may simply be whichever is more
intransigent, not a good result.

Solution: When choosing whether to delegate, candidates do so not
simultaneously but sequentially, in order from most delegable ballots to
least delegable ballots. This means that candidates with fewer delegable
votes are unable to make ultimatums to candidates with more delegable
votes.

Three sub-scenarios:

Assume all votes are delegable (for simplicity). Assume WLOG that A1 is the
one with more votes. Note that if this is a 1-dimensional ideological
spectrum, that is likely to mean that A2 is the squeezed Condorcet winner.

Scenario 1: B prefers A1.
B does not delegate, hoping that A1 and A2 will be unable to negotiate. A1
does not delegate, as an ultimatum to A2. A2 is strategically forced to
delegate if they don't want B to win.

Scenario 2: B prefers A2.
B delegates to A2, knowing that otherwise the equilibrium is an A1 win. A1
and A2 do not delegate. A2 wins. Especially if the voters are ideologically
divided, we can assume that A2 was the CW.

Scenario 3: B prefers neither, or marginally prefers A2 but decides not to
delegate (hoping for a win).
Results are the same as scenario 1. This is perhaps a good center-squeeze
scenario. That is, if there's an approximate 1-dimensional spectrum, chances
are that A2 is the centrist candidate and thus the ideological CW.
However, B's choice not to delegate to A2 reflects on A2's quality. Perhaps
SODA, here, has avoided a mushy middle win which a Condorcet system would
have fallen into.

Note: If B adopts a worse is better attitude, trying to elect the one of
A1 or A2 who will be a weaker opponent in the next election, then they
probably can. However, they must do so openly, so hopefully voters will see
through whatever they use as a rationalization and punish them for their
selfish actions. It is essentially impossible for a good voting system to do
any more than that to avoid such anti-patriotic behavior.



Note: I got essentially no responses to my last message refining SODA (where
I suggested a 5% minimum cutoff to be able to actively delegate votes, with
votes below that delegated automatically). Is that just because nobody had
anything to add, or are people not interested in discussing this system? If
it's the latter, I'd love to know why not.

JQ

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Most Tolerable or Better

2011-06-29 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Jun 29, 2011, at 3:52 PM, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:

This is a three slot method. The two non-blank choices are  
tolerable and

better.

Elect the alternative that is marked tolerable or better on the  
greatest number

of ballots.

If there is a tie, then elect the tied alternative that is marked  
better on the

greatest number of ballots.



this seems to me to be a sorta backward-working Bucklin.  if you  
replace blank with 3rd-choice, tolerable with 2nd-choice, and  
better with 1st-choice, it's a basic ranked ballot like for IRV or  
Condorcet or Borda or Bucklin.  it's a lot like Bucklin except Bucklin  
looks first at only the 1st-choice rankings (and a tie is far less  
likely than a non-majority, which is what Bucklin uses to trigger  
looking at the second-round count of 1st and 2nd rankings).


it's not Bucklin, but it reminds me of Bucklin.

--

r b-j  r...@audioimagination.com

Imagination is more important than knowledge.





Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] SODA in a de-facto two-party system

2011-06-29 Thread fsimmons

 Having considered these issues, there are two refinements I'd
 make to SODA:

 - If, after voting, one candidate has an absolute majority OR
 is the only
 possible winner, they win immediately.

 Sure, I can think an argument for why SODA should elect someone
 who's not
 the initial majority winner. But I don't relish the thought of
 having to
 make that argument, either with a politician or with a regular
 voter. And in
 reality, a majority winner is the correct winner in more than
 95% of the
 cases, so let's just save the time and admit that immediately.


 - If, after voting, one candidate has fewer than 5% of the
 votes, their
 votes are automatically delegated to the first candidate on
 their preference
 list who has more than 5% (if any). The receiving candidate
 may delegate
 them in turn, only if the result thereby obtained or
 encouraged is
 consistent with the preference order of the original
 candidate. (That means
 that if minor A's order is B,C,D,E,F, and D is the first one
 of those with
 more than 5%, and D's order is C,F,X, E,..., then D may
 delegate these votes
 to C, or to C and F if F is already leading E by a greater
 margin than the
 number of votes in question, or to C, F, and E if D is
 delegating their own
 votes to X as well.)

 This appears to be a bigger compromise of principle than the
 above. But
 consider the kingmaker case: in a basically 50/50 split, some
 tiny party
 has the balance of votes, and manages to extract concessions far
 bigger than
 their base of support justifies, just in order to [not] delegate those
 votes. I think that's unjust, and this rule would prevent it.

 I think that 5% is a good cutoff here; that's tens of millions
 of voters,
 and enough to deserve a voice. It shouldn't be too high, because
 this rule
 is effectively taking power away from voters; that's only
 justified if the
 faction is so small that the power is not legitimate, and so
 it's better to
 err a bit on the small side if anything. But under 5% - that is,
 under 10%
 of the winning coalition - doesn't deserve kingmaker power.

 JQ

I like it! Don't be impatient; some of us don't have time to read these things
every day.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Most Tolerable or Better

2011-06-29 Thread fsimmons
Yes, you can think of it as upside down MCA, which is a three slot version of
Bucklin.

- Original Message -
From: robert bristow-johnson


 On Jun 29, 2011, at 3:52 PM, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:

  This is a three slot method. The two non-blank choices are
  tolerable and
  better.
 
  Elect the alternative that is marked tolerable or better on
 the
  greatest number
  of ballots.
 
  If there is a tie, then elect the tied alternative that is
 marked
  better on the
  greatest number of ballots.
 

 this seems to me to be a sorta backward-working Bucklin. if you

 replace blank with 3rd-choice, tolerable with 2nd-choice, and
 better with 1st-choice, it's a basic ranked ballot like for
 IRV or
 Condorcet or Borda or Bucklin. it's a lot like Bucklin except
 Bucklin
 looks first at only the 1st-choice rankings (and a tie is far
 less
 likely than a non-majority, which is what Bucklin uses to
 trigger
 looking at the second-round count of 1st and 2nd rankings).

 it's not Bucklin, but it reminds me of Bucklin.

 --

 r b-j r...@audioimagination.com

 Imagination is more important than knowledge.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Most Tolerable or Better

2011-06-29 Thread fsimmons
What about strategy for Most Tolerable of Better?

In ordinary Approval, the strategy S that maximizes the probability of being
pivotal (in the desired direction) is to approve alternative X if and only if X
is less likely to be tied with an alternative that you prefer over X than it is
with an alternative that you like less than X.

When most of the winning probability is concentrated in only two alternatives,
this strategy reduces to Rob LeGrand's strategy A:  put your approval cutoff
adjacent to the alternative most likely to win on the side of the alternative
with the next greatest winning probability.

Suppose that there are two lesser evils X and Y running about even in winning
probability with the candidate Z that you detest the most (anybody but Z).  Do
you approve both lesser evils X and Y, or just the one X that that you have a
slight preference for?

Under ordinary approval, this is a difficult question, since the probabilities
involved are apt to be pretty rough estimates, and it may be that your preferred
compromise X is just short of the necessary support to beat Z.

[If you use the strategy S that maximizes the probability of being pivotal (in
the desired direction), then you approve Y if and only if Z has a greater
probability of winning than X.  But these two probabilities are not precisely
known.]

Under Most Tolerable or Better you can mark X and Y as better and tolerable,
respectively, while leaving Z at the default bottom.  This maximizes the chance
that Z will not win, and contributes to X over Y in the not too unlikely case
that X and Y end up with the same tolerable or better score ahead of Z.

You might say that these ties are too unlikely to matter, but where there is no
tie or near tie, your ballot cannot be pivotal anyway.




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Condorcet Jury Theorem

2011-06-29 Thread Greg Nisbet
my premise, poorly articulated, but my premise nonetheless is that an
adaptive voting method that takes into account voters' previous behavior
may be able to outperform OMOV in the long run on average.

P=NP is only meant to evoke the relevant properties of objective truth i.e.
that it is true or false and that people don't know for certain what it is.
It is also meant to illustrate how people are NOT Condorcet jurors
themselves. We are NOT objective truth with some noise thrown in. In fact,
even in the P=NP problem, we would only distrust putting it to a public vote
because we have so much additional information about the problem. In
retrospect, using it as an example was a mistake. A system of the ilk I am
proposing doesn't know anything about the content of the issues, simply
what different people believe.

Nevertheless, I believe that we can simulate a Condorcet jury by weighting
people differently based on past behavior. This would make the resulting
voting methods adaptive rather than memory-less. The current methods that I
believe have been proposed thus far are all memory-less. The result of the
n+1st election can't depend on the nth election, indeed the results of any
elections are independent of the order in which they are conducted.

However, I would argue that this ignores important information that we have
in real life. We know something about the structure of non-randomness in
people's opinions and can account for it. Assuming people are honest, I
believe it is possible for an adaptive voting method to outperform methods
that enforce OMOV for the very limited goal I set forward in my first post…
to attempt to determine the truth of propositions, not to make any type of
normative decision.


I'm pretty sure that P = NP? is a question for which the average person
of the public's chance of getting the answer right is much lower than 50%.
So we don't ask the public (and if we had to, the jury theorem says we
should ask just a single person instead of averaging opinions).
Similar arguments have been made against democracy in general, even back to
the ancient Greek times, to the effect that statecraft is a skill and the
public isn't skilled. The jury theorem still works: you don't need to assume
people being wrong in non-random ways for the theorem to tell you it's not a
good idea to predict P = NP by vote.

You absolutely do need people to be wrong in non-random ways. If p.5 for
people, but we were still Condorcet Jurors, you would ask as many people as
possible and then negate the answer. That clearly doesn't work; therefore,
we are not Condorcet Jurors. I'm not claiming that jury theorem doesn't work
or is inapplicable, far from it. I'm claiming that if we have more
information on voters and their past behavior, we should be able to devise
an algorithm that will outperform OMOV.*

*assuming honest voters. I don't want to have to worry about strategic
voters yet.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Most Tolerable or Better

2011-06-29 Thread fsimmons
 On Jun 29, 2011, at 3:52 PM, fsimm...@pcc.edu wrote:
 
  This is a three slot method. The two non-blank choices are 
  tolerable and
  better.
 
  Elect the alternative that is marked tolerable or better on 
 the 
  greatest number
  of ballots.
 
  If there is a tie, then elect the tied alternative that is 
 marked 
  better on the
  greatest number of ballots.
 
 
What if we changed if there is a tie to if there is a statistical tie?

In other words if the difference in the number of tolerable or better votes 
for alternatives A and B is not 
statistically significant, then it is treated as a tie, and the distinction 
between tolerable and better 
kicks in.

You could make it so that the null hypothesis of tied tolerable and better is 
rejected only five percent of 
the time (when true).  This policy would make the tie breaker level (the 
better level) come into play 
more frequently, thus making the game more interesting.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info