Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
I will discus only IRV vs Condorcet. On Tue, 29 Jul 2008 09:45:47 +0100 James Gilmour wrote: Aaron Armitage > Sent: Tuesday, July 29, 2008 1:11 AM IRV and all other ranked choice systems ask for the same input from voters This is where you make your first mistake. IRV and other ranked choice voting system do not all ask for the same input from the voters. IRV asks voters to mark preferences in the knowledge that those preferences will be used as contingency choices, so that a later preference can in no way affect the chance of election of an earlier preference. Some other ranked choice voting systems, in a variety of different ways, make simultaneous use of all the preference information recorded on the ballot paper, such that the later preferences can affect the chances of election of the earlier preferences. The voters know in advance which counting rules will be used in any particular election and modify their marking of preferences accordingly. So the inputs are not the same. While the meaning of ranking is not identical, few voters should notice the difference. In both the voter lists first the most desired candidate. In Condorcet all that the voter says will be part of the tournament. In IRV candidates will be considered only after those the voter lists first have lost. Method matters little since preference controls electability. and produce the same kind of output, namely a single winner. Here is your second mistake. Both kinds of voting system do result in the election of a single winner, but the outcome (output) can be quite different in terms of what that winner represents. In the case of IRV that winner is the contingency choice, with all the implications of that. In Condorcet, the winner may be decided in a very different way from IRV and represent something very different in relation to the voters. In a Borda count, the winner may represent some sort of compromise even when there is one candidate who has an absolute majority of the first preference votes. So all these outputs are quite different. Who cares that the method of doing the analysis varies since the result is usually an identical winner? IRV, often not looking at all that the voter says, sometimes selects winners other than who the voters truly prefer. Condorcet, when presented with a near tie among three or more, invests effort IRV does not attempt to match in deciding on the best winner. For you to say they differ so fundamentally that no common standard can be appealed to looks an awful lot like special pleading. There was no special pleading - just a request that the differences in the inputs and outputs be recognised for what they are - fundamental - and not ignored. And how can you argue that we should adopt IRV instead of Condorcet or Borda or Bucklin if you have to common standard from which to argue that IRV is better? I don't think I have said anywhere that "we" should adopt IRV instead of the other voting systems, but since you ask: I would reject Borda because it can elect a candidate other than the one with an absolute majority of the first preference votes. I would reject Buckilin because it does not comply with "one person, one vote". I am VERY sympathetic to Condorcet and think the basic concept is "sellable" to the electors (presented as a "head-to-head tournament"), despite the inevitable opposition of most politicians, big business and the media moguls. I foresee bigger problems in selling any of various cycle-breaking and tie-breaking solutions that have been proposed. But the real problem with Condorcet is the weak Condorcet winner. It is my judgement (based on long experience as a practical reformer, but only in the UK) that such an outcome would not be politically acceptable to the electorate in an election to public office. Such a winner would, of course, be the real Condorcet winner, but that would not, of itself, make the result politically acceptable to real voters. This truly is a challenge, but might we be able to package the arguments more usefully? Most elections have only one or two serious candidates. Therefore a serious candidate is going to win: Sensible to just vote for one of these as in Plurality. Those wishing to can do ranking. Their vote for a serious candidate (or even both of such) will get counted as above; their votes for other candidates will be too few to matter. Elections with more serious candidates may become more common: Voting ala Plurality remains doable - just less adequate for most voters. Ranking allows more voters to express their desires. Primaries become less useful because there is no need for parties to try to prevent having multiple candidates in the general election. "cycle-breaking and tie-breaking"? This is one topic - near enough to a tie to need analysis. I claim it does not happen often enough that most voters should demand
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
--- On Tue, 7/29/08, Terry Bouricius <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > From: Terry Bouricius <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting > To: [EMAIL PROTECTED], election-methods@lists.electorama.com > Date: Tuesday, July 29, 2008, 1:19 PM > Aaron, > > Just four little points to what Aaron Armitage wrote... > > 1. > "You claim, in short, that using the same inputs > differently makes them > different inputs, and that producing the same kind of > outcome differently > makes it a different outcome." > > > I believe James was arguing that while a voter's > preferences in her mind > might be the same, but knowing whether the ballot would be > counted using > one method or another set of vote processing rules (with or > without > later-no-harm protection, for example) will change how the > voter will mark > the ballot. Or put another way, two ballots with identical > rankings on > them may in fact reflect very different actual preferences > by these two > voters depending on which vote processing rule is going to > be used. Thus, > one can't simply say inputs (if one means actual voter > preferences) are > identical by looking at the rankings without regard to the > vote processing > rule in place. > But voters' sincere preferences aren't the input for any voting system because we don't have access to them. Every ranked ballot system works with ordered lists of candidates provided by voters. I know that strategic voters will adjust how they use the input based on their understanding of the exact mechanism by which the input is turned into an outcome (that's the definition of a strategic voter). But susceptibility to these kinds of manipulations is simply one more way of comparing what remain different ways of converting the same kinds of inputs into the same kinds of results; in fact, several of the social choice criteria directly relate to strategic vulnerability. We're talking about how well Condorcet and IRV perform the same function, not two different functions. > 2. > "Under any definition of "one person, on > vote" that Bucklin fails, IRV > also > fails. But that wouldn't be a proper definition > anyway." > > > Not so. A single transferable vote is very different than a > Bucklin > additive vote. Under IRV each voter has one vote for one > candidate counted > in the final tally. Under Bucklin, voter A may have one > vote in the final > tally, but voter B has two votes for two candidates in > opposition. One > court ruled that Bucklin violated the one vote-one person > concept, while > another court ruled that IRV upheld it. Since these were > different courts, > it certainly isn't conclusive, but the difference is > significant. I > personally think that methods like Bucklin and Approval > might be seen as > satisfying one-person one-vote (nearly as well as IRV) > because a "vote" is > an expression of the voters choice on the matter at hand, > and all voters > have equal rights to mark the ballot with no class of > voters getting an > automatic advantage. > But voter A is the strategic voter and has an advantage over voter B, who has voluntarily diluted his voting strength by voting sincerely. The one person one vote objection was to allowing voters any fallback position at all, which IRV also does. > > 3. > "Take an example. Louisiana uses the same election > system that France > does, > and it malfunctioned the same way in both places; a > crypto-fascist got > enough votes to make it to the runoff, produced a fair > amount of panic, > and > duly lost to an opponent whose only real selling point was > being the only > alternative." > > > But the method is not IRV. In France with sequential > elimination, all > experts agree that le Pen would not have made it into the > final runoff, > and that Jospin would have been the finalist with Chirac. > Louisiana is a > better example, though still weak...since we can't know > for sure how IRV > in a single November election rather than the lower turnout > October > primary Duke passed through, would have changed voter > turnout and > outcomes. > Yes, of course I know it wasn't IRV. That's why I tried to make reasonable guesses about what might have happened, rather than just repeating what did. Even though the particular contingent facts of the election might have gone differently, my overall point stands: there are very reasonable scenarios where the majority preference for the CW over the IRV winner is a serious and substantively-based preference, rather than an artifact of strategic voters' using the CW as a placeholder. Many if not most voters, if allowed to truncate, will omit unknown candidates altogether. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Aaron, Just four little points to what Aaron Armitage wrote... 1. "You claim, in short, that using the same inputs differently makes them different inputs, and that producing the same kind of outcome differently makes it a different outcome." I believe James was arguing that while a voter's preferences in her mind might be the same, but knowing whether the ballot would be counted using one method or another set of vote processing rules (with or without later-no-harm protection, for example) will change how the voter will mark the ballot. Or put another way, two ballots with identical rankings on them may in fact reflect very different actual preferences by these two voters depending on which vote processing rule is going to be used. Thus, one can't simply say inputs (if one means actual voter preferences) are identical by looking at the rankings without regard to the vote processing rule in place. 2. "Under any definition of "one person, on vote" that Bucklin fails, IRV also fails. But that wouldn't be a proper definition anyway." Not so. A single transferable vote is very different than a Bucklin additive vote. Under IRV each voter has one vote for one candidate counted in the final tally. Under Bucklin, voter A may have one vote in the final tally, but voter B has two votes for two candidates in opposition. One court ruled that Bucklin violated the one vote-one person concept, while another court ruled that IRV upheld it. Since these were different courts, it certainly isn't conclusive, but the difference is significant. I personally think that methods like Bucklin and Approval might be seen as satisfying one-person one-vote (nearly as well as IRV) because a "vote" is an expression of the voters choice on the matter at hand, and all voters have equal rights to mark the ballot with no class of voters getting an automatic advantage. 3. "Take an example. Louisiana uses the same election system that France does, and it malfunctioned the same way in both places; a crypto-fascist got enough votes to make it to the runoff, produced a fair amount of panic, and duly lost to an opponent whose only real selling point was being the only alternative." But the method is not IRV. In France with sequential elimination, all experts agree that le Pen would not have made it into the final runoff, and that Jospin would have been the finalist with Chirac. Louisiana is a better example, though still weak...since we can't know for sure how IRV in a single November election rather than the lower turnout October primary Duke passed through, would have changed voter turnout and outcomes. 4. My last point is one of general agreement with Aaron...I agree that we should try to use criteria definitions that allow all single-winner voting methods to be compared...but that is much trickier than it at first appears. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
--- On Tue, 7/29/08, James Gilmour <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > From: James Gilmour <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting > To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com > Date: Tuesday, July 29, 2008, 3:45 AM > Aaron Armitage > Sent: Tuesday, July 29, 2008 1:11 AM > > IRV and all > > other ranked choice systems ask for the same input > from > > voters > > This is where you make your first mistake. IRV and other > ranked choice voting system do not all ask for the same > input from the > voters. IRV asks voters to mark preferences in the > knowledge that those preferences will be used as > contingency choices, so that a > later preference can in no way affect the chance of > election of an earlier preference. Some other ranked > choice voting systems, in > a variety of different ways, make simultaneous use of all > the preference information recorded on the ballot paper, > such that the > later preferences can affect the chances of election of the > earlier preferences. The voters know in advance which > counting rules > will be used in any particular election and modify their > marking of preferences accordingly. So the inputs are not > the same. > > > > and produce the same kind of output, namely a single > > winner. > > Here is your second mistake. Both kinds of voting system > do result in the election of a single winner, but the > outcome (output) can > be quite different in terms of what that winner represents. > In the case of IRV that winner is the contingency choice, > with all the > implications of that. In Condorcet, the winner may be > decided in a very different way from IRV and represent > something very > different in relation to the voters. In a Borda count, the > winner may represent some sort of compromise even when there > is one > candidate who has an absolute majority of the first > preference votes. So all these outputs are quite > different. > You claim, in short, that using the same inputs differently makes them different inputs, and that producing the same kind of outcome differently makes it a different outcome. But you began by contrasting IRV to "social choice" methods like Condorcet and Borda, even though Condorcet and Borda treat the inputs very differently and informed voters will presumably take that into account when they make their rankings. Are Borda and Condorcet also incommensurable, or just IRV? In general, if we followed your logic we couldn't compare different ways of doing the same thing, since if they handled their inputs the same and their results represented the same thing -- that is, the same internal process -- they wouldn't be different methods. A hybrid car uses its gas differently and drives the wheels differently; can we directly compare a hybrid's fuel efficiency to a straight internal combustion car's fuel efficiency, or do we decide that because a non-hybrid isn't trying to be a hybrid it can get away with being less efficient? > I would reject Buckilin because it does not comply with > "one person, one vote". > Under any definition of "one person, on vote" that Bucklin fails, IRV also fails. But that wouldn't be a proper definition anyway. > I am VERY sympathetic to Condorcet and think the basic > concept is "sellable" to the electors (presented > as a "head-to-head > tournament"), despite the inevitable opposition of > most politicians, big business and the media moguls. I > foresee bigger problems > in selling any of various cycle-breaking and tie-breaking > solutions that have been proposed. But the real problem > with Condorcet is > the weak Condorcet winner. It is my judgement (based on > long experience as a practical reformer, but only in the > UK) that such an > outcome would not be politically acceptable to the > electorate in an election to public office. Such a winner > would, of course, be > the real Condorcet winner, but that would not, of itself, > make the result politically acceptable to real voters. > Every scenario for this that I've seen assumes two strong candidates and a third candidate who is only a placeholder; in other words, it implicitly assumes that only serious candidates will be the Republican and the Democrat, or the Conservative and the Labourite or Liberal Democrat, or whatever the local equivalents are. But what happened to all the serious admonitions to consider how the system will change people's behavior? In a Condorcet election there's no reason there would only be two major candidates, and a public thinking in terms of Condorcet would have a completely different understanding of what strong and weak
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Aaron Armitage > Sent: Tuesday, July 29, 2008 1:11 AM > IRV and all > other ranked choice systems ask for the same input from > voters This is where you make your first mistake. IRV and other ranked choice voting system do not all ask for the same input from the voters. IRV asks voters to mark preferences in the knowledge that those preferences will be used as contingency choices, so that a later preference can in no way affect the chance of election of an earlier preference. Some other ranked choice voting systems, in a variety of different ways, make simultaneous use of all the preference information recorded on the ballot paper, such that the later preferences can affect the chances of election of the earlier preferences. The voters know in advance which counting rules will be used in any particular election and modify their marking of preferences accordingly. So the inputs are not the same. > and produce the same kind of output, namely a single > winner. Here is your second mistake. Both kinds of voting system do result in the election of a single winner, but the outcome (output) can be quite different in terms of what that winner represents. In the case of IRV that winner is the contingency choice, with all the implications of that. In Condorcet, the winner may be decided in a very different way from IRV and represent something very different in relation to the voters. In a Borda count, the winner may represent some sort of compromise even when there is one candidate who has an absolute majority of the first preference votes. So all these outputs are quite different. > For you to say they differ so fundamentally that no > common standard can be appealed to looks an awful lot like > special pleading. There was no special pleading - just a request that the differences in the inputs and outputs be recognised for what they are - fundamental - and not ignored. > And how can you argue that we should adopt > IRV instead of Condorcet or Borda or Bucklin if you have to > common standard from which to argue that IRV is better? I don't think I have said anywhere that "we" should adopt IRV instead of the other voting systems, but since you ask: I would reject Borda because it can elect a candidate other than the one with an absolute majority of the first preference votes. I would reject Buckilin because it does not comply with "one person, one vote". I am VERY sympathetic to Condorcet and think the basic concept is "sellable" to the electors (presented as a "head-to-head tournament"), despite the inevitable opposition of most politicians, big business and the media moguls. I foresee bigger problems in selling any of various cycle-breaking and tie-breaking solutions that have been proposed. But the real problem with Condorcet is the weak Condorcet winner. It is my judgement (based on long experience as a practical reformer, but only in the UK) that such an outcome would not be politically acceptable to the electorate in an election to public office. Such a winner would, of course, be the real Condorcet winner, but that would not, of itself, make the result politically acceptable to real voters. IRV has, of course, a corresponding "political" weakness, in that it can reject the candidate who might be everyone's second choice (the Condorcet winner). But experience shows that the electors are prepared to accept that outcome. James Gilmour No virus found in this outgoing message. Checked by AVG. Version: 7.5.526 / Virus Database: 270.5.6/1578 - Release Date: 28/07/2008 17:13 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Aaron's words make sense, but perhaps I can do better talking about two methods that, while using the same ballots but going at the task in different ways, usually agree as to winner. IRV looks only at best liked, discards candidate with fewest such votes, and repeats until a winner remains. Condorcet looks at ALL the ballot rankings, discards candidate liked less when compared with each other candidate, and repeats until no such candidates remain. Since IRV only looks at momentarily best liked, it can discard candidates Condorcet would see many voters truly liking better. Condorcet can complete this part with three or more candidates remaining because they are in near ties such as A>B and B>C and C>A. This is called a cycle and requires special analysis to decide which member should win. Note that cycles require a mixture of voters with differing goals - no one voter can vote all the inequalities described above. DWK On Mon, 28 Jul 2008 17:10:49 -0700 (PDT) Aaron Armitage wrote: --- On Mon, 7/28/08, James Gilmour <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: That all ranked ballot voting systems must be assessed using criteria and tests that can be applied to them all, is your view, and it may be the view of others. But I would suggest it ignores some fundamental differences between the voting systems. IRV in particular makes no pretence at complying with a range of social choice criteria - it is a complete different kind of voting system. I find this a really astonishing thing to say. IRV and all other ranked choice systems ask for the same input from voters and produce the same kind of output, namely a single winner. For you to say they differ so fundamentally that no common standard can be appealed to looks an awful lot like special pleading. And how can you argue that we should adopt IRV instead of Condorcet or Borda or Bucklin if you have to common standard from which to argue that IRV is better? Or is it only the criteria that put IRV in a bad light that are irrelevant? -- [EMAIL PROTECTED]people.clarityconnect.com/webpages3/davek Dave Ketchum 108 Halstead Ave, Owego, NY 13827-1708 607-687-5026 Do to no one what you would not want done to you. If you want peace, work for justice. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
--- On Mon, 7/28/08, James Gilmour <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > That all ranked ballot voting systems must be assessed > using criteria and tests that can be applied to them all, > is your view, and > it may be the view of others. But I would suggest it > ignores some fundamental differences between the voting > systems. IRV in > particular makes no pretence at complying with a range of > social choice criteria - it is a complete different kind > of voting > system. I find this a really astonishing thing to say. IRV and all other ranked choice systems ask for the same input from voters and produce the same kind of output, namely a single winner. For you to say they differ so fundamentally that no common standard can be appealed to looks an awful lot like special pleading. And how can you argue that we should adopt IRV instead of Condorcet or Borda or Bucklin if you have to common standard from which to argue that IRV is better? Or is it only the criteria that put IRV in a bad light that are irrelevant? Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
--- On Mon, 7/28/08, Chris Benham <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > From: Chris Benham <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re:RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting > To: "EM" > Cc: [EMAIL PROTECTED] > Date: Monday, July 28, 2008, 9:57 AM > Aaron, > "In an important respect, Condorcet is more natural > than IRV: if a majority prefers Brad over Carter, this > preference exists whether the voting system does anything > with it, or even elicits enough information to determine > that it exists. " > Yes, except that "Condorcet" is a criterion and > IRV is a method, and "more natural" doesn't > have a precise meaning. > I think the meaning of "more natural" was sufficiently clarified by my explanation, namely that Condorcet methods are based on a property that exists in the preferences themselves, rather than being an artifact of the counting rules. Which is why there can be such a thing as a Condorcet criterion; it refers to a real correspondence between the rankings provided and the result produced. > "Condorcet simply discovers and applies this > preference. IRV, on the other hand, elicits enough > information to discover it exists, but may decide to ignore > it based purely on procedural grounds. There are no good > reasons for this, ever." > IRV meets Later-no-Harm and Later-no-Help and is immune > to Burial strategy, and these properties are incompatible > with the Condorcet criterion. > Some people think these "reasons" are > "good". I know some people claim that there are good reasons to use non-Condorcet methods. I claim that when it gets down to installing a candidate over a candidate who beat him, which all non-Condorcet methods do sometimes (or else they'd be Condorcet methods), those reasons aren't good enough. Suppose my preference is Andrea > Brad > Carter, and Brad > Carter is a majority preference, but Andrea > Brad and Andrea > Carter isn't. Under IRV, I am sometimes (but not always) forced to hold on to Andrea until I no longer have any chance of helping Brad beat Carter, even if my preferences are more like Andrea > Brad > Carter. This quality strikes me as perverse. Nevertheless, Condorcet's failure of LNH is connected to a serious weakness, vulnerability to burial. But this means that when my later preferences do "hurt" my favorite, things are as they should be because it means I didn't create an artificial cycle. > BTW, which of the many methods that meet the Condorcet > criterion is your favourite? > Chris Benham > You're really asking which completion method is my favorite, and I don't have any strong preferences. I believe an actual runoff for the Smith set would be the most appropriate: it would give voters a chance to reconsider with their attention focused on only the serious candidates, and make strategy harder to use. If, for example, the cycle existed because a large number of ballots were Republican > Green > Democrat, the Democrats will have an opportunity to use counter-strategy, or even make the apparent manipulation a campaign issue. It's not really reasonable to have a third or later vote, so some reasonable completion method will need to be used. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Kristofer > Sent: Monday, July 28, 2008 10:58 AM > James Gilmour wrote: > >> it would have to look at the entire ballot. > > > > That is a consequence of your interpretation of how the voting > > system > > is supposed to work and what the voting system is supposed to be > > doing. But that's not what IRV is about. As I said in the previous > > message, the origins of IRV are in the Exhaustive Ballot, and in the > > Exhaustive Ballot there is no possibility of looking "at the entire > > ballot". IRV is not about satisfying a set of criteria derived from > > social choice philosophy. > > In taking the "people out of the loop" in all rounds but the first, the > reduction of Exhaustive Ballot to IRV turns IRV into yet another ranked > ballot method. Thus it wouldn't matter if IRV originates in Exhaustive > Ballot or not, because it has to stand as a ranked ballot method among > other ranked ballot methods, using criteria and tests that can be > applied to all of them. That all ranked ballot voting systems must be assessed using criteria and tests that can be applied to them all, is your view, and it may be the view of others. But I would suggest it ignores some fundamental differences between the voting systems. IRV in particular makes no pretence at complying with a range of social choice criteria - it is a complete different kind of voting system. When I mark my preferences in an IRV ballot I take into account that the counting rules will be IRV rules. If the counting rules would use the preferences in a different way, e.g. a Borda count, then I might well mark my presences in a different order - I certainly would have a lot more to think about. Of course, anyone is perfectly entitled to say that some (or any) social choice voting system is preferable to some (or any) non-social choice voting system, and that would be a valid comparison. But that is a completely different argument. My concern was that a voting system, in this case IRV, was being judged by criteria that are not at all relevant to it. > > > If you want something that only a social choice approach can deliver, > > then clearly IRV is not for you. But that does not make Kathy Dopp's > > original statement a valid criticism of IRV. > > Wouldn't it be, from a social choice point of view if no other? Kathy Dopp's comment was based on an interpretation of "majority" that was not relevant to IRV. What she really wanted to say, was that IRV should not be used because it fails to meet one or more social choice criteria. But as I have said before, that is a completely different argument, and it is a valid argument. > > >> Or more concrete: if you want the sort of compromise that Condorcet > >> gives (and you don't think that's a "weak centrist"), then you > >> can't have LNHarm. I don't think you can have LNHelp either, but > >> I'm not sure about that. > > > > I agree, but one could I think reasonably argue in the specific case > > of Condorcet that it does comply with LNHarm (at least, in Condorcet > > where there were no cycles or ties). Your higher preferences are > > always placed above your lower preferences in the Condorcet > > "head-to-head" comparisons. So YOUR lower preference can never harm > > YOUR higher preference. But that is certainly not true for many other > > social choice voting systems that use the preference information in a > > quite different way. > > That's true; it's the cycles that cause the problem. Still, Woodall's > proof shows that it's possible to make a ballot set with no CW in a way > that no matter who wins, it's possible to append a later preference to > some of the ballots so that another candidate becomes the CW. > The problem is in the transition between cycle and non-cycle, so inasfar > as Condorcet winners usually occur, the Condorcet method passes LNHarm; > but since cycles can occur, that means Condorcet is incompatible with > LNHarm. > > If we look at it from what you call the social choice point of view, > then what has happened that makes Condorcet fail LNHarm is that it's > used a later preference to find the Condorcet winner that it didn't know > of, had it only used earlier preferences. Here it seems you are agreeing with me, that Condorcet conforms to LNHarm in the absence of cycles or ties, but that all the cycle-breaking and tie-breaking methods would cause it to fail that criterion. > >>> "Many" on this list may think that, but it is my experience of > >>> more than 45 years as a practical reformer explaining voting > >>> systems to real electors, that 'later no harm' does matter greatly > >>> to ordinary electors. If they think the voting system will not > >>> comply with 'later no harm', their immediate reaction is to say > >>> "I'm not going to mark a second or any further preference because > >>> that will hurt my first choice candidate - the one I most want to > >>> see elected." And of course, if you once
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
(Oops, seems I sent this only to James Gilmour. Let's try again. ) James Gilmour wrote: >> it would have to look at the entire ballot. > > That is a consequence of your interpretation of how the voting system > is supposed to work and what the voting system is supposed to > be doing. But that's not what IRV is about. As I said in the > previous message, the origins of IRV are in the Exhaustive Ballot, > and in the Exhaustive Ballot there is no possibility of looking "at > the entire ballot". IRV is not about satisfying a set of criteria > derived from social choice philosophy. In taking the "people out of the loop" in all rounds but the first, the reduction of Exhaustive Ballot to IRV turns IRV into yet another ranked ballot method. Thus it wouldn't matter if IRV originates in Exhaustive Ballot or not, because it has to stand as a ranked ballot method among other ranked ballot methods, using criteria and tests that can be applied to all of them. > If you want something that only a social choice approach can deliver, > then clearly IRV is not for you. But that does not make Kathy > Dopp's original statement a valid criticism of IRV. Wouldn't it be, from a social choice point of view if no other? >> Or more concrete: if you want the sort of compromise that Condorcet >> gives (and you don't think that's a "weak centrist"), then you can't >> have LNHarm. I don't think you can have LNHelp either, but I'm not >> sure about that. > > I agree, but one could I think reasonably argue in the specific case > of Condorcet that it does comply with LNHarm (at least, in Condorcet > where there were no cycles or ties). Your higher preferences are > always placed above your lower preferences in the Condorcet > "head-to-head" comparisons. So YOUR lower preference can never harm > YOUR higher preference. But that is certainly not true for many other > social choice voting systems that use the preference information in a > quite different way. That's true; it's the cycles that cause the problem. Still, Woodall's proof shows that it's possible to make a ballot set with no CW in a way that no matter who wins, it's possible to append a later preference to some of the ballots so that another candidate becomes the CW. The problem is in the transition between cycle and non-cycle, so inasfar as Condorcet winners usually occur, the Condorcet method passes LNHarm; but since cycles can occur, that means Condorcet is incompatible with LNHarm. If we look at it from what you call the social choice point of view, then what has happened that makes Condorcet fail LNHarm is that it's used a later preference to find the Condorcet winner that it didn't know of, had it only used earlier preferences. >>> "Many" on this list may think that, but it is my experience of more >>> than 45 years as a practical reformer explaining voting systems to >>> real electors, that 'later no harm' does matter greatly to ordinary >>> electors. If they think the voting system will not comply with >>> 'later no harm', their immediate reaction is to say "I'm not going >>> to mark a second or any further preference because that will hurt my >>> first choice candidate - the one I most want to see elected." And >>> of course, if you once depart from 'later no harm' you open the way >>> to all sorts of strategic voting that just cannot work in a 'later >>> no harm' IRV (or STV) public election with large numbers of voters. >> If the method fails LNHarm about as often as it fails LNHelp, then >> that argument should fail, because bullet voting may harm your other >> choices as much (or more, no way to know in general) as consistently >> voting all of them will. Ceteris paribus, it's better to have a >> method that passes both of the LNHs than neither (since you get >> strategy in the latter case), but the hit you take might not be as >> serious as it seems at first. > > Your argument in respect of bullet voting in IRV is based on a > misinterpretation of what that voter has said to the Returning > Officer. Because IRV conforms to LNHarm, a bullet vote, or any > truncation, is a voter saying "After this point, I opt out and leave > any choice among the other candidates to the other voters." Such a > voter has no "other choices". So there is no question of harming them > or helping them. That wasn't an argument against bullet voting in IRV. I know that IRV satisfies both LNHarm and LNHelp (it's also nonmonotonic, which is a consequence of that it satisfies both and Mutual Majority; but that's not relevant to the case here). What I'm saying, regarding voting systems that fail LNH, is that you can divide strategies into those that every voter would use just to maximize the power of the ballot, and those that require information to pull off. If a voting system satisfies neither of the LNHs, and the rate of failure is balanced (doesn't consistently harm earlier candidates nor consistently help earlier candidates), then ordinar
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Aaron, "In an important respect, Condorcet is more natural than IRV: if a majority prefers Brad over Carter, this preference exists whether the voting system does anything with it, or even elicits enough information to determine that it exists. " Yes, except that "Condorcet" is a criterion and IRV is a method, and "more natural" doesn't have a precise meaning. "Condorcet simply discovers and applies this preference. IRV, on the other hand, elicits enough information to discover it exists, but may decide to ignore it based purely on procedural grounds. There are no good reasons for this, ever." IRV meets Later-no-Harm and Later-no-Help and is immune to Burial strategy, and these properties are incompatible with the Condorcet criterion. Some people think these "reasons" are "good". ""Core support" is a bogus reason: every time IRV chooses someone other than the plurality winner you're letting an overall majority trump a comparison of core supporters. But other times IRV will fail to do this, for reasons that simply don't exist apart from the system itself." "Core support" is IMO just propaganda designed to reassure the public that IRV isn't too radical a change from FPP. BTW, which of the many methods that meet the Condorcet criterion is your favourite? Chris Benham Aaron Armitage wrote (Sun Jul 27,2008): Of course every reason you might offer for choosing one system over another is based on an idea of what a reasonable decision rule for making collective decisions in very large groups should look like. This is true for IRV advocate no less than advocates for other systems; where the system came from is beside the point, especially since most jurisdictions have never used the Exhaustive Ballot. In an important respect, Condorcet is more natural than IRV: if a majority prefers Brad over Carter, this preference exists whether the voting system does anything with it, or even elicits enough information to determine that it exists. Condorcet simply discovers and applies this preference. IRV, on the other hand, elicits enough information to discover it exists, but may decide to ignore it based purely on procedural grounds. There are no good reasons for this, ever. "Core support" is a bogus reason: every time IRV chooses someone other than the plurality winner you're letting an overall majority trump a comparison of core supporters. But other times IRV will fail to do this, for reasons that simply don't exist apart from the system itself. Find a better answer, faster with the new Yahoo!7 Search. www.yahoo7.com.au/search Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Abd ul-Rahman Lomax > Sent: Monday, July 28, 2008 5:35 AM > >As I said in the previous message, the origins of IRV are in the Exhaustive > >Ballot, > >and in the Exhaustive Ballot there is no possibility of looking "at the > >entire ballot". > > Can you provide a source for the claim that "the origins of IRV are > in the Exhaustive Ballot"? No. None of the sources that are readily to hand gives any dates when the Alternative Vote (the much older UK name for IRV) was first seen as an administrative improvement for the Second Ballot and the Exhaustive Ballot. James Gilmour No virus found in this outgoing message. Checked by AVG. Version: 7.5.526 / Virus Database: 270.5.6/1576 - Release Date: 27/07/2008 16:16 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
On Mon, 28 Jul 2008 00:30:10 -0400 Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote: ... Actually, the term in the first sentence is "majority rule," which, in actual operation, makes decisions always between two alternatives, minimized to Yes or No on a single question. ... It could be made compatible, and the method is obvious, and is precisely what Robert's Rules of order describes as how it would be used. A true majority is required to win. IRV then becomes a method of finding majorities, provided that enough voters add enough ranked choices. If all voters rank all the candidates, a majority is guaranteed. We happily complain about others' seen misuse of "majority". Seems to mew the above is misuse. If every voter ranks every candidate, then you have managed a infinity of yeses, zero noes, and nothing to indicate which candidate has won. True that the ranking identifies a winner but, if we were looking at the ranking, we would have no need to demand the complete ranking specified above. Elsewhere I argue for Condorcet as better than IRV - for more completely counting voters' complete preferences. There I argue for abandonment, or at least relaxation of, majority requirements, because voter have more completely expressed their desires. ... -- [EMAIL PROTECTED]people.clarityconnect.com/webpages3/davek Dave Ketchum 108 Halstead Ave, Owego, NY 13827-1708 607-687-5026 Do to no one what you would not want done to you. If you want peace, work for justice. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
At 09:30 AM 7/27/2008, James Gilmour wrote: As I said in the previous message, the origins of IRV are in the Exhaustive Ballot, and in the Exhaustive Ballot there is no possibility of looking "at the entire ballot". Can you provide a source for the claim that "the origins of IRV are in the Exhaustive Ballot"? Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
At 07:06 PM 7/26/2008, James Gilmour wrote: Kathy Dopp > Sent: Saturday, June 21, 2008 5:20 AM > "Later-No-Harm", however, is incompatible with the basic > principles of majority rule, which requires compromise if > decisions are to be made. That's because the peculiar design > of sequential elimination guarantees -- if a majority is not > required -- that a lower preference cannot harm a higher > preference, because the lower preferences are only considered > if a higher one is eliminated. The meaning of the second sentence isn't completely clear to me, but I am fairly sure there is a perverse interpretation of "majority" in the first sentence. Actually, the term in the first sentence is "majority rule," which, in actual operation, makes decisions always between two alternatives, minimized to Yes or No on a single question. Compromises are made for efficiency, with various degrees of damage to majority rule. The traditional method is very simple: a motion for an action, seconded. Discussion. Amendment, each amendment being treated as if it were its own motion, which it is. A calling of the question, typically by supermajority (2/3 for Robert's Rules, but it is always possible for a majority to bypass this, with some damage to collegiality and a general sense that the majority is playing fair). And then vote, and if a true majority of those voting is not obtained, the motion fails and the status quo continues. Deliberative process, as described, breaks down if every voter insists on their first preference, without compromise until it has been proven beyond doubt that the first preference cannot be obtained. Generally, in deliberative process, there is no such elimination. What was rejected before can be recalled and considered again. For Later-no-Harm to function, candidates must actually be eliminated. That doesn't happen under deliberative process. Now, for efficiency, there are voting methods that allow more than one candidate to be considered at a time. Plurality is one such. In deliberative process, there is no harm if the winner obtains a majority, in a Plurality election where voters are properly informed and make the necessary compromises as they vote. But it's tricky to do that optimally, so voters might compromise when they don't need to, etc. Efficient methods would allow voters to indicate preference strength, and Range Voting is really the method that does this most accurately. If voters do this sincerely, the method will predict which candidate would enjoy the maximum overall satisfaction as rated by the voters themselves. (The question of sincere voting in Range is a complex one, with common assumptions being made that are actually self-contradictory, i.e., weak preferences expressed strongly. Why? If it is not merely an accident, it would be because the voter wants the favorite to win, enough to risk loss from not giving some preference strength to another pairwise election. But that's a strong preference!) But I would not consider a decision made by Range Voting to be a democratic decision *unless the approval of a majority for that outcome were explicit.* IRV, as implemented everywhere I've seen it, will elect by plurality. That is, it will elect even though a majority of voters voted for someone else and not for the winner. That is, in case it needs to be said, a majority who showed up and voted, who did not care to vote for the IRV winner, who, by the only means allowed that didn't require some other vote offensive to the voter, voted *against* the winner. IRV, as used, is incompatible with majority rule. It could be made compatible, and the method is obvious, and is precisely what Robert's Rules of order describes as how it would be used. A true majority is required to win. IRV then becomes a method of finding majorities, provided that enough voters add enough ranked choices. If all voters rank all the candidates, a majority is guaranteed. But when full ranking is optional -- and it must be optional for the method to be fully democratic -- majority failure can occur, and thus, Robert's Rules notes, "the election must be repeated." They have in mind repetition with no elimination. What I've realized -- and I never saw this in print anywhere -- is that top-two runoff, in some places, actually doesn't eliminate any candidates, it merely restricts who is on the ballot and, it has been proven, this doesn't prevent a write-in from winning. So there is, technically, no elimination, and IRV under such circumstances would be a clear improvement over plurality, by eliminating some unnecessary runoffs. Turns out, though, that it would only eliminate maybe one-third of runoffs in a place like San Francisco. Bucklin voting, using the same ballot, and probably seeing the same voting patterns, would probably eliminate about half of them. Approval would probably do about the same. An IRV election is an Exhaustive Ballot
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
--- On Sun, 7/27/08, Terry Bouricius <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > From: Terry Bouricius <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting > To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com > Date: Sunday, July 27, 2008, 3:32 PM > Different election methods provide different incentives to > candidates...Under IRV, or two-round runoff, a candidate > who is nobody's > first choice cannot win (they will be eliminated) even if > this candidate > would be a good compromise (or merely an inoffensive > candidate avoiding > all controversial issues), whereas under Condorcet or Borda > (for example) > a candidate who is nobody's first choice CAN win. Thus > IRV prompts > candidates to "stand-out" enough to win a lot of > FIRST choices and reach > out for second choices as well, while that strategy of > stressing first > choices may hurt the candidate under Condorcet or Borda. > IRV advocates > argue (rightly, I think) that it strikes a favorable > balance between > seeking first choices ("core" support) and > alternate rankings ("broad" > support), when compared to methods that disregard whether a > candidate > received any first preferences. > Why are you assuming that standing out means taking clear policy positions? It could just as easy mean running more ads than anyone else or having a more telegenic family or a more famous name. There are a lot of voters who base their first, not their later, preferences on just those things, and we know that because they're often enough to carry a plurality election which only considers first preferences. For that matter, "core support" could mean nothing more than coming second to last all the way to the end. That's unlikely, but no more unlikely than a candidate with no first-place support running a campaign strong enough to make him a Condorcet winner. Regardless of whether voters are making a good choice, if a majority favors one candidate over another, none of us, FairVote included, are qualified to tell it that it must take the candidate it voted AGAINST just to satisfy some airy theoretical concern about having the "right" amount of first-place support, as if we could even tell what that is. It's especially senseless when the people who advocate setting aside a majority vote to satisfy their theories will turn around and act like populists attacking the ivory tower when anyone brings up theoretical criteria that actually make sense. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
this preference exists whether the voting system does anything with it"...is that the voting method in use will affect candidate behavior, and thus may result in Brad NOT being actually preferred over Carter under a different voting method. In other words, voter preferences among candidates (whether scores, or rankings) are not actually "given," as we assume when working out models (A>B>C), but will change depending on what campaign style is rewarded by the voting method in use. Terry Bouricius - Original Message - From: "Aaron Armitage" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> To: Sent: Sunday, July 27, 2008 2:45 PM Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting --- On Sun, 7/27/08, James Gilmour <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: That is a consequence of your interpretation of how the voting system is supposed to work and what the voting system is supposed to be doing. But that's not what IRV is about. As I said in the previous message, the origins of IRV are in the Exhaustive Ballot, and in the Exhaustive Ballot there is no possibility of looking "at the entire ballot". IRV is not about satisfying a set of criteria derived from social choice philosophy. Of course every reason you might offer for choosing one system over another is based on an idea of what a reasonable decision rule for making collective decisions in very large groups should look like. This is true for IRV advocate no less than advocates for other systems; where the system came from is beside the point, especially since most jurisdictions have never used the Exhaustive Ballot. In an important respect, Condorcet is more natural than IRV: if a majority prefers Brad over Carter, this preference exists whether the voting system does anything with it, or even elicits enough information to determine that it exists. Condorcet simply discovers and applies this preference. IRV, on the other hand, elicits enough information to discover it exists, but may decide to ignore it based purely on procedural grounds. There are no good reasons for this, ever. "Core support" is a bogus reason: every time IRV chooses someone other than the plurality winner you're letting an overall majority trump a comparison of core supporters. But other times IRV will fail to do this, for reasons that simply don't exist apart from the system itself. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info ___ All new Yahoo! Mail "The new Interface is stunning in its simplicity and ease of use." - PC Magazine http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Different election methods provide different incentives to candidates...Under IRV, or two-round runoff, a candidate who is nobody's first choice cannot win (they will be eliminated) even if this candidate would be a good compromise (or merely an inoffensive candidate avoiding all controversial issues), whereas under Condorcet or Borda (for example) a candidate who is nobody's first choice CAN win. Thus IRV prompts candidates to "stand-out" enough to win a lot of FIRST choices and reach out for second choices as well, while that strategy of stressing first choices may hurt the candidate under Condorcet or Borda. IRV advocates argue (rightly, I think) that it strikes a favorable balance between seeking first choices ("core" support) and alternate rankings ("broad" support), when compared to methods that disregard whether a candidate received any first preferences. Terry Bouricius - Original Message - From: "Aaron Armitage" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> To: Sent: Sunday, July 27, 2008 4:21 PM Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting --- On Sun, 7/27/08, Terry Bouricius <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > From: Terry Bouricius <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting > To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com > Date: Sunday, July 27, 2008, 2:26 PM > While I agree that "core support" is not always > well measured by first > choices (multiple clones can make all these clones appear > to have little > "core" support, where any of them would appear to > have massive core > support running alone). However, I think the concept of > "core support" is > still an important factor in multi-candidate elections. > While I think > Condorcet methods are much better than most methods, I > remain concerned > that it may, in fact, reward inoffensive candidates who > successfully hide > their policy positions, rather than just true > "compromise" candidates. > Voters tend to have clear opinions of candidates at the top > and bottom of > their preference rankings, leaving the door open for > inoffensive > candidates who have avoided revealing any controversial > views, to become > EVERY voter's second choice ("at least he must be > better than X") and > likely Condorcet winner. The voting method will cause > candidates to tailor > their campaigns accordingly, and I fear Condorcet > encourages candidates to > limit voter information and instead campaign with slogans > like "I am the > candidate who listen to you" and policy will become > even LESS discussed in > campaigns than is already the case in the U.S. > > So an important caveat to the assertion that "if a > majority prefers Brad > over Carter, this preference exists whether the voting > system does > anything with it"...is that the voting method in use > will affect candidate > behavior, and thus may result in Brad NOT being actually > preferred over > Carter under a different voting method. In other words, > voter preferences > among candidates (whether scores, or rankings) are not > actually "given," > as we assume when working out models (A>B>C), but > will change depending on > what campaign style is rewarded by the voting method in > use. > > Terry Bouricius > > I'm not sure this objection applies much more strongly to Condorcet methods than any other single-winner system; a candidate with any possible rough edges taken off will always have more appeal to moderates and low-information voters than one who takes clear policy positions. The closest thing to a real solution is to use proportional multi-winner elections wherever possible. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
--- On Sun, 7/27/08, Terry Bouricius <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > From: Terry Bouricius <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting > To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com > Date: Sunday, July 27, 2008, 2:26 PM > While I agree that "core support" is not always > well measured by first > choices (multiple clones can make all these clones appear > to have little > "core" support, where any of them would appear to > have massive core > support running alone). However, I think the concept of > "core support" is > still an important factor in multi-candidate elections. > While I think > Condorcet methods are much better than most methods, I > remain concerned > that it may, in fact, reward inoffensive candidates who > successfully hide > their policy positions, rather than just true > "compromise" candidates. > Voters tend to have clear opinions of candidates at the top > and bottom of > their preference rankings, leaving the door open for > inoffensive > candidates who have avoided revealing any controversial > views, to become > EVERY voter's second choice ("at least he must be > better than X") and > likely Condorcet winner. The voting method will cause > candidates to tailor > their campaigns accordingly, and I fear Condorcet > encourages candidates to > limit voter information and instead campaign with slogans > like "I am the > candidate who listen to you" and policy will become > even LESS discussed in > campaigns than is already the case in the U.S. > > So an important caveat to the assertion that "if a > majority prefers Brad > over Carter, this preference exists whether the voting > system does > anything with it"...is that the voting method in use > will affect candidate > behavior, and thus may result in Brad NOT being actually > preferred over > Carter under a different voting method. In other words, > voter preferences > among candidates (whether scores, or rankings) are not > actually "given," > as we assume when working out models (A>B>C), but > will change depending on > what campaign style is rewarded by the voting method in > use. > > Terry Bouricius > > I'm not sure this objection applies much more strongly to Condorcet methods than any other single-winner system; a candidate with any possible rough edges taken off will always have more appeal to moderates and low-information voters than one who takes clear policy positions. The closest thing to a real solution is to use proportional multi-winner elections wherever possible. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
HUH!!! How did we get here, where the topic is IRV??? Plurality with runoff: If Plurality fails to produce a winner. then the leading candidates - usually two - are voted on in a separate election. Exhaustive Ballot: If Plurality fails to produce a winner, then the candidate with the fewest votes is eliminated and a further round of voting occurs. This process is repeated for as many rounds as necessary until one candidate has a majority. NOT GOOD to risk having many such rounds in a public election with thousands of voters. IRV (Instant Runoff Voting): Can be thought of as a descendant of either of the above, with the voter permitted to rank multiple candidates on a single ballot and the counters to consider only the top ranked in each round. If Plurality fails to produce a winner, then the candidate with the fewest votes is eliminated from all ballots, all thus exhausted ballots discarded, and a further round of counting occurs. This process is repeated for as many rounds as necessary until one candidate has a majority. I have not done LNH analysis. On Sun, 27 Jul 2008 00:06:51 +0100 James Gilmour wrote: Kathy Dopp > Sent: Saturday, June 21, 2008 5:20 AM "Later-No-Harm", however, is incompatible with the basic principles of majority rule, which requires compromise if decisions are to be made. That's because the peculiar design of sequential elimination guarantees -- if a majority is not required -- that a lower preference cannot harm a higher preference, because the lower preferences are only considered if a higher one is eliminated. The meaning of the second sentence isn't completely clear to me, but I am fairly sure there is a perverse interpretation of "majority" in the first sentence. An IRV election is an Exhaustive Ballot election contracted into one voting event, instead of being spread over several rounds in which the one candidate with fewest votes is eliminated at each round. It is no surprise that the numbers of voters participating varies from round to round - usually a progressive (or severe) decline. The votes in an IRV election might look like this: > > Round 1 > A 4,000 > B 3,000 C>A 400 C>B 1,400 C 200 D>B 100 D 900 > Total voting 10,000 > > Round 2 A 4,000 B 3,100 C>A 400 C>B 1,400 C 200 Total voting 9,100 > > Round 3 A 4,400 B 4,500 Total voting 8,900. > B is the majority winner in Round 3, that is to say, the majority winner of those voters then voting. DWK Exhaustive Ballot election might look like this: Round 1 A 4,000 B 3,000 C 2,000 D 1,000 Total voting 10,000 Round 2 A 3,500 B 2,500 C 1,500 Total voting 7,500 Round 3 A 3,000 B 2,000 Total voting 5,000. A is the majority winner in Round 3, that is to say, the majority winner of those voters then voting. And IRV satisfies that criterion - and the Exhaustive Ballot is the valid comparison for IRV (because that is the origin of IRV). The only difference is that to ensure the integrity of the count (accounting for all ballot papers at all stages of the count), the ballot papers (votes) of those who opt out at the later stages (rounds) are recorded as "non-transferable". But many think that later-no-harm is undesirable "Many" on this list may think that, but it is my experience of more than 45 years as a practical reformer explaining voting systems to real electors, that 'later no harm' does matter greatly to ordinary electors. If they think the voting system will not comply with 'later no harm', their immediate reaction is to say "I'm not going to mark a second or any further preference because that will hurt my first choice candidate - the one I most want to see elected." And of course, if you once depart from 'later no harm' you open the way to all sorts of strategic voting that just cannot work in a 'later no harm' IRV (or STV) public election with large numbers of voters. But many think that later-no-harm is undesirable because it interferes with the process of equitable compromise that is essential to the social cooperation that voting is supposed to facilitate. If I am negotiating with my neighbor, and his preferred option differs from mine, if I reveal that some compromise option is acceptable to me, before I'm certain that my favorite won't be chosen, then I may "harm" the chance of my favorite being chosen. If the method my neighbor and I used to help us make the decision *requires* later-no-harm, it will interfere with the negotiation process, make it more difficult to find mutually acceptable solutions. This is all irrelevant because in a public election there is no negotiation between voter and voter or between voter and candidate. I know that there are proposal for voting system that would incorporate "negotiation" of various kinds, but none of those was under discussion here. James Gilmour -- [EMAIL PROTECTED]people.clarityconnect.com/webpages3/davek
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
While I agree that "core support" is not always well measured by first choices (multiple clones can make all these clones appear to have little "core" support, where any of them would appear to have massive core support running alone). However, I think the concept of "core support" is still an important factor in multi-candidate elections. While I think Condorcet methods are much better than most methods, I remain concerned that it may, in fact, reward inoffensive candidates who successfully hide their policy positions, rather than just true "compromise" candidates. Voters tend to have clear opinions of candidates at the top and bottom of their preference rankings, leaving the door open for inoffensive candidates who have avoided revealing any controversial views, to become EVERY voter's second choice ("at least he must be better than X") and likely Condorcet winner. The voting method will cause candidates to tailor their campaigns accordingly, and I fear Condorcet encourages candidates to limit voter information and instead campaign with slogans like "I am the candidate who listen to you" and policy will become even LESS discussed in campaigns than is already the case in the U.S. So an important caveat to the assertion that "if a majority prefers Brad over Carter, this preference exists whether the voting system does anything with it"...is that the voting method in use will affect candidate behavior, and thus may result in Brad NOT being actually preferred over Carter under a different voting method. In other words, voter preferences among candidates (whether scores, or rankings) are not actually "given," as we assume when working out models (A>B>C), but will change depending on what campaign style is rewarded by the voting method in use. Terry Bouricius - Original Message - From: "Aaron Armitage" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> To: Sent: Sunday, July 27, 2008 2:45 PM Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting --- On Sun, 7/27/08, James Gilmour <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > > That is a consequence of your interpretation of how the > voting system is supposed to work and what the voting > system is supposed to > be doing. But that's not what IRV is about. As I said > in the previous message, the origins of IRV are in the > Exhaustive Ballot, > and in the Exhaustive Ballot there is no possibility of > looking "at the entire ballot". IRV is not about > satisfying a set of > criteria derived from social choice philosophy. > Of course every reason you might offer for choosing one system over another is based on an idea of what a reasonable decision rule for making collective decisions in very large groups should look like. This is true for IRV advocate no less than advocates for other systems; where the system came from is beside the point, especially since most jurisdictions have never used the Exhaustive Ballot. In an important respect, Condorcet is more natural than IRV: if a majority prefers Brad over Carter, this preference exists whether the voting system does anything with it, or even elicits enough information to determine that it exists. Condorcet simply discovers and applies this preference. IRV, on the other hand, elicits enough information to discover it exists, but may decide to ignore it based purely on procedural grounds. There are no good reasons for this, ever. "Core support" is a bogus reason: every time IRV chooses someone other than the plurality winner you're letting an overall majority trump a comparison of core supporters. But other times IRV will fail to do this, for reasons that simply don't exist apart from the system itself. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
--- On Sun, 7/27/08, James Gilmour <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > > That is a consequence of your interpretation of how the > voting system is supposed to work and what the voting > system is supposed to > be doing. But that's not what IRV is about. As I said > in the previous message, the origins of IRV are in the > Exhaustive Ballot, > and in the Exhaustive Ballot there is no possibility of > looking "at the entire ballot". IRV is not about > satisfying a set of > criteria derived from social choice philosophy. > Of course every reason you might offer for choosing one system over another is based on an idea of what a reasonable decision rule for making collective decisions in very large groups should look like. This is true for IRV advocate no less than advocates for other systems; where the system came from is beside the point, especially since most jurisdictions have never used the Exhaustive Ballot. In an important respect, Condorcet is more natural than IRV: if a majority prefers Brad over Carter, this preference exists whether the voting system does anything with it, or even elicits enough information to determine that it exists. Condorcet simply discovers and applies this preference. IRV, on the other hand, elicits enough information to discover it exists, but may decide to ignore it based purely on procedural grounds. There are no good reasons for this, ever. "Core support" is a bogus reason: every time IRV chooses someone other than the plurality winner you're letting an overall majority trump a comparison of core supporters. But other times IRV will fail to do this, for reasons that simply don't exist apart from the system itself. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Kristofer Munsterhjelm > Sent: Sunday, July 27, 2008 12:04 PM > To the degree that finding a good choice requires one to make a > compromise, and the method is supposed to be "as close to deliberation > as one can get", That is your interpretation of what the voting system is supposed to be. > it would have to look at the entire ballot. That is a consequence of your interpretation of how the voting system is supposed to work and what the voting system is supposed to be doing. But that's not what IRV is about. As I said in the previous message, the origins of IRV are in the Exhaustive Ballot, and in the Exhaustive Ballot there is no possibility of looking "at the entire ballot". IRV is not about satisfying a set of criteria derived from social choice philosophy. If you want something that only a social choice approach can deliver, then clearly IRV is not for you. But that does not make Kathy Dopp's original statement a valid criticism of IRV. > Now you may say that in real deliberation, as in a parliament, a participant > doesn't > know of future choices of the others -- but it lets them change their > minds between each balloting, which no ranked method can do. In a parliament it is more likely that the participants might know (or have a reasonable idea about) the future choices of other participants, but that's not relevant to voters in public elections. > The best a ranked method can do is to use preferences to find something > that can be agreed by all, and for that, Kathy's "LNH incompatibility" > argument holds. This has validity ONLY if you set the premise that a social choice solution is required of the voting system. I am well aware that the social choice approach dominates on this list, but that is not the only way of looking at voting systems. Nor does it validate a spurious argument. > Or more concrete: if you want the sort of compromise that Condorcet > gives (and you don't think that's a "weak centrist"), then you can't > have LNHarm. I don't think you can have LNHelp either, but > I'm not sure about that. I agree, but one could I think reasonably argue in the specific case of Condorcet that it does comply with LNHarm (at least, in Condorcet where there were no cycles or ties). Your higher preferences are always placed above your lower preferences in the Condorcet "head-to-head" comparisons. So YOUR lower preference can never harm YOUR higher preference. But that is certainly not true for many other social choice voting systems that use the preference information in a quite different way. > > Round 1 > > A 4,000 > > B 3,000 > > C 2,000 > > D 1,000 > > Total voting 10,000 > > > > Round 2 > > A 3,500 > > B 2,500 > > C 1,500 > > Total voting 7,500 > > > > Round 3 > > A 3,000 > > B 2,000 > > Total voting 5,000. > > > > A is the majority winner in Round 3, that is to say, the > majority winner of those voters then voting. And IRV satisfies that > > criterion - and the Exhaustive Ballot is the valid comparison for > > IRV (because that is the origin of IRV). The only difference is that > > to ensure the integrity of the count (accounting for all ballot papers > > at all stages of the count), the ballot papers (votes) of those who > > opt out at the later stages (rounds) are recorded as > > "non-transferable". > > Any elimination method can have that criterion. As long as you don't > break early, after sufficient eliminations there'll be only two > candidates remaining. At that point, they're either tied or one of them > has a majority of those voters when voting. It doesn't matter if you use > Borda-elimination, IRV, average Plurality elimination (Carey's Q > method), or the exhaustive version of Coombs. > > I seem to remember one on this list saying something to the effect of > "if you want to see how spurious this reasoning is, just take the > elimination process one step further and then you'll always have > unanimity! Except it isn't." This reasoning (in relation to the Exhaustive Ballot and to IRV) is not spurious, and if anyone seriously suggested it was spurious it would show just how desperate they had become in looking for arguments to bolster an unsustainable proposition. > > > "Many" on this list may think that, but it is my experience of more > > than 45 years as a practical reformer explaining voting systems to > > real electors, that 'later no harm' does matter greatly to ordinary > > electors. If they think the voting system will not comply with 'later > > no harm', their immediate reaction is to say "I'm not going to mark a > > second or any further preference because that will hurt my first > > choice candidate - the one I most want to see elected." And of > > course, if you once depart from 'later no harm' you open the way to > > all sorts of strategic voting that just cannot work in a 'later no > > harm' IRV (or STV) public election with large numbers of voters. > > If the met
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
James Gilmour wrote: Kathy Dopp > Sent: Saturday, June 21, 2008 5:20 AM "Later-No-Harm", however, is incompatible with the basic principles of majority rule, which requires compromise if decisions are to be made. That's because the peculiar design of sequential elimination guarantees -- if a majority is not required -- that a lower preference cannot harm a higher preference, because the lower preferences are only considered if a higher one is eliminated. The meaning of the second sentence isn't completely clear to me, but I am fairly sure there is a perverse interpretation of "majority" in the first sentence. An IRV election is an Exhaustive Ballot election contracted into one voting event, instead of being spread over several rounds in which the one candidate with fewest votes is eliminated at each round. It is no surprise that the numbers of voters participating varies from round to round - usually a progressive (or severe) decline. The votes in an Exhaustive Ballot election might look like this: To the degree that finding a good choice requires one to make a compromise, and the method is supposed to be "as close to deliberation as one can get", it would have to look at the entire ballot. Now you may say that in real deliberation, as in a parliament, a participant doesn't know of future choices of the others -- but it lets them change their minds between each balloting, which no ranked method can do. The best a ranked method can do is to use preferences to find something that can be agreed by all, and for that, Kathy's "LNH incompatibility" argument holds. Or more concrete: if you want the sort of compromise that Condorcet gives (and you don't think that's a "weak centrist"), then you can't have LNHarm. I don't think you can have LNHelp either, but I'm not sure about that. Round 1 A 4,000 B 3,000 C 2,000 D 1,000 Total voting 10,000 Round 2 A 3,500 B 2,500 C 1,500 Total voting 7,500 Round 3 A 3,000 B 2,000 Total voting 5,000. A is the majority winner in Round 3, that is to say, the majority winner of those voters then voting. And IRV satisfies that criterion - and the Exhaustive Ballot is the valid comparison for IRV (because that is the origin of IRV). The only difference is that to ensure the integrity of the count (accounting for all ballot papers at all stages of the count), the ballot papers (votes) of those who opt out at the later stages (rounds) are recorded as "non-transferable". Any elimination method can have that criterion. As long as you don't break early, after sufficient eliminations there'll be only two candidates remaining. At that point, they're either tied or one of them has a majority of those voters when voting. It doesn't matter if you use Borda-elimination, IRV, average Plurality elimination (Carey's Q method), or the exhaustive version of Coombs. I seem to remember one on this list saying something to the effect of "if you want to see how spurious this reasoning is, just take the elimination process one step further and then you'll always have unanimity! Except it isn't." "Many" on this list may think that, but it is my experience of more than 45 years as a practical reformer explaining voting systems to real electors, that 'later no harm' does matter greatly to ordinary electors. If they think the voting system will not comply with 'later no harm', their immediate reaction is to say "I'm not going to mark a second or any further preference because that will hurt my first choice candidate - the one I most want to see elected." And of course, if you once depart from 'later no harm' you open the way to all sorts of strategic voting that just cannot work in a 'later no harm' IRV (or STV) public election with large numbers of voters. If the method fails LNHarm about as often as it fails LNHelp, then that argument should fail, because bullet voting may harm your other choices as much (or more, no way to know in general) as consistently voting all of them will. Ceteris paribus, it's better to have a method that passes both of the LNHs than neither (since you get strategy in the latter case), but the hit you take might not be as serious as it seems at first. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Kathy Dopp > Sent: Saturday, June 21, 2008 5:20 AM > "Later-No-Harm", however, is incompatible with the basic > principles of majority rule, which requires compromise if > decisions are to be made. That's because the peculiar design > of sequential elimination guarantees -- if a majority is not > required -- that a lower preference cannot harm a higher > preference, because the lower preferences are only considered > if a higher one is eliminated. The meaning of the second sentence isn't completely clear to me, but I am fairly sure there is a perverse interpretation of "majority" in the first sentence. An IRV election is an Exhaustive Ballot election contracted into one voting event, instead of being spread over several rounds in which the one candidate with fewest votes is eliminated at each round. It is no surprise that the numbers of voters participating varies from round to round - usually a progressive (or severe) decline. The votes in an Exhaustive Ballot election might look like this: Round 1 A 4,000 B 3,000 C 2,000 D 1,000 Total voting 10,000 Round 2 A 3,500 B 2,500 C 1,500 Total voting 7,500 Round 3 A 3,000 B 2,000 Total voting 5,000. A is the majority winner in Round 3, that is to say, the majority winner of those voters then voting. And IRV satisfies that criterion - and the Exhaustive Ballot is the valid comparison for IRV (because that is the origin of IRV). The only difference is that to ensure the integrity of the count (accounting for all ballot papers at all stages of the count), the ballot papers (votes) of those who opt out at the later stages (rounds) are recorded as "non-transferable". > But many think that > later-no-harm is undesirable "Many" on this list may think that, but it is my experience of more than 45 years as a practical reformer explaining voting systems to real electors, that 'later no harm' does matter greatly to ordinary electors. If they think the voting system will not comply with 'later no harm', their immediate reaction is to say "I'm not going to mark a second or any further preference because that will hurt my first choice candidate - the one I most want to see elected." And of course, if you once depart from 'later no harm' you open the way to all sorts of strategic voting that just cannot work in a 'later no harm' IRV (or STV) public election with large numbers of voters. > But many think that > later-no-harm is undesirable because it interferes with the > process of equitable compromise that is essential to the > social cooperation that voting is supposed to facilitate. If > I am negotiating with my neighbor, and his preferred option > differs from mine, if I reveal that some compromise option is > acceptable to me, before I'm certain that my favorite won't > be chosen, then I may "harm" the chance of my favorite being > chosen. If the method my neighbor and I used to help us make > the decision *requires* later-no-harm, it will interfere with > the negotiation process, make it more difficult to find > mutually acceptable solutions. This is all irrelevant because in a public election there is no negotiation between voter and voter or between voter and candidate. I know that there are proposal for voting system that would incorporate "negotiation" of various kinds, but none of those was under discussion here. James Gilmour No virus found in this outgoing message. Checked by AVG. Version: 7.5.526 / Virus Database: 270.5.6/1574 - Release Date: 25/07/2008 16:27 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Jul 5, 2008, at 6:13 AM, James Gilmour wrote: Abd ul-Rahman Lomax > Sent: Monday, June 23, 2008 7:19 PM But, in the United States, where I live, IRV isn't replacing pure FPTP. It's replacing Top Two Runoff (TTR). And it is pretty clear to me that TTR is superior in just about every way, I suspect all such judgements must in the end be matters of opinion, but the French Presidential election of 2002 shows the major failing of Top-Two Run-Off. I think many commentators would take the view that IRV would have been superior to TTRO in that election. Had that election been by Exhaustive Ballot (eliminating one candidate in each round) or by IRV, I am fairly sure that the final contest would not have been between Chirac and Le Pen. It is also reasonable to suggest that, in such circumstances, the eventual winner would not have been Chirac, but a candidate much more representative of the voters. The implications of a different result for French politics during the subsequent five years would be pure speculation on my part, so I'll leave it there. An additional word on IRV vs TTR in San Francisco. One of the main arguments for moving from TTR to IRV in SF was the extremely low turnout in runoff elections--I suppose that's the TTR equivalent of massive ballot truncation. I don't have the figures at hand, but turnout for SF runoffs has been laughably low. The limitation to three rankings is a function of the existing mark- sense voting equipment. Presumably this limitation will be addressed in time. While SF IRV elections are nominally non-partisan, there are effectively three (sometimes four) parties: business-oriented Democrats, progressive Democrats, Greens, and from time to time Republicans. The boundaries are fuzzy, and coalitions are fluid. With, as Abd points out, as many as 22 candidates on the ballot, this environment seems far from ideal for TTR. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Abd ul-Rahman Lomax > Sent: Monday, June 23, 2008 7:19 PM > But, in the United States, where I live, IRV > isn't replacing pure FPTP. It's replacing Top Two > Runoff (TTR). And it is pretty clear to me that > TTR is superior in just about every way, I suspect all such judgements must in the end be matters of opinion, but the French Presidential election of 2002 shows the major failing of Top-Two Run-Off. I think many commentators would take the view that IRV would have been superior to TTRO in that election. Had that election been by Exhaustive Ballot (eliminating one candidate in each round) or by IRV, I am fairly sure that the final contest would not have been between Chirac and Le Pen. It is also reasonable to suggest that, in such circumstances, the eventual winner would not have been Chirac, but a candidate much more representative of the voters. The implications of a different result for French politics during the subsequent five years would be pure speculation on my part, so I'll leave it there. James Gilmour No virus found in this outgoing message. Checked by AVG. Version: 7.5.526 / Virus Database: 270.4.5/1535 - Release Date: 04/07/2008 17:03 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
At 01:09 PM 6/23/2008, Stéphane Rouillon wrote: After a nice discussion about keeping cool, usually a great idea if one can manage it. On the other hand, sometimes getting a little hot can get things done. So now can you acknoledge that IRV is better than FPTP ? I can accpet IRV being worst than any other method (even if I do not agree all the time) but FPTP has to be worst! I would once have agreed with this, and, still, under some conditions, would agree that IRV is, in some ways, better than Plurality. However, it also can be worse in some ways, and there's the rub: what is the balance? Political activists, once they've made a decision -- and they tend not to be the best of decision-makers, not thoroughly investigating before deciding -- they become like a guided missile that can't be recalled, it will continue trying to hit its target even if it would become obvious, to an intelligent pilot, that it is an Iranian Airbus rather than a military jet. But, in the United States, where I live, IRV isn't replacing pure FPTP. It's replacing Top Two Runoff (TTR). And it is pretty clear to me that TTR is superior in just about every way, that common arguments used to claim the reverse are spurious, and that the one possible superiority, cost, becomes, actually, an argument for different reforms, not IRV, with its quirks and its typical reproduction of Plurality results in nonpartisan elections, and, in partisan elections, its reproduction of TTR problems without the ameliorating factors. Why is IRV being pushed in the U.S. as if it were a positive reform? The initiative did not come from voting systems experts. It came from political activists, interested in proportional representation. The history is pretty clear: There was a conference in the early 1990s to consider how to bring PR to the U.S. Out of that conference (but not by the conference itself, it was a small group who acted on their own), came the formation of the Center for Proportional Representation, I think it was called. At some point, I'm not clear when, they changed their name to the Center for Voting and Democracy, to represent a wider focus and to match the strategy that had been developed. Possibly the best method in common use for Proportional Representation is Single Transferable Vote. We now know how to do it better, to be sure, but STV is pretty good, and it gets better the more members districts have. Now, problem is, STV is a complicated voting system, more complicated even than IRV, because the vote transfers get pretty hairy as members are elected. (I'm assuming that one of the better methods is being used. STV if it is just the "top" candidates isn't so good, it's going to imitate, more or less, plurality-at-large.) This was considered an obstacle, and correctly so. There are other methods which aren't so difficult, that can be even more accurately proportional and simpler for voters, but remember, these were not voting systems experts and they didn't want to invent something new. (Though, in my opinion, the *best* method, and surely the simplest, would be Asset Voting, as first described by Lewis Carroll in the early 1880s and reinvented by Mike Ossipoff, Warren Smith, and possibly others, recently.) What to do? I can imagine the excitement when the name "Instant runoff voting" was proposed. Runoff voting was in used in the U.S., and it costs money to hold those runoff elections. The extra cost of STV could be justified by the cost savings from runoffs. So if they could get jurisdictions using top two runoff to establish IRV, it would then be a smaller step for these jurisdictions to move to proportional representation. It was a political strategy, and it did not take into account the serious problems of IRV. For starters, IRV is used in two-party systems, and its effect is to protect the major parties from election spoilage by minor parties. It does allow third parties to exist, but makes it very difficult for them to actually thrive. Because of PR in the Senate, I think it is, they can exercise some power. But they don't win seats in the House where IRV is used. (I'm could be getting things mixed up, but we have Australian readers who, I'm sure, will correct me if I get it wrong.) STV is a good multiwinner method, as I mentioned, for proportional representation, because the members it elects are clearly good choices, except for the last one. When you are electing many members, that the last member can be a bit off doesn't matter so much. But when that's the only one elected Further, IRV as generally used in Australia (Preferential Voting) is different from IRV as being implemented here. First of all, full ranking of all candidates is required, or the ballot is informal and is not counted. This has two consequences: a majority is always found, but the majority can be, to some extent, coerced, and "donkey voting" is com
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Jun 26, 2008, at 0:54 , Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote: Note that the utilities of B and C were 123 and 99. I didn't anchor the scale in any way but numbers around 100 could still be "above average politician". "Above average" among what sample? Certainly not this one! The sample was the politicians of your country (+ other candidates). Maybe their utility is typically around 30. (Utility 543 was possibly for yourself or your friend.) I think three frontrunners is not a very distant scenario. I also think spoilers are quite possible in Range and Approval. Some spoiler scenarios were already mentioned in this thread. You also already replied to Chris Benham on the McCain-Obama-Clinton example in another mail (and therefore I'll try to be brief here). While three frontrunners is certainly possible in theory, it's rare in a two-party system, it happens in certain ways. But I assume the idea was to enrich the typical "two parties, two candidates and minor spoilers" set-up. If the small party candidates will stay minor candidates with no chances of being elected forever then we could use e.g. a method where the ballot has first one option, D or R, and then a write-in field where you can write any minor candidate name (or several) but that field will be ignored in the counting process. I mean that there must be at least three viable candidates in some elections if any any of the minor candidates are ever expected to raise from the "joke category" upwards (well, unless the changes always happen so quickly that the old leading candidates/ parties are already at the "joke category" at the time of the election.) Juho ___ The all-new Yahoo! Mail goes wherever you go - free your email address from your Internet provider. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
On Jun 25, 2008, at 4:26 , Kathy Dopp wrote: 1. the method of keeping my house cool in summer and warm in winter (I do set a furnace to 64 degrees F in the winter days and 53 degrees F at night but the house usually stays much warmer) is low-tech and is architectural (I did my own architecture) A massive pile of rocks inside the house? 2. requires some human intervention (perhaps 3 or 4 minutes twice per day). Let the sun in, stop the heat going out, let the coolness of night get in, lock the heat in? Any guesses on why my grass stays green without any water in a very dry climate, although all my neighbors do water their lawns? Maybe lots of water inside the house instead of stone? Sorry for not including any EM related test in this mail. Juho ___ The all-new Yahoo! Mail goes wherever you go - free your email address from your Internet provider. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
At 02:45 PM 6/24/2008, Juho wrote: On Jun 24, 2008, at 3:10 , Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote: Or if A and B are the strongest candidates then maybe strategically A=10, B=0, C=0. In Approval the voter might vote A=1, B=0, C=0. Or if B and C are the strongest candidates then maybe A=1, B=1, C=0. If it were me, I might be buying tickets out of the country. That is *really* bad. *Sincere normalized rating, unmodified by election probabilities, is almost zero.* Voters with utilities like this, if they believe A doesn't have a prayer, tend to not vote. Note that the utilities of B and C were 123 and 99. I didn't anchor the scale in any way but numbers around 100 could still be "above average politician". "Above average" among what sample? Certainly not this one! I think three frontrunners is not a very distant scenario. I also think spoilers are quite possible in Range and Approval. Some spoiler scenarios were already mentioned in this thread. You also already replied to Chris Benham on the McCain-Obama-Clinton example in another mail (and therefore I'll try to be brief here). While three frontrunners is certainly possible in theory, it's rare in a two-party system, it happens in certain ways. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
At 01:51 PM 6/24/2008, Chris Benham wrote: - Original Message From: Abd ul-Rahman Lomax <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> No. That fight is over the Democratic Party nomination and endorsement. It means that the whole apparatus of the Democratic Party is devoted to one candidate, which is, of course, strongly in the interest of the Democratic Party. You know that that is somewhat beside the point. But I get the impression that most of the money goes directly to the campaigns of the individual candidates and that the media attention is mainly focused on the individual candidates, rather than say "the policies of the Democratic Party" irrespective of who is their endorsed candidate. Actually not beside the point. Media attention is, of course, focused on the candidates. *In the primary.* And then on one candidate from both major parties *in the general election.* If we were to try to combine the primaries with the general election, which is what happened in Louisiana, we'd have similar problems with vote-splitting. Primaries aren't an indispensable part of the U.S. political system; used to be that state parties elected delegates, and delegates made the decision. It was actually a better system, in my opinion. Decided whom to run in a general election is a terribly complicated decision, the question isn't only "who is best," but also "who is electable." Instead of expensive primary races, I'd focus on much cheaper methods of making sure that the party convention is very representative and trustworthy. Guess what method(s) I'd use, Chris? Then, the drama of the convention brings free publicity, much better than happens now with rubber-stamp conventions where nothing really exciting happens, they are just big celebrations. And the real money is then saved for the real election. While it's true that the primary system allows a candidate to "show his or her stuff" under difficult conditions, one single race isn't really enough to test that well. >Why not simply endorse both candidates? After all, one cannot >possibly spoil the election for the other because Approval has >no spoiler problem. Voters simply approve candidates or not >completely regardless of what other candidates are on the ballot, >right? Sure. If we imagine that somehow the parties have decided not to nominate candidates, snowballs in hell nevermind, running both Obama and Clinton against a single McCain would probaby result in very common double-voting. Now, if Obama and Clinton heavily campaign against each other, slinging mud, etc, trying to convince the voters that the other one is practically the devil, nobody would benefit from this except McCain. Which is quite why we don't do things this way. Parties in Australia don't run multiple candidates for the same single-winner office, do they? No, but very closely allied candidates sometimes run against each other, such as a candidate each from both Coalition partners (the Liberals and the Nationals). I consider the Coalition partners to be the same party, effectively, and usually they don't run two candidates in the same race. It would be interesting to see what happened where they do. It could be that the pact broke down, or it could be that it was safe. With IRV, a certain amount of this could be done safely. But if there was a real race with the other leg of the tripod, the splitting of campaign effort could result in a bad result. I think that's important to realize. It's not just what's on the ballot and how the votes are counted. That may be less than half of what's involved. I don't see how the split-vote problem in Approval is a "very different animal than the split vote problem in Plurality". To me it is just much less severe. The "split-vote problem in IRV" is much less and normally unnoticable. You have to understand how Plurality works: it works through processes outside the ballot, it works through party nominations. Split vote happens when a third party throws a monkey wrench in the process. Under those conditions, Approval fixes the problem quite as well as IRV, without the fuss. Bucklin *clearly* fixes it. If a supporter of a third party isn't going to add an additional vote in Bucklin, they are going to truncate in IRV. Pretty much the same with Approval. However, what happens if that third party gets on the order of one-third the first-preference vote? This is where IRV can clearly break down. Approval as a plurality method can do poorly as well, though not generally as poorly. And, of course, if a majority is required, Approval should come out just fine. I think in the US scenario with voluntary voting, if both Clinton and Obama ran McCain would have less chance of winning with IRV than with Approval or Range or Bucklin or any other reasonable method that springs to mind. This is because both Clinton and Obama have their enthusiastic supporters some of whom wouldn't bother voting if their favourite wasn't runn
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
On Tue, Jun 24, 2008 at 2:43 PM, > Date: Tue, 24 Jun 2008 21:45:56 +0300 > From: Juho <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting > On Jun 24, 2008, at 7:41 , Kathy Dopp wrote: > >> How does the grass in my lawn stay green when I never water or irrigate it >> and I live in a very dry climate? >> >> How does my house heat up to 80 degrees Farenheit inside during the winter >> even when it is below freezing outside - without using any fossil fuels and >> without burning any wood? > > Since you live (at least relatively) close to Yellowstone you might > have one cold and one hot well available. The grass would also > benefit of that, unless it is made of plastic. > Hi Juho OK. Another good guess however it would have to be an awfully long pipe to reach a hotsprings from my house because the nearest one is over 20 miles drive away or over a huge mountain pass about 2,500 ft higher than my home which is only open in the summers. Shall I give you the answers? Hint: 1. the method of keeping my house cool in summer and warm in winter (I do set a furnace to 64 degrees F in the winter days and 53 degrees F at night but the house usually stays much warmer) is low-tech and is architectural (I did my own architecture) 2. requires some human intervention (perhaps 3 or 4 minutes twice per day). 3. the climate here in Utah is very different from yours in England. It is much dryer here. Any guesses on why my grass stays green without any water in a very dry climate, although all my neighbors do water their lawns? BTW, on voting issues, I updated this today in preparation for a radio interview. There are few places that have more secretive elections than where I live now and this is my proposal for fixing that: http://utahcountvotes.org/legislature/UTLegislativeElectionReform.pdf Kathy Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham) (tidied-up re-post)
At 12:55 AM 6/23/2008, Chris Benham wrote: >Kathy, > >Imagine that Approval is used to elect the US President and >as in the current campaign the Republicans are fielding one >candidate, McCain. Does that mean that the big fight for the >Democrat nomination between Clinton and Obama we've just >seen would in the Approval scenario be completely unnecessary? Abd: "No. That fight is over the Democratic Party nomination and endorsement. It means that the whole apparatus of the Democratic Party is devoted to one candidate, which is, of course, strongly in the interest of the Democratic Party." Chris: You know that that is somewhat beside the point. But I get the impression that most of the money goes directly to the campaigns of the individual candidates and that the media attention is mainly focused on the individual candidates, rather than say "the policies of the Democratic Party" irrespective of who is their endorsed candidate. >Why not simply endorse both candidates? After all, one cannot >possibly spoil the election for the other because Approval has >no spoiler problem. Voters simply approve candidates or not >completely regardless of what other candidates are on the ballot, >right? Abd: "Sure. If we imagine that somehow the parties have decided not to nominate candidates, snowballs in hell nevermind, running both Obama and Clinton against a single McCain would probaby result in very common double-voting. Now, if Obama and Clinton heavily campaign against each other, slinging mud, etc, trying to convince the voters that the other one is practically the devil, nobody would benefit from this except McCain. Which is quite why we don't do things this way. Parties in Australia don't run multiple candidates for the same single-winner office, do they?" Chris: No, but very closely allied candidates sometimes run against each other, such as a candidate each from both Coalition partners (the Liberals and the Nationals). Abd: "The problem, were it Approval, wouldn't be so much the voting method. (Which, by the way, loses most of the problems it has if a majority is required or there is a runoff). It would be the rest of the system, the process by which voters become informed, or deluded, depending on your point of view. >I think that in practical effect Approval does have a "spoiler" or >split-vote problem that would be sufficient for the Democrats to >still want to endorse one candidate only. There are *lots* of reasons why the Democrats would want to do that. Or any party. This is a red herring argument. The "split vote problem" in Approval is a very different animal than the split vote problem in Plurality, or, for that matter, in IRV." Chris: I don't see how the split-vote problem in Approval is a "very different animal than the split vote problem in Plurality". To me it is just much less severe. The "split-vote problem in IRV" is much less and normally unnoticable. I think in the US scenario with voluntary voting, if both Clinton and Obama ran McCain would have less chance of winning with IRV than with Approval or Range or Bucklin or any other reasonable method that springs to mind. This is because both Clinton and Obama have their enthusiastic supporters some of whom wouldn't bother voting if their favourite wasn't running, but if their favourite was running they would show up and (at the urging of their favourite) rank both Clinton and Obama above McCain. IRV, meeting both Majority for Solid Coalitions and Later-no-Harm has no "defection incentive" like other methods. http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2006-November/018844.html >What I actually wrote in my initial post on the 5 "fairness >principles in your paper (regarding IIA): > >In practical effect *no* method meets this.Approval and Range can >be said to meet >Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) only if the votes are >interpreted as the voters giving >ratings on some fixed scale that is independent of the actual candidates. Abd: "No, that's not correct. Perhaps it would be useful if you actually state the version of IIA you are using. Usually, it refers to adding or subtracting a candidate without changing the "preference order" of the other candidates, but if you are going to use it with Range and Approval, you have to modify it; the basic modification is that the Range Votes or Approval Votes don't change, and all that happens is that a new candidate is added to the ballot or taken off the ballot." Chris: If the voters rate the candidates on some fixed scale that is independent of the candidates, then by definition the Range or Approval votes would be unchanged by adding (or removing) a candidate. What's "not correct" about it? Abd: "If voters are allowed to actually change their votes, *no method meets IIA.* Simple proof: there is a candidate whose name is a trigger for a long-hidden internal program that causes human beings to fall i
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting - Not What It Seems
Hello, Continuing my commentry on Kathy Dopp's anti-IRV paper, under "Flaws of Instant Runoff Voting" we find: "13. voters may not be allowed to participate in the final selection round of an IRV election because all their choices were eliminated before the last counting round." The only way voters may "not be allowed to participate in the final selection round of an IRV election" is if they are restricted from ranking as many candidates as they wish, a restriction that I strongly oppose (and doesn't exist in Australia). Presumably Kathy thinks it is a bad thing that some voters aren't allowed to participate in the final IRV selection round, so we can logically infer that Kathy prefers IRV with unrestricted ranking to IRV with restricted ranking, right? Wrong. Further down the paper she writes:"Restricting the ranking depth of ranked choice ballots could improve IRV methods by reducing noise and making it easier for voters." Kathy, your hero Abd ul Lomax disagrees! He recently wrote: "If you are going to use a preferential ballot, with STV as the method, allowing full ranking is important." http://groups.yahoo.com/group/RangeVoting/message/8276 "STV" stands for 'Single Transferable Vote'. IRV is single-winner STV. Chris BenhamNot all voters or ballots are treated equally: Unlike with actual runoff elections, some IRV Get the name you always wanted with the new y7mail email address. www.yahoo7.com.au/mail Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
On Jun 24, 2008, at 7:41 , Kathy Dopp wrote: How does the grass in my lawn stay green when I never water or irrigate it and I live in a very dry climate? How does my house heat up to 80 degrees Farenheit inside during the winter even when it is below freezing outside - without using any fossil fuels and without burning any wood? Since you live (at least relatively) close to Yellowstone you might have one cold and one hot well available. The grass would also benefit of that, unless it is made of plastic. Juho ___ Try the all-new Yahoo! Mail. "The New Version is radically easier to use" The Wall Street Journal http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Jun 24, 2008, at 3:10 , Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote: Or if A and B are the strongest candidates then maybe strategically A=10, B=0, C=0. In Approval the voter might vote A=1, B=0, C=0. Or if B and C are the strongest candidates then maybe A=1, B=1, C=0. If it were me, I might be buying tickets out of the country. That is *really* bad. *Sincere normalized rating, unmodified by election probabilities, is almost zero.* Voters with utilities like this, if they believe A doesn't have a prayer, tend to not vote. Note that the utilities of B and C were 123 and 99. I didn't anchor the scale in any way but numbers around 100 could still be "above average politician". The sincere opinions/utilities A=543, B=123, C=99 were valid in all the cases but typical voter behaviour in Range and Approval was to normalize the vote and maybe to vote strategically depending on who the strongest candidates are. The ratings given to the candidates varied although the opinions/utilities stayed the same all the time. This changing behaviour may sometimes lead to one of the candidates being a spoiler. Plurality, if voters vote sincerely, guarantees the spoiler effect. It's part of the method. Range allows something different, but nobody coerces voters. *Voters* can decide to act in ways that mimic the spoiler effect, but it's not intrinsic to the method, and if voters vote with any reasonable understanding at all, there is no spoiler effect with any significant frequency with Range or Approval. How many voters in 2000 would not have known that Bush and Gore were the frontrunners? The decision in Approval is quite simple: if you want to influence the election, vote for one of the frontrunners, period. Indeed, it gets tricky when there are three frontrunners, but that is vanishingly rare in the U.S. I think three frontrunners is not a very distant scenario. I also think spoilers are quite possible in Range and Approval. Some spoiler scenarios were already mentioned in this thread. You also already replied to Chris Benham on the McCain-Obama-Clinton example in another mail (and therefore I'll try to be brief here). The Democrats would do wisely if they would not nominate the second candidate as a "spoiler" even if the campaign would not be a mud slinging campaign. And Clinton would do wisely (from the D party point of view) if she would not accept a nomination by some other party close to Democrats. And in a close election any candidate close to Democrats would probably do wisely (from D point of view) if he/ she didn't join the race (since Republicans are more likely to rate all Democrat resembling candidates at 0 than Democrat like voters would rate all Democrat like candidates at max points). Juho ___ Now you can scan emails quickly with a reading pane. Get the new Yahoo! Mail. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
- Original Message From: Abd ul-Rahman Lomax <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> To: Chris Benham <[EMAIL PROTECTED]>; EM Sent: Tuesday, 24 June, 2008 10:01:46 AM Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham) At 12:55 AM 6/23/2008, Chris Benham wrote: >Kathy, > >Imagine that Approval is used to elect the US President and >as in the current campaign the Republicans are fielding one >candidate, McCain. Does that mean that the big fight for the >Democrat nomination between Clinton and Obama we've just >seen would in the Approval scenario be completely unnecessary? No. That fight is over the Democratic Party nomination and endorsement. It means that the whole apparatus of the Democratic Party is devoted to one candidate, which is, of course, strongly in the interest of the Democratic Party. You know that that is somewhat beside the point. But I get the impression that most of the money goes directly to the campaigns of the individual candidates and that the media attention is mainly focused on the individual candidates, rather than say "the policies of the Democratic Party" irrespective of who is their endorsed candidate. >Why not simply endorse both candidates? After all, one cannot >possibly spoil the election for the other because Approval has >no spoiler problem. Voters simply approve candidates or not >completely regardless of what other candidates are on the ballot, >right? Sure. If we imagine that somehow the parties have decided not to nominate candidates, snowballs in hell nevermind, running both Obama and Clinton against a single McCain would probaby result in very common double-voting. Now, if Obama and Clinton heavily campaign against each other, slinging mud, etc, trying to convince the voters that the other one is practically the devil, nobody would benefit from this except McCain. Which is quite why we don't do things this way. Parties in Australia don't run multiple candidates for the same single-winner office, do they? No, but very closely allied candidates sometimes run against each other, such as a candidate each from both Coalition partners (the Liberals and the Nationals). The problem, were it Approval, wouldn't be so much the voting method. (Which, by the way, loses most of the problems it has if a majority is required or there is a runoff). It would be the rest of the system, the process by which voters become informed, or deluded, depending on your point of view. >I think that in practical effect Approval does have a "spoiler" or >split-vote problem that would be sufficient for the Democrats to >still want to endorse one candidate only. There are *lots* of reasons why the Democrats would want to do that. Or any party. This is a red herring argument. The "split vote problem" in Approval is a very different animal than the split vote problem in Plurality, or, for that matter, in IRV. I don't see how the split-vote problem in Approval is a "very different animal than the split vote problem in Plurality". To me it is just much less severe. The "split-vote problem in IRV" is much less and normally unnoticable. I think in the US scenario with voluntary voting, if both Clinton and Obama ran McCain would have less chance of winning with IRV than with Approval or Range or Bucklin or any other reasonable method that springs to mind. This is because both Clinton and Obama have their enthusiastic supporters some of whom wouldn't bother voting if their favourite wasn't running, but if their favourite was running they would show up and (at the urging of their favourite) rank both Clinton and Obama above McCain. IRV, meeting both Majority for Solid Coalitions and Later-no-Harm has no "defection incentive" like other methods. http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2006-November/018844.html >What I actually wrote in my initial post on the 5 "fairness >principles in your paper (regarding IIA): > >In practical effect *no* method meets this.Approval and Range can >be said to meet >Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) only if the votes are >interpreted as the voters giving >ratings on some fixed scale that is independent of the actual candidates. No, that's not correct. Perhaps it would be useful if you actually state the version of IIA you are using. Usually, it refers to adding or subtracting a candidate without changing the "preference order" of the other candidates, but if you are going to use it with Range and Approval, you have to modify it; the basic modification is that the Range Votes or Approval Votes don't change, and all that happens is that a new candidate is added to the ballot or taken off the ballot. If the voters rate the candidates on some fixed scale that is
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
On Mon, Jun 23, 2008 at 11:09 AM, Stéphane Rouillon <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > Finally a question for my vacations! > > I would use geothermia. Simply dig a long tube in the ground with the two > halfs at different underground level and put the ends at differents levels > of your house. It should pump cool air > from the underground to your basement, when it gets hot then to the upstairs > where it goes through the second end far underground and back in the cycle. > what is important is that the length > of the underground tubes is long enough so the pumping effect can drag the > hot air form upstairs > stronger then the boussinesq force keeps it elevated (hot air is lighter). Hi Stephane, What a great idea. Would that work? Or would one need to pump fluid or to use a fan to pump air around such tubes into the ground? I like it. However, that is *not* how I keep my house below 68/74 approx degrees downstairs/upstairs. It was in the 90s again here today and my house inside is now 68/72 degrees downstairs/upstairs even though I have no air conditioning or swamp cooler. Hints: 1. I do not live in a cave . . 2. Components of how my house stays cool in summer are related to how it warms itself without a furnace or a heater of any kind in winter. 3. I live in a high mountain desert. > > So now can you acknoledge that IRV is better than FPTP ? I just counted to see how many of the "17 flaws of IRV" listed in my paper, also apply to plurality voting - only 3. So, since IRV (to my count) has at least 14 flaws that plurality voting does not have, and only 3 benefits over plurality (including one benefit that is only a perceived rather thant an actual benefit), I would say that plurality voting is far superior to IRV IMO. My paper's URL is here: http://electionarchive.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf > I can accpet IRV being worst than any other method (even if I do not agree > all the time) > but FPTP has to be worst! Nope. IRV is the worst voting method I have seen, except for the one that Chris showed us on this list of converting voter ratings to approval votes for N-1 candidates, but then I haven't seen all the voting methods people may have dreamed up - and do not want to. I would like to see a picture of your idea for digging holes with pipes to keep houses cool as my current method only works to the great extent that it does in certain climes. The area were I live is only about 17 miles away as the crow flies from some hot springs (volcanic activity) beneath the crust where it looks from the lay of the land like the entire town is situated in an old small caldera volcano, so those homes in that nearby town could probably not use your method. I live a few hundred miles or more South of Yellowstone Park. I believe that Yellowstone is the largest known caldera volcano in the world. When Yellowstone explodes again, hot lava may land on my roof, and I would try to escape by driving South since the ash would travel East with the Jet Stream air current around the globe. However, under and around my town are old Silver mines that do have cool 50 degree air in them, but I live in a meadow. After you solve the first puzzle, I have two other puzzles for you. How does the grass in my lawn stay green when I never water or irrigate it and I live in a very dry climate? How does my house heat up to 80 degrees Farenheit inside during the winter even when it is below freezing outside - without using any fossil fuels and without burning any wood? Kathy Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Sun, 22 Jun 2008 21:55:20 -0700 (PDT) Chris Benham wrote: Kathy, Imagine that Approval is used to elect the US President and as in the current campaign the Republicans are fielding one candidate, McCain. Does that mean that the big fight for the Democrat nomination between Clinton and Obama we've just seen would in the Approval scenario be completely unnecessary? Why not simply endorse both candidates? After all, one cannot possibly spoil the election for the other because Approval has no spoiler problem. Voters simply approve candidates or not completely regardless of what other candidates are on the ballot, right? BUT, Approval is unable to be told that, while both Democrats are seen as better than McCain, one is MUCH better than the other. I think that in practical effect Approval does have a "spoiler" or split-vote problem that would be sufficient for the Democrats to still want to endorse one candidate only. What I actually wrote in my initial post on the 5 "fairness principles in your paper (regarding IIA): In practical effect *no* method meets this.Approval and Range can be said to meet Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) only if the votes are interpreted as the voters giving ratings on some fixed scale that is independent of the actual candidates. On this perverse interpretation Approval and Range do not reduce to FPP in the 2 candidate election, in violation of Dopp's "fairness principle 4": "Any candidate who is the favorite [first] choice of a majority of voters should win." (approval or non-approval counts as "rating" on a 2-point scale). This latter point you seem to implicitly acknowledge in one of your recent posts: "In actuality, if these are the same voters both before and after you add another candidate C, then your first example with two candidates, to be consistent with your second example with three candidates should be: 25 A 40 AB 35 B so that B wins in the first example AND in the second when another candidate is introduced." Chris Benham -- [EMAIL PROTECTED]people.clarityconnect.com/webpages3/davek Dave Ketchum 108 Halstead Ave, Owego, NY 13827-1708 607-687-5026 Do to no one what you would not want done to you. If you want peace, work for justice. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
At 12:55 AM 6/23/2008, Chris Benham wrote: Kathy, Imagine that Approval is used to elect the US President and as in the current campaign the Republicans are fielding one candidate, McCain. Does that mean that the big fight for the Democrat nomination between Clinton and Obama we've just seen would in the Approval scenario be completely unnecessary? No. That fight is over the Democratic Party nomination and endorsement. It means that the whole apparatus of the Democratic Party is devoted to one candidate, which is, of course, strongly in the interest of the Democratic Party. Why not simply endorse both candidates? After all, one cannot possibly spoil the election for the other because Approval has no spoiler problem. Voters simply approve candidates or not completely regardless of what other candidates are on the ballot, right? Sure. If we imagine that somehow the parties have decided not to nominate candidates, snowballs in hell nevermind, running both Obama and Clinton against a single McCain would probaby result in very common double-voting. Now, if Obama and Clinton heavily campaign against each other, slinging mud, etc, trying to convince the voters that the other one is practically the devil, nobody would benefit from this except McCain. Which is quite why we don't do things this way. Parties in Australia don't run multiple candidates for the same single-winner office, do they? The problem, were it Approval, wouldn't be so much the voting method. (Which, by the way, loses most of the problems it has if a majority is required or there is a runoff). It would be the rest of the system, the process by which voters become informed, or deluded, depending on your point of view. I think that in practical effect Approval does have a "spoiler" or split-vote problem that would be sufficient for the Democrats to still want to endorse one candidate only. There are *lots* of reasons why the Democrats would want to do that. Or any party. This is a red herring argument. The "split vote problem" in Approval is a very different animal than the split vote problem in Plurality, or, for that matter, in IRV. What I actually wrote in my initial post on the 5 "fairness principles in your paper (regarding IIA): In practical effect *no* method meets this.Approval and Range can be said to meet Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) only if the votes are interpreted as the voters giving ratings on some fixed scale that is independent of the actual candidates. No, that's not correct. Perhaps it would be useful if you actually state the version of IIA you are using. Usually, it refers to adding or subtracting a candidate without changing the "preference order" of the other candidates, but if you are going to use it with Range and Approval, you have to modify it; the basic modification is that the Range Votes or Approval Votes don't change, and all that happens is that a new candidate is added to the ballot or taken off the ballot. If voters are allowed to actually change their votes, *no method meets IIA.* Simple proof: there is a candidate whose name is a trigger for a long-hidden internal program that causes human beings to fall into a trance when they contemplate whether or not to vote for a candidate, and they leave the booth with false memories of what happened (really happens with trance, sometimes, i.e, false memory). The voters see this new name on the ballot, and regardless of how they would have voted, they become incapable of voting, so all candidates tie with no votes. And thus the winner could change. On this perverse interpretation Approval and Range do not reduce to FPP in the 2 candidate election, in violation of Dopp's "fairness principle 4": "Any candidate who is the favorite [first] choice of a majority of voters should win." (approval or non-approval counts as "rating" on a 2-point scale). Chris, you should look at Dhillon and Mertens, "Relative Utilitarianism," where they purport to prove that Range Voting is a unique solution to a version of Arrow's voting axioms that accommodate Range Voting. Relative Utilitarianism refers to "votes" which are "normalized von Neuman-Morgenstern utilities in the range of 0-1. I.e., Range Voting. Warren Smith is actually not in outer space on this (their work preceded his). Because of the normalization, in the two candidate case, Majority is satisfied. Because vN-M utilities are modified by probabilities, it gets complicated in the three-candidate case, where RU is considered the unique solution. If I remember correctly. I'm hoping to help get a popularization of Dhillon and Mertens prepared, it's needed. Smith calls their use of symbols "Notation from Hell." And he's familiar with the conventions! Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
At 12:23 PM 6/23/2008, Juho wrote: Let's assume that our voter has fixed preferences of A=543, B=123, C=99. The election method is either Range with values from 0 to 10 or Approval. If the election has two candidates, B and C, the voter might vote in Range B=10, C=0 and in Approval B=1, C=0. We can assume that the voter will normalize the vote and rank one of the candidates at 10 (or 1 in Approval) and one at 0. Right. However, let's do the full normalization for the total candidate set, first, otherwise the absolute utilities, which may be on the Heaven-Hell scale, could be misleading. Normalizing, we have A: 10.00 B: 0.54 C: 0.00 In other words, B, compared to A, is almost as bad as C. If the election has three candidates the voter might vote in Range A=10, B=1, C=0. Maybe. More likely, because it doesn't make much difference to the voter: Or if A and B are the strongest candidates then maybe strategically A=10, B=0, C=0. In Approval the voter might vote A=1, B=0, C=0. Or if B and C are the strongest candidates then maybe A=1, B=1, C=0. If it were me, I might be buying tickets out of the country. That is *really* bad. *Sincere normalized rating, unmodified by election probabilities, is almost zero.* Voters with utilities like this, if they believe A doesn't have a prayer, tend to not vote. If this were Plurality, they would not vote for B under just about any circumstances. If it were Optional Preferential Voting, they'd truncate. A preference increment of 1/20 range is quite possibly not reliably determinable. I think that 1/10 is hard to tell. The reasons for wanting higher resolution range have to do with an ability to express preference with less effect strategicically. So, given utilities like those above, I might vote A 100, B 1, C 0. If I could tell a difference. The sincere opinions/utilities A=543, B=123, C=99 were valid in all the cases but typical voter behaviour in Range and Approval was to normalize the vote and maybe to vote strategically depending on who the strongest candidates are. The ratings given to the candidates varied although the opinions/utilities stayed the same all the time. This changing behaviour may sometimes lead to one of the candidates being a spoiler. Plurality, if voters vote sincerely, guarantees the spoiler effect. It's part of the method. Range allows something different, but nobody coerces voters. *Voters* can decide to act in ways that mimic the spoiler effect, but it's not intrinsic to the method, and if voters vote with any reasonable understanding at all, there is no spoiler effect with any significant frequency with Range or Approval. How many voters in 2000 would not have known that Bush and Gore were the frontrunners? The decision in Approval is quite simple: if you want to influence the election, vote for one of the frontrunners, period. Indeed, it gets tricky when there are three frontrunners, but that is vanishingly rare in the U.S. If it had been Approval, would Nader still have been a spoiler? (Assuming he was, there is some possible controversy about that, though I do accept the reality of it myself.) Suppose he had not run. How would his supporters have voted? The question is, if they believed his arguments or voted for him because they already felt that way, that there was no important difference between Bush and Gore, they might not have voted at all. It's entirely possible that the Nader candidacy increased turnout, for people who wanted to vote for him. The real question is how many Gore votes disappeared into the Nader rabbit-hole. Probably some. That election, in Florida, which was itself a crisis point, exquisitely sensitive, was very close, the official margin (never mind the actual votes) was 0.009%. But then we'd have to look at other possible spoilers in the other direction. Buchanan. Brown. Both of them might have taken Bush votes. Here is the point: With Range or Approval, voters would not be *forced* to make the choice. They still might. Same with IRV (which can generally be considered to fix the minor candidate version of the spoiler effect, just about its one good feature). If voters are convinced by Nader that there is no difference between Bush and Gore, they might well truncate with IRV just as well. Indeed, there were some arguments from this side that it was better for Bush to win, because it made things worse than thus people would be more motivated to seek better solutions. (This is a very dangerous argument, and never mind that it contradicts the argument that Bush and Gore are the same. But I've heard people make this very argument, in person. I'll admit it makes me angry: they are responsible, then, for the deaths of those who needlessly died because of their desire to make things worse. The ends do *not* justify the means. The means *are* the ends, that is all we have: what we do. We don't control "ends.") What if Florida had an early open
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Finally a question for my vacations! I would use geothermia. Simply dig a long tube in the ground with the two halfs at different underground level and put the ends at differents levels of your house. It should pump cool air from the underground to your basement, when it gets hot then to the upstairs where it goes through the second end far underground and back in the cycle. what is important is that the length of the underground tubes is long enough so the pumping effect can drag the hot air form upstairs stronger then the boussinesq force keeps it elevated (hot air is lighter). So now can you acknoledge that IRV is better than FPTP ? I can accpet IRV being worst than any other method (even if I do not agree all the time) but FPTP has to be worst! Steph, the canadian engineer in vacation in Cuba PS: Maybe I should dig holes in the hotel, it is so hot! From: "Kathy Dopp" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> Reply-To: [EMAIL PROTECTED] To: election-methods@lists.electorama.com Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham) Date: Sun, 22 Jun 2008 17:28:06 -0600 On Sun, Jun 22, 2008 at 5:00 PM, <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > Send Election-Methods mailing list submissions to >election-methods@lists.electorama.com > > To subscribe or unsubscribe via the World Wide Web, visit > http://lists.electorama.com/listinfo.cgi/election-methods-electorama.com > > or, via email, send a message with subject or body 'help' to >[EMAIL PROTECTED] > > You can reach the person managing the list at >[EMAIL PROTECTED] > > When replying, please edit your Subject line so it is more specific > than "Re: Contents of Election-Methods digest..." > From: Juho <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris > > Although Chris' voters changed their vote they didn't change their > opinions between the elections. If there are new candidates they may be better than the old ones Juho, In Chris' approval example, voters changed their approval votes for the existing candidates, not simply added approvals for new candidates. The spoiler is a "nonwinning" candidate who changes the outcome of an election. I.e. If the new candidate wins, or does not change the outcome, he is not a spoiler. Apparently the voters *did* change their opinions between elections judging from their ballots - rather than using mindreading. Now of course if you and Chris read all the voters' minds and every voter in the world thinks exactly like you and Chris imagine them to, then I am wrong. However, I prefer thinking that I can *not* know how all voters think or would strategize and to simply judge what a voting method does given the actual votes. Hey since you guys seem to think you are much smarter than I am and you like puzzles, solve this little (true situation) puzzle: The temperature outside my house is 90+ degrees today and inside my house is 68 degrees downstairs and 74 degrees upstairs at 5:20 p.m and this is the hottest it will get inside my house today. Yet I have no air conditioner, no fan, no swamp cooler, etc. These same temperatures (roughly) exist inside and outside my house during the entire summer. How do I keep my house under 68 degrees inside (downstairs) and under 74 degrees (upstairs) all summer with no air conditioner or swamp cooler when it is routinely in the 90s outside? Cheers, Kathy Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Jun 23, 2008, at 2:28 , Kathy Dopp wrote: Although Chris' voters changed their vote they didn't change their opinions between the elections. If there are new candidates they may be better than the old ones Juho, In Chris' approval example, voters changed their approval votes for the existing candidates, not simply added approvals for new candidates. Here's one explanation to why this happened. Let's assume that our voter has fixed preferences of A=543, B=123, C=99. The election method is either Range with values from 0 to 10 or Approval. If the election has two candidates, B and C, the voter might vote in Range B=10, C=0 and in Approval B=1, C=0. We can assume that the voter will normalize the vote and rank one of the candidates at 10 (or 1 in Approval) and one at 0. If the election has three candidates the voter might vote in Range A=10, B=1, C=0. Or if A and B are the strongest candidates then maybe strategically A=10, B=0, C=0. In Approval the voter might vote A=1, B=0, C=0. Or if B and C are the strongest candidates then maybe A=1, B=1, C=0. The sincere opinions/utilities A=543, B=123, C=99 were valid in all the cases but typical voter behaviour in Range and Approval was to normalize the vote and maybe to vote strategically depending on who the strongest candidates are. The ratings given to the candidates varied although the opinions/utilities stayed the same all the time. This changing behaviour may sometimes lead to one of the candidates being a spoiler. The temperature outside my house is 90+ degrees today and inside my house is 68 degrees downstairs and 74 degrees upstairs at 5:20 p.m and this is the hottest it will get inside my house today. Yet I have no air conditioner, no fan, no swamp cooler, etc. These same temperatures (roughly) exist inside and outside my house during the entire summer. How do I keep my house under 68 degrees inside (downstairs) and under 74 degrees (upstairs) all summer with no air conditioner or swamp cooler when it is routinely in the 90s outside? A large cellar or other heat/cold storage capabilities would help. Maybe also modern windows, isolation and cool nights. Juho ___ Now you can scan emails quickly with a reading pane. Get the new Yahoo! Mail. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Kathy, Imagine that Approval is used to elect the US President and as in the current campaign the Republicans are fielding one candidate, McCain. Does that mean that the big fight for the Democrat nomination between Clinton and Obama we've just seen would in the Approval scenario be completely unnecessary? Why not simply endorse both candidates? After all, one cannot possibly spoil the election for the other because Approval has no spoiler problem. Voters simply approve candidates or not completely regardless of what other candidates are on the ballot, right? I think that in practical effect Approval does have a "spoiler" or split-vote problem that would be sufficient for the Democrats to still want to endorse one candidate only. What I actually wrote in my initial post on the 5 "fairness principles in your paper (regarding IIA): In practical effect *no* method meets this.Approval and Range can be said to meet Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) only if the votes are interpreted as the voters giving ratings on some fixed scale that is independent of the actual candidates. On this perverse interpretation Approval and Range do not reduce to FPP in the 2 candidate election, in violation of Dopp's "fairness principle 4": "Any candidate who is the favorite [first] choice of a majority of voters should win." (approval or non-approval counts as "rating" on a 2-point scale). This latter point you seem to implicitly acknowledge in one of your recent posts: "In actuality, if these are the same voters both before and after you add another candidate C, then your first example with two candidates, to be consistent with your second example with three candidates should be: 25 A 40 AB 35 B so that B wins in the first example AND in the second when another candidate is introduced." Chris Benham Get the name you always wanted with the new y7mail email address. www.yahoo7.com.au/mail Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Kathy, Imagine that Approval is used to elect the US President and as in the current campaign the Republicans are fielding one candidate, McCain. Does that mean that the big fight for the Democrat nomination between Clinton and Obama we've just seen would in the Approval scenario be completely unnecessary? Why not simply endorse both candidates? After all, one cannot possibly spoil the election for the other because Approval has no spoiler problem. Voters simply approve candidates or not completely regardless of what other candidates are on the ballot, right? I think that in practical effect Approval does have a "spoiler" or split-vote problem that would be sufficient for the Democrats to still want to endorse one candidate only. What I actually wrote in my initial post on the 5 "fairness principles in your paper (regarding IIA): In practical effect *no* method meets this.Approval and Range can be said to meet Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) only if the votes are interpreted as the voters giving ratings on some fixed scale that is independent of the actual candidates. On this perverse interpretation Approval and Range do not reduce to FPP in the 2 candidate election, in violation of Dopp's "fairness principle 4": "Any candidate who is the favorite [first] choice of a majority of voters should win." (approval or non-approval counts as "rating" on a 2-point scale). This latter point you seem to implicitly acknowledge in one of your recent posts: "In actuality, if these are the same voters both before and after you add another candidate C, then your first example with two candidates, to be consistent with your second example with three candidates should be: 25 A 40 AB 35 B so that B wins in the first example AND in the second when another candidate is introduced." Chris Benham Get the name you always wanted with the new y7mail email address. www.yahoo7.com.au/mail Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
At 01:17 PM 6/22/2008, James Gilmour wrote: Kathy Dopp > Sent: Sunday, June 22, 2008 4:53 AM > I try not to waste time > on stupid ideas and I've already wasted over 6 weeks of this > year considering IRV which is an incredibly stupid voting > method at first glance after 15 minutes of study IMO. So what does this tell us about the many thousands of public elections and civic organisation elections that have been conducted by the IRV voting system since it was introduced for public elections around 100 years ago? For starters, what is being proposed in the U.S. isn't that system. It wasn't called "instant runoff voting," and the rules are different. Smoke that! Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Sun, Jun 22, 2008 at 5:00 PM, <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > Send Election-Methods mailing list submissions to >election-methods@lists.electorama.com > > To subscribe or unsubscribe via the World Wide Web, visit > > http://lists.electorama.com/listinfo.cgi/election-methods-electorama.com > > or, via email, send a message with subject or body 'help' to >[EMAIL PROTECTED] > > You can reach the person managing the list at >[EMAIL PROTECTED] > > When replying, please edit your Subject line so it is more specific > than "Re: Contents of Election-Methods digest..." > From: Juho <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris > > Although Chris' voters changed their vote they didn't change their > opinions between the elections. If there are new candidates they may be > better than the old ones Juho, In Chris' approval example, voters changed their approval votes for the existing candidates, not simply added approvals for new candidates. The spoiler is a "nonwinning" candidate who changes the outcome of an election. I.e. If the new candidate wins, or does not change the outcome, he is not a spoiler. Apparently the voters *did* change their opinions between elections judging from their ballots - rather than using mindreading. Now of course if you and Chris read all the voters' minds and every voter in the world thinks exactly like you and Chris imagine them to, then I am wrong. However, I prefer thinking that I can *not* know how all voters think or would strategize and to simply judge what a voting method does given the actual votes. Hey since you guys seem to think you are much smarter than I am and you like puzzles, solve this little (true situation) puzzle: The temperature outside my house is 90+ degrees today and inside my house is 68 degrees downstairs and 74 degrees upstairs at 5:20 p.m and this is the hottest it will get inside my house today. Yet I have no air conditioner, no fan, no swamp cooler, etc. These same temperatures (roughly) exist inside and outside my house during the entire summer. How do I keep my house under 68 degrees inside (downstairs) and under 74 degrees (upstairs) all summer with no air conditioner or swamp cooler when it is routinely in the 90s outside? Cheers, Kathy Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Tells us little since this is one person's opinion. IRV lets voters state their desires more completely than Plurality and is often better at picking a winner - but sometimes fails badly, so: Not too bad when you do not know of better. I join Kathy in wantng to move to better. DWK On Sun, 22 Jun 2008 18:17:06 +0100 James Gilmour wrote: Kathy Dopp > Sent: Sunday, June 22, 2008 4:53 AM I try not to waste time on stupid ideas and I've already wasted over 6 weeks of this year considering IRV which is an incredibly stupid voting method at first glance after 15 minutes of study IMO. So what does this tell us about the many thousands of public elections and civic organisation elections that have been conducted by the IRV voting system since it was introduced for public elections around 100 years ago? James Gilmour -- [EMAIL PROTECTED]people.clarityconnect.com/webpages3/davek Dave Ketchum 108 Halstead Ave, Owego, NY 13827-1708 607-687-5026 Do to no one what you would not want done to you. If you want peace, work for justice. Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
A brief reaction to some of Abd's commentary on my simple example of how Range can suffer from spoiler dynamics... Abd wrote A new candidate, C, is considered "fantastic" by 25/55 of the A supporters. So they switch their votes. As would be expected, surely, from such an introduction, results can change. But Bouricius has made, actually, quite a preposterous assumption. He's assuming black and white ratings for all other voters. Nearly half the A supporters think C is so much better than A that they think he's better than A by as much as A is than B, yet, *none* of the other voters are moved by this candidate? So it is *not* an "entirely plausible scenario." Firstly, a scenario doesn't need to be highly plausible to prove that a method can violate a criterion. And yet, I repeat my assertion that my example is highly plausible. To make it even more plausible I will also assume some of the previous A voters who didn't think C was fantastic thought C was somewhere between A and B in worthiness, so give C a 5, and some others who are on the other side of issue X think C is worse than B, so elevate B to 5 and give C 0. Of course for realism I could say some use scores of 3, 7, etc., but the average of 5 just makes the math easier to follow. I'll even throw in some modifications in how the B voters score candidates with the entry of C for even more "realism." Let's say most (25 of 45) view A and C as clones (on the issues they care about) and give both 0, but that ten voters agree on issue X with candidate C and ten disagree on issue X, so ten give C a 5, but the other ten elevate A to a 5 so they can score C lower than A at 0. Thus we have results as follows (I can send anyone who wants a spreadsheet showing this): A=475 B= 500 C= 400 Thus in this completely plausible Range spoiler scenario, C has again spoiled A's election and changed B from a loser to a winner. Much of the rest of Abd's conjecture about likely voter behavior assumes accurate polling information is widely available and voters use smart strategic calculations in hopes of avoiding the spoiler problem. That same hope sometimes allows a spoiler scenario to be avoided under traditional plurality (FPTP) rules, but the fact remains that both methods are prone to spoiler problems. -Terry Bouricius [EMAIL PROTECTED] (802) 864-8382 - Original Message - From: "Abd ul-Rahman Lomax" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> To: "Terry Bouricius" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]>; Sent: Sunday, June 22, 2008 1:57 PM Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham) At 12:35 PM 6/22/2008, Terry Bouricius wrote: >Ms. Dopp has requested a clearer example of how Range and Approval voting >can experience a spoiler scenario (through violation of the Independence >of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) Criterion). Although her inability to >follow Chris's logic led her to use extremely disrespectful language, I >will assume she was having a bad day and was just extremely frustrated. Perhaps. Or perhaps she was the newcomer saying that the emperor has no clothes, which can be extraordinarily rude, if you think about it. >Here is a simple example, that I hope she can follow... Certainly I'll look at it closely! >How a voter scores a particular candidate (or whether the candidate is on >the positive or negative side of an approval cut-off) depends on what >other candidates the voter has to compare the candidate to. The word "score" as being used by Bouricius implies relative scoring, most notably what in Range would be called "normalization." These are *not* absolute ratings, and aren't commensurable from one voter to another between various election configurations. >If the voter thinks candidate A is okay, and B is horrible in a two way >race, the voter will likely score A as a 10 and B as a 0 (approve A and >not approve B). [Rather than insert an Approval Voting translation for >each point from here on I will just use a Range example, though the >dynamic is the same.] Yes. That's correct. But the same, of course, is true if B is merely less than okay. Bouricius is teetering, here, on confusing Range with Approval. Voter's don't "score" candidates in Approval except as A and B, and we may assume some underlying rating, which will be, properly, continuous, not set up in discreet steps from 0 to 10. And, because this is a single voter, normalization has no effect. The only thing that has an effect is where the voter sets the approval cutoff, which is a decision made -- quite properly -- based on the election environment. In recent posts to the Range Voting list, Smith has shown how serial Approval elections cause voters to lower their approval cutoff, perhaps, as new candidates are also introduced as compromises. >If there are 100 voters an
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Jun 22, 2008, at 22:33 , Kathy Dopp wrote: In fact, I would oppose any voting method which did "not" violate Chris' new condition that even when voters change their votes, the winner should stay the same. Although Chris' voters changed their vote they didn't change their opinions between the elections. If there are new candidates they may be better than the old ones and also e.g. in FPP one would vote those instead of the ones one voted when the new candidates were not available. In Approval voting typically is strategically planned in the sense that in order to cast a vote with some meaningful impact on the outcome (or to follow the optimal strategy) one typically should select the candidates that one approves based on the available candidates, one's own preferences and on how one expects others to vote. That is why it makes sense to individual voters to approve different candidate sets in different elections. Juho ___ Inbox full of spam? Get leading spam protection and 1GB storage with All New Yahoo! Mail. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Yes, this was an excellent (clear basic) example as well. The introduction of new candidates definitely changes the scoring of the candidates by the voters. One can study also voter specific absolute scoring that never changes despite of changes in the candidate list. This is a theoretical option that assumes fully sincere ratings based on some absolute scale (where each voter has himself/herself frozen 0 and 10 at some fixed positions, or alternatively the election organizer has given those fixed points, e.g. 0="totally unacceptable", 10="best possible person in the world"). The examples assumed normalized Range votes (where voters typically use both 0 and 10 in their ballot). In real life competitive elections normalized votes are of course typical (in Range one may also get lots of exaggerated votes where voter uses mostly 0 and 10 and seldom any intermediate values), which makes the examples much more realistic than the theoretical absolute scale approach that I mentioned above. Juho On Jun 22, 2008, at 19:35 , Terry Bouricius wrote: Ms. Dopp has requested a clearer example of how Range and Approval voting can experience a spoiler scenario (through violation of the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) Criterion). Although her inability to follow Chris's logic led her to use extremely disrespectful language, I will assume she was having a bad day and was just extremely frustrated. Here is a simple example, that I hope she can follow... How a voter scores a particular candidate (or whether the candidate is on the positive or negative side of an approval cut-off) depends on what other candidates the voter has to compare the candidate to. If the voter thinks candidate A is okay, and B is horrible in a two way race, the voter will likely score A as a 10 and B as a 0 (approve A and not approve B). [Rather than insert an Approval Voting translation for each point from here on I will just use a Range example, though the dynamic is the same.] If there are 100 voters and 55 prefer A>B and 45 B>A, this two-way race could end with a total score of 550 for A (55 voters giving a 10 and 45 giving a 0) to 450 for B. Thus A is both the de facto majority choice as well as the Range score winner. Now comes the spoiler...What if candidate C decides to run as well? It happens that a significant portion (let's say 25 out of the 55) of the former A supporters who care most about issue X view candidate C as a fantastically superior candidate to A or B (though they still prefer A over B as well). It seems likely that many of these voters would feel the need to reduce the score of ten they otherwise would give to A to make room on the scale so they can indicate how superior C is to A. These 25 voters might now score the candidates as follows, A=5, B=0, and C=10. In other words, the score that A now receives from some voters depends on whether C has entered the race. The B supporters who generally don't care much about issue X view C as just another version of A, so give this new candidate a 0 as well. Under this entirely plausible scenario, with C in the race, now the total scores might be A now only gets 425 (30 x 10 and 25 x 5), while B still gets 450 (45 x 10) and C gets 250 (25 x 10). Thus C has "spoiled" the race for A. The entry of C caused B to go from a loser to a winner. The identical dynamic can be demonstrated for Approval Voting using voter decisions about where to draw their approval cut-off line, once C enters the race. -Terry Bouricius [EMAIL PROTECTED] (802) 864-8382 - Original Message - From: "Kathy Dopp" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> To: Sent: Saturday, June 21, 2008 8:54 PM Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham) Chris, You example clearly does not provide an example of approval voting being subjected to the spoiler effect. You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval voting methods. Chris, This is the LAST time I will take any of my time to respond to any of your emails since your emails either lack any logic or show that you did not take the time to read and study either Abd ul's email rebuttals of Fair Vote or the paper I wrote and I don't have time to waste on annoying silliness. On Sat, Jun 21, 2008 at 5:03 PM, > Date: Sat, 21 Jun 2008 > Ok. Suppose? the method is Approval, there are two candidates (A and B) and the voters' utilities (sincere ratings on some fixed scale independent of the candidates) are: 40: A100, B98 25: A98,?? B1 35: B100, A1 OK. Then if this example is counted using approval voting by removing the ratings for these vo
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Chris, This is what you are now claiming is a "fairness" condition: ... that to be fair, the winner of an election must not change with the introduction of a new nonwinning candidate, even if the voters change their votes for the prior (old) candidates. As a voter, I would object to this "fairness" condition that requires any different vote I cast after changing my mind about which candidates to "approve" should not count towards who wins the election contest. In fact, I would oppose any voting method which did "not" violate Chris' new condition that even when voters change their votes, the winner should stay the same. As his example shows, he changes the voters' votes as follows: 65 A 35 B to 40 AB 25 A 35 B Yet Chris expects the same candidate A to win in the second example, where B win.s instead So Chris's new "fairness" condition does not even require the introduction of any third candidate, it just requires that the winner of the election stay the same even if voters change their votes for the same candidates. I.e. In short, "the actual votes which voters cast should not count towards who wins" is Chris' new fairness condition, which I hope that every voting system will violate Chris' version of the IIA "fairness" condition. Cheers, Kathy Cheers, Kathy Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Abd, "When you assume a set of ratings which are clearly normalized, they are no longer independent and absolute, and conclusions drawn from them, based on the introduction of a new candidate or a candidate withdrawal, are no longer valid. By using normalized utilities, and assuming that they remain the same, Chris has made a preposterous assumption, so no wonder his results are defective." The utilities I gave were not normalised, they were absolute. The only "prepostrous assumptions" I made were that in a 2-candidate election the voters would 'strategically' only approve the candidate they prefer to the other, and with 3 candidates the voters might approve the 2 candidates they like nearly the same and much better than the third candidate. "Range and Approval do not violate IIA as originally interpreted. However, it's possible to reinterpret IIA to apply it to nonpreferential ballots, in a particular way, and Range and Approval can thus be made to violate this new version of the criterion. Essentially, if voters change their votes as a result of the introduction of new candidates, a different result may occur that doesn't involve that new candidate being a winner. " That is right. But interpreting Range and Approval in the way needed for it to meet IIA means that it fails even 2-candidate Majority Favourite, so it doesn't magically evade Arrow's Impossibility Theorem. "So does Approval satisfy the Majority Criterion?" No, as stated in Kathy Dopp's paper. "However, Woodall, it seems, may have thought differently, since, if I recall correctly, he considered Plurality as failing Majority." As has been pointed out to you more than once, Woodall's version of "Majority" is equivalent to Majority for Solid Coalitions (aka Mutual Majority) which FPP ("First Preference Plurality") can't meet because it only considers first preferences. Chris Benham Abd ul Lomax wrote (Sun Jun 22 10:01:40 PDT 2008 ): At 03:58 AM 6/22/2008, Chris Benham wrote: >Kathy, >I choose my words carefully. > >"You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for >ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by >your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your >own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval >voting methods." > >Apart from a passing reference to Range the only voting method I discussed >or referred to was Approval. >I didn't suggest that voters be "asked for ratings". >40: A100, B98 >25: A98, B1 >35: B100, A1 >These numbers I gave represent nothing outside the heads of the >individual voters. >I'm sorry if I didn't make that clear enough. This corresponds with >the use in >EM circles of the word "utilities". On one level, Chris is correct. However, that Kathy didn't "understand" that points out a problem that may be obvious to a relatively newcomer to the topic of alternative voting systems (Dopp) but not so obvious to someone who has been immersed in the topic for years. When you assume a set of ratings which are clearly normalized, they are no longer independent and absolute, and conclusions drawn from them, based on the introduction of a new candidate or a candidate withdrawal, are no longer valid. By using normalized utilities, and assuming that they remain the same, Chris has made a preposterous assumption, so no wonder his results are defective. Range and Approval do not violate IIA as originally interpreted. However, it's possible to reinterpret IIA to apply it to nonpreferential ballots, in a particular way, and Range and Approval can thus be made to violate this new version of the criterion. Essentially, if voters change their votes as a result of the introduction of new candidates, a different result may occur that doesn't involve that new candidate being a winner. Chris and I have had this discussion many times as it relates to the Majority Criterion If a majority of voters express their strict preference for a candidate in Approval, that candidate must win. But if they dilute that expression with approval of another candidate, that candidate might lose (to a candidate with a *larger* majority). So does Approval satisfy the Majority Criterion? It depends on the definition and, problem was, the original criterion did not contemplate equal approval of candidates at the "top of their preference lists," and there was no distinction made between preference lists and actual votes in the election. A complete ranking was simply assumed. However, Woodall, it seems, may have thought differently, since, if I recall correctly, he considered Plurality as failing Majority. I'd have to review this to make sure I got it right Get the name you always wanted with the new y7mail email address. www.yahoo7.com.au/mail Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
At 12:35 PM 6/22/2008, Terry Bouricius wrote: Ms. Dopp has requested a clearer example of how Range and Approval voting can experience a spoiler scenario (through violation of the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) Criterion). Although her inability to follow Chris's logic led her to use extremely disrespectful language, I will assume she was having a bad day and was just extremely frustrated. Perhaps. Or perhaps she was the newcomer saying that the emperor has no clothes, which can be extraordinarily rude, if you think about it. Here is a simple example, that I hope she can follow... Certainly I'll look at it closely! How a voter scores a particular candidate (or whether the candidate is on the positive or negative side of an approval cut-off) depends on what other candidates the voter has to compare the candidate to. The word "score" as being used by Bouricius implies relative scoring, most notably what in Range would be called "normalization." These are *not* absolute ratings, and aren't commensurable from one voter to another between various election configurations. If the voter thinks candidate A is okay, and B is horrible in a two way race, the voter will likely score A as a 10 and B as a 0 (approve A and not approve B). [Rather than insert an Approval Voting translation for each point from here on I will just use a Range example, though the dynamic is the same.] Yes. That's correct. But the same, of course, is true if B is merely less than okay. Bouricius is teetering, here, on confusing Range with Approval. Voter's don't "score" candidates in Approval except as A and B, and we may assume some underlying rating, which will be, properly, continuous, not set up in discreet steps from 0 to 10. And, because this is a single voter, normalization has no effect. The only thing that has an effect is where the voter sets the approval cutoff, which is a decision made -- quite properly -- based on the election environment. In recent posts to the Range Voting list, Smith has shown how serial Approval elections cause voters to lower their approval cutoff, perhaps, as new candidates are also introduced as compromises. If there are 100 voters and 55 prefer A>B and 45 B>A, this two-way race could end with a total score of 550 for A (55 voters giving a 10 and 45 giving a 0) to 450 for B. Thus A is both the de facto majority choice as well as the Range score winner. Using "score," multiplied by 10, for Approval results looks to me like Bouricius is setting something up. Now comes the spoiler...What if candidate C decides to run as well? It happens that a significant portion (let's say 25 out of the 55) of the former A supporters who care most about issue X view candidate C as a fantastically superior candidate to A or B (though they still prefer A over B as well). It seems likely that many of these voters would feel the need to reduce the score of ten they otherwise would give to A to make room on the scale so they can indicate how superior C is to A. These 25 voters might now score the candidates as follows, A=5, B=0, and C=10. In other words, the score that A now receives from some voters depends on whether C has entered the race. The B supporters who generally don't care much about issue X view C as just another version of A, so give this new candidate a 0 as well. Under this entirely plausible scenario, with C in the race, now the total scores might be A now only gets 425 (30 x 10 and 25 x 5), while B still gets 450 (45 x 10) and C gets 250 (25 x 10). This is such a complex explanation that, at first sight, I'm tempted to totally ignore it. Sigh. A new candidate, C, is considered "fantastic" by 25/55 of the A supporters. So they switch their votes. As would be expected, surely, from such an introduction, results can change. But Bouricius has made, actually, quite a preposterous assumption. He's assuming black and white ratings for all other voters. Nearly half the A supporters think C is so much better than A that they think he's better than A by as much as A is than B, yet, *none* of the other voters are moved by this candidate? So it is *not* an "entirely plausible scenario." The real matter is much simpler. First of all, technical compliance with election criteria can be highly misleading. As an example, Approval is commonly asserted to fail the Majority Criterion, and supposedly this is a bad thing. After all, majority rule and all that. However, Approval only fails the special definitions of the Majority Criterion invented to deal with the problem of applying it to methods which allow equal ranking at the top. And so whether it fails or not depends on the precise definition, it's no longer "objective." Secondly, even granting these definitions, what are the conditions under which it fails? It fails when more than one candidate is approved by a majority. How common is this? Not terribly! It practically never would happen in a two-p
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Kathy Dopp > Sent: Sunday, June 22, 2008 4:53 AM > I try not to waste time > on stupid ideas and I've already wasted over 6 weeks of this > year considering IRV which is an incredibly stupid voting > method at first glance after 15 minutes of study IMO. So what does this tell us about the many thousands of public elections and civic organisation elections that have been conducted by the IRV voting system since it was introduced for public elections around 100 years ago? James Gilmour No virus found in this outgoing message. Checked by AVG. Version: 7.5.524 / Virus Database: 270.4.1/1512 - Release Date: 21/06/2008 09:27 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
At 03:58 AM 6/22/2008, Chris Benham wrote: Kathy, I choose my words carefully. "You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval voting methods." Apart from a passing reference to Range the only voting method I discussed or referred to was Approval. I didn't suggest that voters be "asked for ratings". 40: A100, B98 25: A98, B1 35: B100, A1 These numbers I gave represent nothing outside the heads of the individual voters. I'm sorry if I didn't make that clear enough. This corresponds with the use in EM circles of the word "utilities". On one level, Chris is correct. However, that Kathy didn't "understand" that points out a problem that may be obvious to a relatively newcomer to the topic of alternative voting systems (Dopp) but not so obvious to someone who has been immersed in the topic for years. When you assume a set of ratings which are clearly normalized, they are no longer independent and absolute, and conclusions drawn from them, based on the introduction of a new candidate or a candidate withdrawal, are no longer valid. By using normalized utilities, and assuming that they remain the same, Chris has made a preposterous assumption, so no wonder his results are defective. Range and Approval do not violate IIA as originally interpreted. However, it's possible to reinterpret IIA to apply it to nonpreferential ballots, in a particular way, and Range and Approval can thus be made to violate this new version of the criterion. Essentially, if voters change their votes as a result of the introduction of new candidates, a different result may occur that doesn't involve that new candidate being a winner. Chris and I have had this discussion many times as it relates to the Majority Criterion If a majority of voters express their strict preference for a candidate in Approval, that candidate must win. But if they dilute that expression with approval of another candidate, that candidate might lose (to a candidate with a *larger* majority). So does Approval satisfy the Majority Criterion? It depends on the definition and, problem was, the original criterion did not contemplate equal approval of candidates at the "top of their preference lists," and there was no distinction made between preference lists and actual votes in the election. A complete ranking was simply assumed. However, Woodall, it seems, may have thought differently, since, if I recall correctly, he considered Plurality as failing Majority. I'd have to review this to make sure I got it right Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Ms. Dopp has requested a clearer example of how Range and Approval voting can experience a spoiler scenario (through violation of the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) Criterion). Although her inability to follow Chris's logic led her to use extremely disrespectful language, I will assume she was having a bad day and was just extremely frustrated. Here is a simple example, that I hope she can follow... How a voter scores a particular candidate (or whether the candidate is on the positive or negative side of an approval cut-off) depends on what other candidates the voter has to compare the candidate to. If the voter thinks candidate A is okay, and B is horrible in a two way race, the voter will likely score A as a 10 and B as a 0 (approve A and not approve B). [Rather than insert an Approval Voting translation for each point from here on I will just use a Range example, though the dynamic is the same.] If there are 100 voters and 55 prefer A>B and 45 B>A, this two-way race could end with a total score of 550 for A (55 voters giving a 10 and 45 giving a 0) to 450 for B. Thus A is both the de facto majority choice as well as the Range score winner. Now comes the spoiler...What if candidate C decides to run as well? It happens that a significant portion (let's say 25 out of the 55) of the former A supporters who care most about issue X view candidate C as a fantastically superior candidate to A or B (though they still prefer A over B as well). It seems likely that many of these voters would feel the need to reduce the score of ten they otherwise would give to A to make room on the scale so they can indicate how superior C is to A. These 25 voters might now score the candidates as follows, A=5, B=0, and C=10. In other words, the score that A now receives from some voters depends on whether C has entered the race. The B supporters who generally don't care much about issue X view C as just another version of A, so give this new candidate a 0 as well. Under this entirely plausible scenario, with C in the race, now the total scores might be A now only gets 425 (30 x 10 and 25 x 5), while B still gets 450 (45 x 10) and C gets 250 (25 x 10). Thus C has "spoiled" the race for A. The entry of C caused B to go from a loser to a winner. The identical dynamic can be demonstrated for Approval Voting using voter decisions about where to draw their approval cut-off line, once C enters the race. -Terry Bouricius [EMAIL PROTECTED] (802) 864-8382 - Original Message - From: "Kathy Dopp" <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> To: Sent: Saturday, June 21, 2008 8:54 PM Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham) Chris, You example clearly does not provide an example of approval voting being subjected to the spoiler effect. You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval voting methods. Chris, This is the LAST time I will take any of my time to respond to any of your emails since your emails either lack any logic or show that you did not take the time to read and study either Abd ul's email rebuttals of Fair Vote or the paper I wrote and I don't have time to waste on annoying silliness. On Sat, Jun 21, 2008 at 5:03 PM, > Date: Sat, 21 Jun 2008 > Ok. Suppose? the method is Approval, there are two candidates (A and B) and the voters' > utilities (sincere ratings on some fixed scale independent of the > candidates) are: > 40: A100, B98 > 25: A98,?? B1 > 35: B100, A1 OK. Then if this example is counted using approval voting by removing the ratings for these voters, there is a TIE since 100% of voters approve of both A and B. > > I assume that with just 2 candidates, all voters will simply approve the > one they prefer to > the other, to give the Approval result: > 65: A > 35: B OK. This is a completely separate example of approval voting than your first example. BTW, in any election: 1. voters have to make a choice on how they vote and cannot vote more than one way in the same election using one ballot, and 2. the election has to be either conducted via one election method or another - I.e. approval voting is analogous to rating candidates 0 (not approved) or 1 (approved), and so your above example shows ALL candidates are approved if one tries to switch that to approval from ratings. In this example A wins. > A wins. Now suppose that a third candidate (C) is introduced, and > including this extra > candidate the voters'? utilities are: > > > 40: A100, B98, C1 > 25: C100, A98,?B1 > 35: B100, C98, A1 OK. In this example, removing the ratings to get approval voting example (a third exampl
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Sun, Jun 22, 2008 at 1:58 AM, Chris Benham <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> wrote: > > Apart from a passing reference to Range the only voting method I discussed > or referred to was Approval. OK Chris, Let us look at your alleged two examples of "approval" voting. LOOK at what you gave us: 65 A 35 B then you gave 40 AB 25 CA 35 BC What you did was CHANGE the votes of 40 of the 65 people who did not approve of B in the first example, so that 40 of them all of a suddenly approve of B now in the second example. Which is it? Do these 40 people approve of B or not? Apparently you simply alter the votes of your voters in the second example to get the result that you want and hope that people will not notice your slight of hand. In actuality, if these are the same voters both before and after you add another candidate C, then your first example with two candidates, to be consistent with your second example with three candidates should be: 25 A 40 AB 35 B so that B wins in the first example AND in the second when another candidate is introduced. Or alternatively, if you want to give an honest logically consistent example by altering your second case with three candidates to be consistent with the first case with two instead, it would be: 40 A 25 CA 35 BC so that A wins in both the first and second example. Your manipulating and changing the candidates whom voters approve of all of a sudden when you add another candidate - well this type of trick is very consistent with the tactics of Fair Vote and IRV proponents and not only does not impress me, its lack of honesty offends me. Again Chris, I would like to be working on more productive pursuits than discussing this nonsense with you. Please try to find an honest example where voters' opinions of the first two candidates do not change when you add a third candidate and I believe that you will find that you cannot Cheers, Katy > > Chris Benham > > > > Kathy Dopp kathy.dopp at gmail.com > Sat Jun 21 17:54:52 PDT 2008 > Chris, > > You example clearly does not provide an example of approval voting > being subjected to the spoiler effect. > > You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for > ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by > your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your > own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval > voting methods. > > Chris, This is the LAST time I will take any of my time to respond to > any of your emails since your emails either lack any logic or show > that you did not take the time to read and study either Abd ul's email > rebuttals of Fair Vote or the paper I wrote and I don't have time to > waste on annoying silliness. > > On Sat, Jun 21, 2008 at 5:03 PM, > Date: Sat, 21 Jun 2008 > Ok. > Suppose the method is Approval, there are two candidates (A and B) > and the voters' >>utilities (sincere ratings on some fixed scale independent of the candidates) >>are: >>40: A100, B98 >>25: A98, B1 >>35: B100, A1 > > OK. Then if this example is counted using approval voting by removing > the ratings for these voters, there is a TIE since 100% of voters > approve of both A and B. > >> >>I assume that with just 2 candidates, all voters will simply approve the one >>they prefer to >>the other, to give the Approval result: >>65: A >>35: B > > OK. This is a completely separate example of approval voting than your > first example. BTW, in any election: > > 1. voters have to make a choice on how they vote and cannot vote more > than one way in the same election using one ballot, and > > 2. the election has to be either conducted via one election method or > another - I.e. approval voting is analogous to rating candidates 0 > (not approved) or 1 (approved), and so your above example shows ALL > candidates are approved if one tries to switch that to approval from > ratings. > > In this example A wins. > >>A wins. Now suppose that a third candidate (C) is introduced, and including >>this extra >>candidate the voters' utilities are: >> >> >>40: A100, B98, C1 >>25: C100, A98,B1 >>35: B100, C98, A1 > > OK. In this example, removing the ratings to get approval voting > example (a third example related to neither of the first two, ALL > voters approve of A, B, and C and so A, B, and C are TIED again. It > seems like a pretty unlikely scenario, but then I suppose it is > possible. > >>Now all the voters have one candidate they like very much, another they like >>nearly as much, >>and one they like very much less. The voters best zero-information strategy >>is to all approve 2 >>candidates, to give the Approval ballots: >>40: AB >>25: CA >>35: BC > > OK, in THIS (yet another separate example of approval voting which is > not related to either of your prior examples in any way except by > dropping particular candidates from prior examples), B wins. > > You are capable of understanding I hope that this example is entirely > different from your prior exa
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Jun 22, 2008, at 6:52 , Kathy Dopp wrote: 5. Change the rules (or is the rule for your new voting method always "approve a number of top candidates equal to the total number of candidates minus one" for each voter?) and this time drop all except the top two choices of voters and give the remaining candidates one approval vote each. In the examples voters seem to have range style personal utilities, based on which they then decide how to vote in Approval. The election method can thus be basic Approval (as Chris said). The key assumption seems to be that the available set of candidates may influence on which ones will be approved (i.e. irrelevant alternatives may have an impact in Approval). For example, if there are only "good" candidates then the voter is likely to approve some of them and not approve some of them. If one adds some "bad" candidates to the candidate list then the voter possibly approves all the "good" candidates (although their utility values are still the same) and does not approve the "bad" candidates. In the examples of Chris it was always quite clear which candidates were the better ones and which ones were the worse ones if the voter wants to split them in two groups (which is a sensible approach to vote in Approval). Juho ___ The all-new Yahoo! Mail goes wherever you go - free your email address from your Internet provider. http://uk.docs.yahoo.com/nowyoucan.html Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Kathy, I choose my words carefully. "You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval voting methods." Apart from a passing reference to Range the only voting method I discussed or referred to was Approval. I didn't suggest that voters be "asked for ratings". 40: A100, B98 25: A98, B1 35: B100, A1 These numbers I gave represent nothing outside the heads of the individual voters. I'm sorry if I didn't make that clear enough. This corresponds with the use in EM circles of the word "utilities". Chris Benham Kathy Dopp kathy.dopp at gmail.com Sat Jun 21 17:54:52 PDT 2008 Chris, You example clearly does not provide an example of approval voting being subjected to the spoiler effect. You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval voting methods. Chris, This is the LAST time I will take any of my time to respond to any of your emails since your emails either lack any logic or show that you did not take the time to read and study either Abd ul's email rebuttals of Fair Vote or the paper I wrote and I don't have time to waste on annoying silliness. On Sat, Jun 21, 2008 at 5:03 PM, > Date: Sat, 21 Jun 2008 > Ok. Suppose the method is Approval, there are two candidates (A and B) and the voters' >utilities (sincere ratings on some fixed scale independent of the candidates) >are: >40: A100, B98 >25: A98, B1 >35: B100, A1 OK. Then if this example is counted using approval voting by removing the ratings for these voters, there is a TIE since 100% of voters approve of both A and B. > >I assume that with just 2 candidates, all voters will simply approve the one >they prefer to >the other, to give the Approval result: >65: A >35: B OK. This is a completely separate example of approval voting than your first example. BTW, in any election: 1. voters have to make a choice on how they vote and cannot vote more than one way in the same election using one ballot, and 2. the election has to be either conducted via one election method or another - I.e. approval voting is analogous to rating candidates 0 (not approved) or 1 (approved), and so your above example shows ALL candidates are approved if one tries to switch that to approval from ratings. In this example A wins. >A wins. Now suppose that a third candidate (C) is introduced, and including >this extra >candidate the voters' utilities are: > > >40: A100, B98, C1 >25: C100, A98,B1 >35: B100, C98, A1 OK. In this example, removing the ratings to get approval voting example (a third example related to neither of the first two, ALL voters approve of A, B, and C and so A, B, and C are TIED again. It seems like a pretty unlikely scenario, but then I suppose it is possible. >Now all the voters have one candidate they like very much, another they like >nearly as much, >and one they like very much less. The voters best zero-information strategy is >to all approve 2 >candidates, to give the Approval ballots: >40: AB >25: CA >35: BC OK, in THIS (yet another separate example of approval voting which is not related to either of your prior examples in any way except by dropping particular candidates from prior examples), B wins. You are capable of understanding I hope that this example is entirely different from your prior examples and that none of your examples are of the same approval election? If you are illogically claiming that these three entirely separate examples are the same you must (I am guessing) be thinking in backwards fashion that you can devine voter ratings from approval ballots or that you can delusionally know how all voters would change ratings to approval votes and vice-versa. I.e. Certainly you must agree that: 1. voters must decide ONE way to cast their ONE ballot, and 2. it is not humanly possible to devine what ratings voters would give to each candidate from looking at their approval voting ballots because IF you are talking about APPROVAL voting, then there ARE NO RATINGS, and you might agree that no one has superhuman powers to know by looking at approval ballots, the ratings voters would give. Chris, If you want to provide an example that makes a lick of sense and does not assume that you can magically read all voters' minds, and is logical and valid for EITHER approval or range voting which exhibits the spoiler effect, then you must find an example that is RANGE voting alone or an example which is APPROVAL voting that exhibits the spoiler effect; or alternatively use only 0's and 1's to signify your approval voting ratings. Approval voting is analogous to giving a ra
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Kathy, I choose my words carefully. "You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval voting methods." Apart from a passing reference to Range the only voting method I discussed or referred to was Approval. I didn't suggest that voters be "asked for ratings". 40: A100, B98 25: A98, B1 35: B100, A1 These numbers I gave represent nothing outside the heads of the individual voters. I'm sorry if I didn't make that clear enough. This corresponds with the use in EM circles of the word "utilities". Chris Benham Kathy Dopp kathy.dopp at gmail.com Sat Jun 21 17:54:52 PDT 2008 Chris, You example clearly does not provide an example of approval voting being subjected to the spoiler effect. You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval voting methods. Chris, This is the LAST time I will take any of my time to respond to any of your emails since your emails either lack any logic or show that you did not take the time to read and study either Abd ul's email rebuttals of Fair Vote or the paper I wrote and I don't have time to waste on annoying silliness. On Sat, Jun 21, 2008 at 5:03 PM, > Date: Sat, 21 Jun 2008 > Ok. Suppose the method is Approval, there are two candidates (A and B) and the voters' >utilities (sincere ratings on some fixed scale independent of the candidates) >are: >40: A100, B98 >25: A98, B1 >35: B100, A1 OK. Then if this example is counted using approval voting by removing the ratings for these voters, there is a TIE since 100% of voters approve of both A and B. > >I assume that with just 2 candidates, all voters will simply approve the one >they prefer to >the other, to give the Approval result: >65: A >35: B OK. This is a completely separate example of approval voting than your first example. BTW, in any election: 1. voters have to make a choice on how they vote and cannot vote more than one way in the same election using one ballot, and 2. the election has to be either conducted via one election method or another - I.e. approval voting is analogous to rating candidates 0 (not approved) or 1 (approved), and so your above example shows ALL candidates are approved if one tries to switch that to approval from ratings. In this example A wins. >A wins. Now suppose that a third candidate (C) is introduced, and including >this extra >candidate the voters' utilities are: > > >40: A100, B98, C1 >25: C100, A98,B1 >35: B100, C98, A1 OK. In this example, removing the ratings to get approval voting example (a third example related to neither of the first two, ALL voters approve of A, B, and C and so A, B, and C are TIED again. It seems like a pretty unlikely scenario, but then I suppose it is possible. >Now all the voters have one candidate they like very much, another they like >nearly as much, >and one they like very much less. The voters best zero-information strategy is >to all approve 2 >candidates, to give the Approval ballots: >40: AB >25: CA >35: BC OK, in THIS (yet another separate example of approval voting which is not related to either of your prior examples in any way except by dropping particular candidates from prior examples), B wins. You are capable of understanding I hope that this example is entirely different from your prior examples and that none of your examples are of the same approval election? If you are illogically claiming that these three entirely separate examples are the same you must (I am guessing) be thinking in backwards fashion that you can devine voter ratings from approval ballots or that you can delusionally know how all voters would change ratings to approval votes and vice-versa. I.e. Certainly you must agree that: 1. voters must decide ONE way to cast their ONE ballot, and 2. it is not humanly possible to devine what ratings voters would give to each candidate from looking at their approval voting ballots because IF you are talking about APPROVAL voting, then there ARE NO RATINGS, and you might agree that no one has superhuman powers to know by looking at approval ballots, the ratings voters would give. Chris, If you want to provide an example that makes a lick of sense and does not assume that you can magically read all voters' minds, and is logical and valid for EITHER approval or range voting which exhibits the spoiler effect, then you must find an example that is RANGE voting alone or an example which is APPROVAL voting that exhibits the spoiler effect; or alternatively use only 0's and 1's to signify your approval voting ratings. Approval voting is analogous to giving a ra
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
On Sat, Jun 21, 2008 at 5:03 PM, Sorry bout my impatience Chris, but I try not to waste time on stupid ideas and I've already wasted over 6 weeks of this year considering IRV which is an incredibly stupid voting method at first glance after 15 minutes of study IMO. We cannot train our brains to solve the tough problems of life and think clearly while wasting brain cycles studying dumb ideas like the new voting method you just introduced us to in your email - which I will precisely describe for you here so that you can hopefully understand how little it has to do with either range or approval voting methods: 1. Have voters rate the two candidates in the race from 1 to 100 > 40: A100, B98 > 25: A98,?? B1 > 35: B100, A1 2. Vote counting method: Drop all but the top choices of voters who have just rated the same candidates from 1 to 100 and give each remaining candidate one approval vote. > 65: A > 35: B 3. The winner is the candidate with the most first choice "approval" votes. 4. Introduce a third candidate and have voters rate him as well, using the prior ratings for the first two candidates, so this example of a rating voting system is the same except for the additional candidate for voter ratings. > > 40: A100, B98, C1 > 25: C100, A98,?B1 > 35: B100, C98, A1 5. Change the rules (or is the rule for your new voting method always "approve a number of top candidates equal to the total number of candidates minus one" for each voter?) and this time drop all except the top two choices of voters and give the remaining candidates one approval vote each. > candidates, to give the Approval ballots: > 40: AB > 25: CA > 35: BC Voila. This hair-brained voting method DOES exhibit the spoiler effect! Good going Chris. While I will bet that you can invent any number of hair-brained voting methods which violate the spoiler effect like this "voter-ratings-from-1-to-100-converted-to-top(N-1) candidate approvals worth 1 each" where N is equal to the number of total candidates, your example shows ZIP about the approval method. However, in your example the two range voting examples (with and without the third party candidate) show *no* spoiler effect. B wins both times. PLEASE try to use the range or approval voting methods, rather than inventing a new method that no one would ever think was a good idea, as you did above, when you try to come up with an example which is supposed to show how the range or approval methods are susceptible to the spoiler effect. I hope I have adequately described your method here so that you understand that it is not the same as approval voting. Please do not send us any more ill-considered emails Chris. Some of us have more important things to get done than to discuss hair-brained voting schemes like IRV and the method you just proposed as being equivalent to approval voting but which is not even close to it. Cheers, Kathy Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting (Chris Benham)
Chris, You example clearly does not provide an example of approval voting being subjected to the spoiler effect. You managed to invent a really bad voting method (asking voters for ratings and then converting their ratings to approval/disapproval by your new voting method) and applied your method of conversions to your own example, but it has nothing to do with either range or approval voting methods. Chris, This is the LAST time I will take any of my time to respond to any of your emails since your emails either lack any logic or show that you did not take the time to read and study either Abd ul's email rebuttals of Fair Vote or the paper I wrote and I don't have time to waste on annoying silliness. On Sat, Jun 21, 2008 at 5:03 PM, > Date: Sat, 21 Jun 2008 > Ok. Suppose? the method is Approval, there are two candidates (A and B) and the voters' > utilities (sincere ratings on some fixed scale independent of the candidates) > are: > 40: A100, B98 > 25: A98,?? B1 > 35: B100, A1 OK. Then if this example is counted using approval voting by removing the ratings for these voters, there is a TIE since 100% of voters approve of both A and B. > > I assume that with just 2 candidates, all voters will simply approve the one > they prefer to > the other, to give the Approval result: > 65: A > 35: B OK. This is a completely separate example of approval voting than your first example. BTW, in any election: 1. voters have to make a choice on how they vote and cannot vote more than one way in the same election using one ballot, and 2. the election has to be either conducted via one election method or another - I.e. approval voting is analogous to rating candidates 0 (not approved) or 1 (approved), and so your above example shows ALL candidates are approved if one tries to switch that to approval from ratings. In this example A wins. > A wins. Now suppose that a third candidate (C) is introduced, and including > this extra > candidate the voters'? utilities are: > > > 40: A100, B98, C1 > 25: C100, A98,?B1 > 35: B100, C98, A1 OK. In this example, removing the ratings to get approval voting example (a third example related to neither of the first two, ALL voters approve of A, B, and C and so A, B, and C are TIED again. It seems like a pretty unlikely scenario, but then I suppose it is possible. > Now all the voters have one candidate they like very much, another they like > nearly as much, > and one they like very much less.? The voters best zero-information strategy > is to all approve? 2 > candidates, to give the Approval ballots: > 40: AB > 25: CA > 35: BC OK, in THIS (yet another separate example of approval voting which is not related to either of your prior examples in any way except by dropping particular candidates from prior examples), B wins. You are capable of understanding I hope that this example is entirely different from your prior examples and that none of your examples are of the same approval election? If you are illogically claiming that these three entirely separate examples are the same you must (I am guessing) be thinking in backwards fashion that you can devine voter ratings from approval ballots or that you can delusionally know how all voters would change ratings to approval votes and vice-versa. I.e. Certainly you must agree that: 1. voters must decide ONE way to cast their ONE ballot, and 2. it is not humanly possible to devine what ratings voters would give to each candidate from looking at their approval voting ballots because IF you are talking about APPROVAL voting, then there ARE NO RATINGS, and you might agree that no one has superhuman powers to know by looking at approval ballots, the ratings voters would give. Chris, If you want to provide an example that makes a lick of sense and does not assume that you can magically read all voters' minds, and is logical and valid for EITHER approval or range voting which exhibits the spoiler effect, then you must find an example that is RANGE voting alone or an example which is APPROVAL voting that exhibits the spoiler effect; or alternatively use only 0's and 1's to signify your approval voting ratings. Approval voting is analogous to giving a rating of 1 or 0, not the example you gave. So Chris, go back to the drawing board and eventually I believe that you will discover that you can NOT come up with a valid example of either approval or range voting that is susceptible to the spoiler effect. I.e. If you want to give an example where approval voting fails, use 1 or 0 for your approval/disapproval for candidates. Otherwise come up with a range voting example, but your twisting all logic like you have done in order to come up with a fake example is very annoying because it is so stupid, and I am simply *not* going to respond to any more illogical silliness on your part Chris; nor am I going to continue to waste my time copying and pasting sentences from this list or from my paper which you have not bothered to read. Ta
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
Kathy, All of your points have already been addressed in my paper or by Abd ul Rahman Lomax on this list. For example, re "later no harm": I gather you are referring to Abd's "Dopp: 15. “Violates some election fairness principles ."" post. I hadn't read that because it was part of a series attacking a FairVote page that in turn was purporting to debunk a version of your paper that you had announced was soon to be superseded. Now that I know that you agree with it and that it fully applies to the newest version of your paper, I'll get around to studying it and responding. http://lists.electorama.com/pipermail/election-methods-electorama.com/2008-June/021745.html BTW, you are in point of fact, incorrect that some voting methods do not meet Arrow's "independence of alternatives" condition, that is unless, like Arrow, you are excluding all rating voting methods like range and approval voting. If I am wrong in this, then you will be able to provide an example using the range or approval voting method which does not meet this Arrows' condition that "the introduction of a nonwinning candidate changes the outcome of who wins", not merely make the claim without any supporting example. Ok. Suppose the method is Approval, there are two candidates (A and B) and the voters' utilities (sincere ratings on some fixed scale independent of the candidates) are: 40: A100, B98 25: A98, B1 35: B100, A1 I assume that with just 2 candidates, all voters will simply approve the one they prefer to the other, to give the Approval result: 65: A 35: B A wins. Now suppose that a third candidate (C) is introduced, and including this extra candidate the voters' utilities are: 40: A100, B98, C1 25: C100, A98, B1 35: B100, C98, A1 Now all the voters have one candidate they like very much, another they like nearly as much, and one they like very much less. The voters best zero-information strategy is to all approve 2 candidates, to give the Approval ballots: 40: AB 25: CA 35: BC I assume that you (Kathy) agrees that this is a reasonable way for these voters to vote, because this is the Approval election in Appendix A (example 2) in your paper, with the voters having the same sincere rankings. Now B wins. IIA says that the winner must either remain A or change to the new candidate C. You can say that Approval meets IIA if you assume that the voted approvals in the 2 candidate election are absolute (by some fixed standard independent of the candidates) so that the entry of a new candidate can have no effect on the voters' approval or non-approval of the original candidates. BTW, I think the particular chosen "wording" of IIA is a sophist attempt to make Approval and Range's alleged meeting of it look more plausible. I think it is also supposed to go the other way as well, i.e. dropping a non-winning candidate shouldn't change the result. On the "cast ballots" Approval meets this. It means if we work my example backwards and go from 3 candidates to 2, then after dropping C we get these Approval ballots: 40: AB 25: A 35: B B still wins, but obviously in practice if we were having a fresh election without C then not many voters would approve both the candidates. Chris Benham Kathy Dopp kathy.dopp at gmail.com Fri Jun 20 21:20:05 PDT 2008 > Date: Fri, 20 Jun 2008 13:29:17 -0700 (PDT) > From: Chris Benham > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting - > Since I regard? "IRV" (the Alternative Vote,?unlimited strict > ranking?"version") as > one of? the good methods, the best in my judgement of the methods that meet > Later-no-Harm,?I am encouraged to respond? to Kathy Dopp's anti-IRV propaganda > piece. > Chris, All of your points have already been addressed in my paper or by Abd ul Rahman Lomax on this list. For example, re "later no harm": "Later-No-Harm", that a lower preference cannot harm a higher preference, is FairVote's favorite election criterion. "Later-No-Harm", however, is incompatible with the basic principles of majority rule, which requires compromise if decisions are to be made. That's because the peculiar design of sequential elimination guarantees -- if a majority is not required -- that a lower preference cannot harm a higher preference, because the lower preferences are only considered if a higher one is eliminated. But many think that later-no-harm is undesirable because it interferes with the process of equitable compromise that is essential to the social cooperation that voting is supposed to facilitate. If I am negotiating with my neighbor, and his preferred option differs from mine, if I reveal that some compromise option is acceptable to me, before I'm certain that my favorite won't be chosen, then I may "harm" the
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting
> Date: Fri, 20 Jun 2008 13:29:17 -0700 (PDT) > From: Chris Benham <[EMAIL PROTECTED]> > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting - > Since I regard? "IRV" (the Alternative Vote,?unlimited strict > ranking?"version") as > one of? the good methods, the best in my judgement of the methods that meet > Later-no-Harm,?I am encouraged to respond? to Kathy Dopp's anti-IRV propaganda > piece. > Chris, All of your points have already been addressed in my paper or by Abd ul Rahman Lomax on this list. For example, re "later no harm": "Later-No-Harm", that a lower preference cannot harm a higher preference, is FairVote's favorite election criterion. "Later-No-Harm", however, is incompatible with the basic principles of majority rule, which requires compromise if decisions are to be made. That's because the peculiar design of sequential elimination guarantees -- if a majority is not required -- that a lower preference cannot harm a higher preference, because the lower preferences are only considered if a higher one is eliminated. But many think that later-no-harm is undesirable because it interferes with the process of equitable compromise that is essential to the social cooperation that voting is supposed to facilitate. If I am negotiating with my neighbor, and his preferred option differs from mine, if I reveal that some compromise option is acceptable to me, before I'm certain that my favorite won't be chosen, then I may "harm" the chance of my favorite being chosen. If the method my neighbor and I used to help us make the decision *requires* later-no-harm, it will interfere with the negotiation process, make it more difficult to find mutually acceptable solutions. On the other hand, the "harm" in Bucklin method of counting votes only occurs if your favorite doesn't win by a majority in the first round. BTW, you are in point of fact, incorrect that some voting methods do not meet Arrow's "independence of alternatives" condition, that is unless, like Arrow, you are excluding all rating voting methods like range and approval voting. If I am wrong in this, then you will be able to provide an example using the range or approval voting method which does not meet this Arrows' condition that "the introduction of a nonwinning candidate changes the outcome of who wins", not merely make the claim without any supporting example. -- All your questions are either already answered in my paper somewhere or are deliberately not addressed in my paper because the topic of the paper is restricted to the flaws and benefits of the IRV method and only touches on other topics only as necessary to provide an overview, as in the recent appendix supplied by voting system experts. Please re-read my paper again and I am certain that you will see this. Thank you for correcting my grammatical mistake in using "criteria" where I should have used "criterion". Cheers, Kathy Dopp Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting - Not What It Seems
Hello, Since I regard "IRV" (the Alternative Vote, unlimited strict ranking "version") as one of the good methods, the best in my judgement of the methods that meet Later-no-Harm, I am encouraged to respond to Kathy Dopp's anti-IRV propaganda piece. Some Fairness Principles for Voting MethodsConditions have been proposed to judge whether or not voting and vote-counting methods result in fair or in non-fair, paradoxical election results. 1. The addition of an alternative (candidate) who does not win should not affect the outcome. If you have an election contest where candidate A wins, and you introduce a new candidate C, then either candidate A should still win, or candidate C should now win. In other words, spoilers should not be possible or the addition of an alternative (or candidate) that doesn't win should not affect the outcome. This is some times called "independence of irrelevant alternatives" that says that the collective preference order of any pair of alternatives x and y must depend solely on the individual voters' preferences between these alternatives and not on their preferences for other irrelevant (nonwinning) alternatives. IRV does elections where "spoilers" determined who won, neither does the existing plurality voting method meet this condition. do seem to meet this fairness condition.not meet this condition of fairness. (See appendix A.) As we’ve seen from prior U.S.ix Other alternative voting methods, such as approval or range voting In practical effect *no* method meets this.Approval and Range can be said to meet Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives (IIA) only if the votes are interpreted as the voters giving ratings on some fixed scale that is independent of the actual candidates. On this perverse interpretation Approval and Range do not reduce to FPP in the 2 candidate election, in violation of Dopp's "fairness principle 4": .Any candidate who is the favorite [first] choice of a majority of voters should win I don't see what IIA actually has to do with "fairness". To me it is only about congruity or mathematical elegance. 2. must be preferred to alternative y in the collective preference order result]. This is some times called the "Pareto condition" that says whenever all individuals prefer an alternative x to another y then x must be preferred to y in the collective preference order. It is possible to find examples of when IRV and plurality voting violate this fairness condition.Whenever all individuals prefer an alternative x to another alternative y then alternative xx [the final election No it isn't. And why in a single-winner election method do we care about the whole "collective preference order" instead of just the winner? (See appendix B.) There is no example of IRV or plurality voting failing Pareto in appendix B, only one of Approval meeting it.3. The candidate who wins should have received a majority of voters’ votes.Some jurisdictions require winning candidates to have a majority (more votes than 50% of the ballots cast by voters). Maybe so, but should they? I gather that if this requirement isn't met, the decision on who fills the office is taken out of the hands of the voters. Some voting methods, such as plurality voting and IRV condition. Actual top-two runoff elections do.do not meet this Only if "voters" means only those who showed up for the second round. Say in a 3 candidate election, I can't see any justification for making this big distinction between a "majority" in the second round of Top-Two Runoff (TTR) and the majority of voters who participate in the second round of IRV. Kathy, do you insist that the election method requires voters to make second trip to the polls whenever the first doesn't produce a winner who "receives a majority of voters' votes"? Two-round methods can have their plusses, but in general I think it is more appropriate to compare IRV only with other decisive single-round methods. But while we're here, IRV (Alternative Vote, unlimited ranking) dominates TTR in terms of criterion compliances, including those that relate to "majority rule". Both TTR and IRV meet Condorcet Loser, but IRV (Alt.V, unlimited ranking) has the extra advantages over plurality voting (FPP) of meeting Majority for Solid Coalitions (aka Mutual Majority), Mutual Dominant Third, and Clone-Winner. 4. IRV does not always pick a majority winner out of all ballots cast, IRV proponents emphasize that candidate as the winner. However, the existing plurality voting method also meets this condition, which IRV proponents call the "majority criteria".Any candidate who is the favorite [first] choice of a majority of voters should win. Whileif a majority winner exists among voters’ first choices, then IRV will always select this I think some call this the "Majority Criterion" ("criteria" is the plural of *criterion*). I and others prefer the name "Majority Favorite". It isn
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting - Not What ItSeems
Chris I had no problem in Copying & Pasting from the PDF file given at the link in Kathy Dopp's e-mailed version of the revised news release: The full report "Realities Mar Instant Runoff Voting - 17 Flaws and 3 Benefits" is found on-line at http://electionarchive.org/ucvAnalysis/US/RCV-IRV/InstantRunoffVotingFlaws.pdf James > -Original Message- > From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] > [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On > Behalf Of Chris Benham > Sent: Wednesday, June 18, 2008 5:07 AM > To: EM > Cc: Kathy Dopp > Subject: Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff > Voting - Not What ItSeems > > > Does anyone know of any way of getting access to some version > of Kathy Dopp's IRV paper from which it is possible to copy > and paste? > > Chris Benham > Kathy Dopp kathy.dopp at gmail.com > Mon Jun 16 15:14:22 PDT 2008 > > RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting - Not What It Seems > By The National Election Data Archive > Park City, UT June 16, 2008 No virus found in this outgoing message. Checked by AVG. Version: 7.5.524 / Virus Database: 270.3.0/1505 - Release Date: 16/06/2008 07:20 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
Re: [Election-Methods] RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting - Not What It Seems
Does anyone know of any way of getting access to some version of Kathy Dopp's IRV paper from which it is possible to copy and paste? Chris Benham Kathy Dopp kathy.dopp at gmail.com Mon Jun 16 15:14:22 PDT 2008 RELEASE: Instant Runoff Voting - Not What It Seems By The National Election Data Archive Park City, UT June 16, 2008 Get the name you always wanted with the new y7mail email address. www.yahoo7.com.au/mail Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info