Re: ... cosmology? KNIGHT KNAVE

2004-07-28 Thread Bruno Marchal
Hi John,
At 17:19 26/07/04 -0400, John M wrote:
Bruno, (and ClassG)
We have an overwhelming ignorance about Ks and Ks. We don't know their
logical built, their knowledege-base, their behavior.

Indeed.

Is the K vs K rule a physical, or rather human statement, when - in the
latter case there may be violations (punishable by jail - ha ha).

Neither physical, nor human ... (see below).

Do K  K abide by 100.00% by the ONE rule we know about them, or ~99.999%,
when there still may be an aberration?

100,00%

Are they robots or humans? Looks like
machines. Are machines omniscient?

Interesting question (not addressed by Smullyan!). But easy though.
From Godel's incompleteness (which we have not yet proved,
except in the diagonalisation post some time ago, but on which
we will come back: it is the heart of the matter in FU's term),
it will be easy to prove that:
- Machine cannot be omniscient.
- Both knight and knaves are omniscient, and so they cannot
  be machine.
I expect, but will not argue now, that knights cannot exist at all,
even in platonia (and this with or without comp).
Does this throws doubts on what we can infer from FU's puzzles?
No, because the KK island is just a pedagogical tool for building
a fictive but easily imaginable situation where reasoners must
believe some self-referential propositions. But with the diagonalization
lemma (alias the heart of the matter) we will eliminate the need of the
KK island. It is the logical fate of the correct machine to meet
inescapably true and believable (provable) self-referential propositions,
from which we can derive true but unbelievable propositions,
... and much more.
Bruno
PS: Thanks to those who have send me hard puzzles! I will try to solve
them after 16 August. I will be busy until then. I will just answer Hal
Finney KK Posts, and then finish my paper. I hope I will get the authorization
to make it public soon for it will be a good base to proceed on. It is a
step toward the English paper I promised to Wei Dai, a long time ago.
http://iridia.ulb.ac.be/~marchal/


Re: ... cosmology? KNIGHT KNAVE

2004-07-28 Thread Bruno Marchal
At 09:54 27/07/04 -0700, Hal Finney wrote:
I am confused about how belief works in this logical reasoner of type 1.
Suppose I am such a reasoner.  I can be thought of as a theorem-proving
machine who uses logic to draw conclusions from premises.  We can imagine
there is a numbered list of everything I believe and have concluded.
It starts with my premises and then I add to it with my conclusions.

OK.


In this case my premises might be:
1. Knights always tell the truth
2. Knaves always lie
3. Every native is either a knight or a knave
4. A native said, you will never believe I am a knight.
Now we can start drawing conclusions.  Let t be the proposition that
the native is a knight (and hence tells the truth).  Then 3 implies:
5. t or ~t
Point 4 leads to two conclusions:
6. t implies ~Bt
7. ~t implies Bt
Here I use ~ for not, and Bx for I believe x.  I am ignoring some
complexities involving the future tense of the word will but I think
that is OK.

Perfect. Here Hal believes p means that sooner or later Hal will
assert, believe or prove p. It means p belongs to the list you mentionned.


However now I am confused.  How do I work with this letter B?  What kind
of rules does it follow?
I understand that Bx, I believe x, is merely a shorthand for saying that
x is on my list of premises/conclusions.

Correct. This means Bx is a equivalent with Hal believes x. The
only difference is that Bx is supposed to be in the language of the machine.


If I ever write down x on
my numbered list, I could also write down Bx and BBx and BBBx as far
as I feel like going.  Is this correct?

Well, not necessarily. Unless you are a normal machine, which
I hope you are!
So let us accept the following definition: a machine is normal when,
if it ever assert x, it will sooner or later asserts Bx.
Normality is a form of self-awareness: when the machine believes x,
it will believe Bx, that is it will believe that it will believe x.


But what about the other direction?  From Bx, can I deduce x?  That's
pretty important for this puzzle.  If Bx merely is a shorthand for
saying that x is on my list, then it seems fair to say that if I ever
write down Bx I can also write down x.  But this seems too powerful.

You are right. It is powerful, but rather fair also.
let us define a machine to be stable if that is the case. When the
machine believes Bx the machine believes x.


So what are the correct rules that I, as a simple machine, can follow for
dealing with the letter B?

Actually we will be interested in a lot of sort of machine. But I do
hope you are both normal and stable. Actually I'm sure you are.


The problem is that the rules I proposed here lead to a contradiction.
If x implies Bx, then I can write down:
8. t implies Bt
Note, this does not mean that if he is a knight I believe it, but rather
that if I ever deduce he is a knight, I believe it, which is simply the
definition of believe in this context.

Here you are mistaken. It is funny because you clearly see
the mistake, given that you say 'attention  (t implies Bt) does
not mean if he is a knight the I believe it. But of course (t implies Bt)
*does* mean if he is a knight the I believe it. You add it means only
(and here I add a slight correction) if I ever deduce he is a knight I
will deduce I believe he is a knight which really is, in the machine
language: (Bt implies BBt) instead of (t implies Bt).
To be sure: a machine is normal if for any proposition p, if the machine
believes p, it will believe Bp. But this is equivalent with saying
that for any proposition p, the proposition (Bp implies BBp) is true
*about* the machine.
Same remark for stability: you can say a machine is stable
if all the propositions (BBp implies Bp) are true about the machine.
This does not mean the stable or normal machine will ever believe
being stable or normal. You have (momentarily) confuse a proposition
being true on a machine, and being believe by a machine.


But 6 and 8 together mean that t implies a contradiction, hence I can 
conclude:

9. ~t
He is a knave.  7 then implies
10. Bt
I believe he is a knight.  And if Bx implies x, then:
11. t
and I have reached a contradiction with 9.
So I don't think I am doing this right.

By taking into account the confusion above, you should be able
to prove, with t still the same proposition (that is (t - -Bt)), that
(in case you are a normal reasoner of type 1):
if you are consistent, then t is not provable (believable, assertable by you)
if you are consistent and stable, then -t is not provable either.
That's Godel's first incompleteness theorem. (once we eliminate
the KK island from the reasoning to be sure). Bravo.
To sum up; any normal stable reasoner of type 1 meeting
a knight saying you will never believe I'm a knight will be
forever incomplete. (incomplete = there is a proposition like t,
which is neither provable nor refutable).
And so a machine cannot be omniscient because, although
the KK island does not exist, the diagonalization lemma
will 

Re: Quantum Rebel

2004-07-28 Thread CMR
Oops, I too was a victim of viral paranoia this AM and committed wholesale
deletion of all attachment laden emails in my box including, apparently,
Russel's. letter. Can someone send or forward me a copy? (of the letter not
a virus) ;)

Thanks!


 Please, Russell,
 for the peace of our minds who believe in 'smart' viruses and have none of
 the software you indicated:
 Could you at least put a word in the e-mail that thei comes from you? (eg
 Safe from RS or from Russ etc.)
 I wanted to open this attachment in blind face and paranoid shiver,
however
 went first to FILE - Properties - 2nd page and checked the from line at
 the bottom.  Boring. Even there it may be a virus usiing your mailbox -
 before you detect it.
 I am not the only one suffering from virus-paranioa.
 Cheerz
 John Mikes



Re: Quantum Rebel

2004-07-28 Thread Saibal Mitra
I just read the New Scientist article Quantum Rebel last night about
Shariar Afshar's work on the double slit experiment. Ingenious as the
experiment is, I really don't think it says anything about different
interpretations of QM. Indeed, the outcome of the experiment is just
what I'd expect from quantum theory, regardless of which
interpretation is used.

OK - so the claim is that Bohr's complementarity principle (CP) is tested
by this experiment and found wanting. I decided to go back to the two
text books I learnt quantum mechanics from - Leonard Schiff's book
which is the older and more traditional of the two, and Rammamurti
Shankar's book which has the more modern approach, but which I found
explained things better. Shankar doesn't mention the CP at all, and
for Schiff, the CP is basically a restatement of the Heisenberg
uncertainty principle, a principle not tested by Afshar's experiment.

In the double slit experiment, how I understand the CP to work is that
one cannot measure which slit a photon passes through, and retain an
interference pattern. Assuming it is possible to do this, one could
divide the measures data into those photons that passed through slit A,
and those that passed through slit B. The resulting distribution of
photons arriving at the screen of
the two slit experiment is then the sum of the distributions of the
two subsets of data. However, the two sub distributions do not have
inteference patterns so how can the sum have an interference
pattern. Hence any such measurement of which slit the photon passes
through must affect the photons so as to destroy the intereference
pattern.

Now in the article, Afshar claims to have measured which slit the
photon passed through and verified the existence of an interference
pattern. However, this is not the case - without the wires in
place to detect the presence of the interference pattern, photons
arriving at detector A have passed through slit A, and vice-versa with
detector B and slit B. However, with the wires in place, some photons
are scattered, indeed some photons which passed through slit A will
arrive at detector B. With both slits open, and the wire placed
exactly at a null point of the interference pattern, the photons
passing through slit A and arriving at detector B exactly counteracts
the photons passing thoguh slit B that have been lost through
scattering. The mathematics of quantum mechanics assures this,
coincidental this may seem.

It may be a question of interpretations of interpretations of QM,
however on the basis of the New Scientist article, I don't believe
Afshar have shown a problem with the complementarity principle.

  Cheers

--
*PS: A number of people ask me about the attachment to my email, which
is of type application/pgp-signature. Don't worry, it is not a
virus. It is an electronic signature, that may be used to verify this
email came from me if you have PGP or GPG installed. Otherwise, you
may safely ignore this attachment.


A/Prof Russell Standish  Director
High Performance Computing Support Unit, Phone 9385 6967, 8308 3119 (mobile)
UNSW SYDNEY 2052   Fax   9385 6965, 0425 253119 ()
Australia[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Room 2075, Red Centrehttp://parallel.hpc.unsw.edu.au/rks
International prefix  +612, Interstate prefix 02


- Oorspronkelijk bericht -
Van: CMR [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Aan: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Verzonden: Wednesday, July 28, 2004 03:40 PM
Onderwerp: Re: Quantum Rebel


 Oops, I too was a victim of viral paranoia this AM and committed wholesale
 deletion of all attachment laden emails in my box including, apparently,
 Russel's. letter. Can someone send or forward me a copy? (of the letter
not
 a virus) ;)

 Thanks!


  Please, Russell,
  for the peace of our minds who believe in 'smart' viruses and have none
of
  the software you indicated:
  Could you at least put a word in the e-mail that thei comes from you?
(eg
  Safe from RS or from Russ etc.)
  I wanted to open this attachment in blind face and paranoid shiver,
 however
  went first to FILE - Properties - 2nd page and checked the from line
at
  the bottom.  Boring. Even there it may be a virus usiing your mailbox -
  before you detect it.
  I am not the only one suffering from virus-paranioa.
  Cheerz
  John Mikes




Re: Quantum Rebel

2004-07-28 Thread Jeanne Houston
I also deleted everything immediately, fearing the viral possibilities of
the attachments.

Jeanne

- Original Message - 
From: CMR [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Wednesday, July 28, 2004 9:40 AM
Subject: Re: Quantum Rebel


 Oops, I too was a victim of viral paranoia this AM and committed wholesale
 deletion of all attachment laden emails in my box including, apparently,
 Russel's. letter. Can someone send or forward me a copy? (of the letter
not
 a virus) ;)

 Thanks!


  Please, Russell,
  for the peace of our minds who believe in 'smart' viruses and have none
of
  the software you indicated:
  Could you at least put a word in the e-mail that thei comes from you?
(eg
  Safe from RS or from Russ etc.)
  I wanted to open this attachment in blind face and paranoid shiver,
 however
  went first to FILE - Properties - 2nd page and checked the from line
at
  the bottom.  Boring. Even there it may be a virus usiing your mailbox -
  before you detect it.
  I am not the only one suffering from virus-paranioa.
  Cheerz
  John Mikes




Re: Quantum Rebel

2004-07-28 Thread Saibal Mitra
The probability that Russell's message contained a virus was low (he uses
linux) but nonzero. So, I guess that's bad news for some of my copies in the
multiverse.


- Oorspronkelijk bericht -
Van: Jeanne Houston [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Aan: CMR [EMAIL PROTECTED]; [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Verzonden: Wednesday, July 28, 2004 04:20 PM
Onderwerp: Re: Quantum Rebel


 I also deleted everything immediately, fearing the viral possibilities of
 the attachments.

 Jeanne

 - Original Message -
 From: CMR [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 Sent: Wednesday, July 28, 2004 9:40 AM
 Subject: Re: Quantum Rebel


  Oops, I too was a victim of viral paranoia this AM and committed
wholesale
  deletion of all attachment laden emails in my box including, apparently,
  Russel's. letter. Can someone send or forward me a copy? (of the letter
 not
  a virus) ;)
 
  Thanks!
 
 
   Please, Russell,
   for the peace of our minds who believe in 'smart' viruses and have
none
 of
   the software you indicated:
   Could you at least put a word in the e-mail that thei comes from you?
 (eg
   Safe from RS or from Russ etc.)
   I wanted to open this attachment in blind face and paranoid shiver,
  however
   went first to FILE - Properties - 2nd page and checked the from line
 at
   the bottom.  Boring. Even there it may be a virus usiing your
mailbox -
   before you detect it.
   I am not the only one suffering from virus-paranioa.
   Cheerz
   John Mikes
 




Re: Quantum Rebel

2004-07-28 Thread scerir
Saibal Mitra fwded

 It may be a question of interpretations of interpretations of QM,
 however on the basis of the New Scientist article, I don't believe
 Afshar have shown a problem with the complementarity principle.

I agree. But imagine the usual two-slit set-up. And this
unusual screen, to reveal the interference pattern ...
_
_
_
_
_
_

They are a set of photographic plates, they can register
both the photons and their directions, i.e. if they come
from the upper or from the lower slit (photons coming from
the upper slit hit the upper face of the photographic plate,
photons coming from the lower slit hit the lower face, there
is a principle of conservation of momentum after all).

Calculations made by Zurek and Wooters show that this kind
of screen works, that is it can reveal - in principle - both
the welcher weg and the interference pattern.

But the complementarity principle forbids that. 
  
 *PS: A number of people ask me about the attachment to my email, which
 is of type application/pgp-signature. 

The problem with that signature is that we (or just me?) do not receive
any text, in the body of the msg. Just blank.



Re: ... cosmology? KNIGHT KNAVE

2004-07-28 Thread Hal Finney
This is confusing because I believe p has two different meanings.
One is that I have written down p with a number in front of it,
as one of my theorems.  The other meaning is the string Bp.

But that string only has meaning from the perspective of an outside
observer.  To me, as the machine, it is just a pair of letters.  B doesn't
have to mean believe.  It could mean Belachen, which is German for
believe.

All I need to know, as a formal system, is what rules the letter B
follows.

Bruno wrote:

 At 09:54 27/07/04 -0700, Hal Finney wrote:
 If I ever write down x on
 my numbered list, I could also write down Bx and BBx and BBBx as far
 as I feel like going.  Is this correct?

 Well, not necessarily. Unless you are a normal machine, which
 I hope you are!
 So let us accept the following definition: a machine is normal when,
 if it ever assert x, it will sooner or later asserts Bx.
 Normality is a form of self-awareness: when the machine believes x,
 it will believe Bx, that is it will believe that it will believe x.


 But what about the other direction?  From Bx, can I deduce x?  That's
 pretty important for this puzzle.  If Bx merely is a shorthand for
 saying that x is on my list, then it seems fair to say that if I ever
 write down Bx I can also write down x.  But this seems too powerful.

 You are right. It is powerful, but rather fair also.
 let us define a machine to be stable if that is the case. When the
 machine believes Bx the machine believes x.

So in my terms, I can add two axioms:

0a. x implies Bx
0b. Bx implies x

The first is the axiom of normality, and the second is the axiom of
stability.  I don't find these words to be particularly appropriate,
by the way, but I suppose they are traditional.

It also seems to me that these axioms, which define the behavior of
the letter B, don't particularly well represent the concept of belief.
The problem is that beliefs can be uncertain and don't follow the law
of the excluded middle.  If p is that there is life on Mars, then (p or
~p) is true.  Either there's life there or there isn't.  But it's not
true that (Bp or B~p).  It's not the case that either I believe there
is life on Mars or I believe there is no life on Mars.  The truth is,
I don't believe either way.

But axioms 0a and 0b let me conclude (Bp or B~p).  Obviously they
collectively imply p if and only if Bp.  Therefore from (p or ~p)
we can immediately get (Bp or B~p).  Hence for normal people, the law
of the excluded middle applies to beliefs.

This proof is pure logic and has no dependence on the meaning of B.
If B is Belachen, I have showed that if p implies Belachen(p), then
it follows that (Belachen(p) or Belachen(~p)) is true.  That's all.

It's a step outside the system to say that B follows rules which make it
appropriate for us to treat it as meaning believes.  But do 0a. and
0b. really capture the meaning of belief?  I question that.  B looks
more like an identity operator under those axioms.

 The problem is that the rules I proposed here lead to a contradiction.
 If x implies Bx, then I can write down:
 
 8. t implies Bt
 
 Note, this does not mean that if he is a knight I believe it, but rather
 that if I ever deduce he is a knight, I believe it, which is simply the
 definition of believe in this context.


 Here you are mistaken. It is funny because you clearly see
 the mistake, given that you say 'attention  (t implies Bt) does
 not mean if he is a knight the I believe it. But of course (t implies Bt)
 *does* mean if he is a knight the I believe it.

I don't see this.  To me as the machine, there is no meaning.  I am just
playing with letters.  t implies Bt is only a shorthand for if he is a
knight then B(if he is a knight).  There is no more meaning than that.
The letter B is just a letter that follows certain rules.

We only get meaning from outside, when we look at what the machine is
doing and try to relate the way the rules work to concepts in the real
world.  It is at this point that we bring in the interpretation of Bx as
the machine believes x.

Suppose for some proposition q the machine deduces it on step 117:

117. q

Does this mean that q is true?  No, it means that that the machine
believes q.  Does it mean that Bq is true?  Yes.  Bq is true, because Bq
is a shorthand for saying that the machine believes q, and by definition
the machine believes something when it writes it down in its numbered
list.  We can see it right there, number 117.  So the machine believes
q and Bq is true.  But q is not (necessarily) true.  The machine writing
something down does not mean it is true.  By definition, it means the
machine believes it.

Consider a different example:

191. Bp

What does this mean?  Does it mean that Bp is true?  No, it means that the
machine believes Bp, because by definition, what the machine writes down
in its numbered list is what it believes.  Is BBp true?  Yes, it is true,
because that says that the machine believes Bp, and that means that Bp
is in the 

Re: Quantum Rebel

2004-07-28 Thread Jesse Mazer
Saibal Mitra wrote:
Now in the article, Afshar claims to have measured which slit the
photon passed through and verified the existence of an interference
pattern. However, this is not the case - without the wires in
place to detect the presence of the interference pattern, photons
arriving at detector A have passed through slit A, and vice-versa with
detector B and slit B. However, with the wires in place, some photons
are scattered, indeed some photons which passed through slit A will
arrive at detector B. With both slits open, and the wire placed
exactly at a null point of the interference pattern, the photons
passing through slit A and arriving at detector B exactly counteracts
the photons passing thoguh slit B that have been lost through
scattering. The mathematics of quantum mechanics assures this,
coincidental this may seem.
A poster on sci.physics.research elaborates on this point a little with a 
nice thought-experiment involving enlarging the wires until they are almost 
touching, at which point you just have a new set of slits:

http://makeashorterlink.com/?W3F012BE8
Now I haven't done any calculations or read the New Scientist article
except looking at the lab setup graphics, but if I would hazard a quick
guess, it would be that it will turn out that even if the wires are
placed in the interference fields valleys, the finite width of the
wires will diffract just enough photons to erase the which-way
information that was gained by focusing the detectors at the holes in
the wall through the lens.
Consider the limiting case with wires placed with their centres in the
interference fields valleys as before, but expand their width so much
that they almost touch each other. What you have now is yet another
wall with a bunch of slits in! Obviously, almost all which-way
information is lost after the wavefronts pass these almost
infinitesimal slits since they will diffract the photons equally no
matter from which hole in the *first* wall they originated, so any
detector placed after this obstacle will be like running a new
multiple-slit interference setup (although with the lens now severely
defocusing the too-closely placed new slits). And since the which-way
information from the first wall is erased, interference is free to
happen between the first and the second wall. After the secondary wall
the detectors can pick up which-way information causing them to behave
as if there was little subsequent interference.
Conversely, the other limiting case is with no wires (or secondary
wall) present. Then all which-way information is present and again the
detectors behave as if there was no interference.
The experiment shows a case in between these limits and the effect I
guessed at above could (and should, according to traditional QM) turn
out to always cancel any attempt to find both 100% interference and
100% which-way information. This would be better showed with some
calculations of course...



Re: Quantum Rebel

2004-07-28 Thread Jesse Mazer
Actually, looking at the diagram and explanation of the experiment posted at 
http://www.kathryncramer.com/wblog/archives/000674.html I think Saibal Mitra 
and the sci.physics.research poster I quoted may have misunderstood what 
happened in this experiment. I may have misunderstood, but it sounded as if 
both were arguing that the finite width of the wires could erase some of the 
which-path information and explain why you'd see interference at the final 
detectors. But the diagram seems to say that *no* interference was found at 
the detectorsthe interference Afshar is talking about was just in the 
fact that no photons were scattering against the wires because they were all 
placed in the interference valleys. So the idea seems to be that 
interference is the explanation for why no photons scatter against the 
wires, but the focusing lens behind the wires makes sure that photons from 
the left slit always go to the left detector and the photons from the right 
slit always go to the right detector--this is the violation of 
complementarity, that the photons behave like a wave in avoiding the wires 
but behave like particles when arriving at the detectors. I'm not sure that 
the notion of complementarity has ever been sufficiently well-defined to 
say that this experiment violates it though, and in any case, as long as the 
results of the experiment match the predictions made by the standard theory 
of quantum mechanics, it cannot be taken as a disproof of the Everett 
interpretation, since the basic idea of the Everett interpretation is to 
keep the standard rules for wavefunction evolution but just to drop the 
collapse idea (the projection postulate).

Jesse



Re: Quantum Rebel

2004-07-28 Thread Saibal Mitra
Not me but Russell wrote that. I should have made that clear better when I
posted Russell's attachment (Sorry Russell!).


- Oorspronkelijk bericht -
Van: Jesse Mazer [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Aan: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Verzonden: Wednesday, July 28, 2004 08:59 PM
Onderwerp: Re: Quantum Rebel


 Saibal Mitra wrote:

 Now in the article, Afshar claims to have measured which slit the
 photon passed through and verified the existence of an interference
 pattern. However, this is not the case - without the wires in
 place to detect the presence of the interference pattern, photons
 arriving at detector A have passed through slit A, and vice-versa with
 detector B and slit B. However, with the wires in place, some photons
 are scattered, indeed some photons which passed through slit A will
 arrive at detector B. With both slits open, and the wire placed
 exactly at a null point of the interference pattern, the photons
 passing through slit A and arriving at detector B exactly counteracts
 the photons passing thoguh slit B that have been lost through
 scattering. The mathematics of quantum mechanics assures this,
 coincidental this may seem.

 A poster on sci.physics.research elaborates on this point a little with a
 nice thought-experiment involving enlarging the wires until they are
almost
 touching, at which point you just have a new set of slits:

 http://makeashorterlink.com/?W3F012BE8

 Now I haven't done any calculations or read the New Scientist article
 except looking at the lab setup graphics, but if I would hazard a quick
 guess, it would be that it will turn out that even if the wires are
 placed in the interference fields valleys, the finite width of the
 wires will diffract just enough photons to erase the which-way
 information that was gained by focusing the detectors at the holes in
 the wall through the lens.
 
 Consider the limiting case with wires placed with their centres in the
 interference fields valleys as before, but expand their width so much
 that they almost touch each other. What you have now is yet another
 wall with a bunch of slits in! Obviously, almost all which-way
 information is lost after the wavefronts pass these almost
 infinitesimal slits since they will diffract the photons equally no
 matter from which hole in the *first* wall they originated, so any
 detector placed after this obstacle will be like running a new
 multiple-slit interference setup (although with the lens now severely
 defocusing the too-closely placed new slits). And since the which-way
 information from the first wall is erased, interference is free to
 happen between the first and the second wall. After the secondary wall
 the detectors can pick up which-way information causing them to behave
 as if there was little subsequent interference.
 
 Conversely, the other limiting case is with no wires (or secondary
 wall) present. Then all which-way information is present and again the
 detectors behave as if there was no interference.
 
 The experiment shows a case in between these limits and the effect I
 guessed at above could (and should, according to traditional QM) turn
 out to always cancel any attempt to find both 100% interference and
 100% which-way information. This would be better showed with some
 calculations of course...





Re: Quantum Rebel

2004-07-28 Thread Russell Standish
Can anyone tell me why the body of the email is blank to some people?
Is it some overzealous defang program the removes the body as well as
the attachment?

I don't care if the attachment is removed - it doesn't contain
information - its purpose is to authenticate the letter only, and can
be safely ignored by anyone who doesn't care.

I'll send this email unsigned, to make sure the body gets through...

Cheers

On Wed, Jul 28, 2004 at 06:08:40PM +0200, scerir wrote:
   
  *PS: A number of people ask me about the attachment to my email, which
  is of type application/pgp-signature. 
 
 The problem with that signature is that we (or just me?) do not receive
 any text, in the body of the msg. Just blank.

-- 
*PS: A number of people ask me about the attachment to my email, which
is of type application/pgp-signature. Don't worry, it is not a
virus. It is an electronic signature, that may be used to verify this
email came from me if you have PGP or GPG installed. Otherwise, you
may safely ignore this attachment.


A/Prof Russell Standish  Director
High Performance Computing Support Unit, Phone 9385 6967, 8308 3119 (mobile)
UNSW SYDNEY 2052 Fax   9385 6965, 0425 253119 ()
Australia[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Room 2075, Red Centrehttp://parallel.hpc.unsw.edu.au/rks
International prefix  +612, Interstate prefix 02