This is in response to Robin's comments on rationality.

I agree with Robin that institutions  shape the selves whose lives 
they structure, and in this context that the instrumentally rational agents 
that people rational choice models tend to be produced by the universal 
reign of markets. I think an appreciation of this, though, must lead to 
an attempt to formulate a thicker notion of rationality, if we are to do 
what Robin wants to do--evaluate institutions.

Once we appreciate the shaping of agency and preferences by institutions, 
the standard welfare criteria, such as Pareto-efficiency, become simply 
tests of "coherence" between the agent-creating institutions and the 
agents they create. Arguably, coherence in this sense is neither 
necessary nor sufficient for an institutional structure's being judged good.
Not sufficient: reread Brave New World. Not necessary either, because we 
might argue for the superiority of less coherent institutions which create 
unsatisfied 
Socratess to those which create satisfied pigs. (Apologies to Mill.)

The point is that to evaluate institutions is to evaluate a package:
institution-plus-types-of-agents, and we're then doing at the theoretical 
level what people do practically when they think not so much about how to 
get what they transparently want, but what sort of people they want to 
be, what sort of wants they should have. And the theorist should follow 
the practical agent in this: trying to articulate the sorts of criteria 
that are employed by the latter, and push for "reflective equilibrium".
Unless one thinks that reason has no place here, we as practical agents 
employ and we as "social scientists" need to articulate a thicker kind of 
rationality. In Susan Hurley's phrase, a theory of rationality for human 
agents is "an ethic". I put the quote marks around "scientist" advisedly: 
this sort of endeavor won't pass muster under conceptions of science 
which make it the neutral examination of some independently existing 
reality. 

Reply via email to