RE: The President and the Pope

2004-06-17 Thread Mark Graber



Suppose President 
Bush bribes a few legislators in order to get the last votes necessary to pass a 
constitutional amendment limiting marriage to one man and one woman. Could 
he defend his actions by pointing out that Seward may have used briberty to 
procure the last crucial votes necessary to get the 13th Amendment out of 
Congress.

1. A certain kind of Formalism. 
Bush and Seward stand and fall together. If the one can use bribery, the 
other can.

2. The issue matters. Bribery is 
justified only for particularly overwhelming causes. History is the 
ultimate justice. We think Seward behaved correctly because we think 
slavery a sufficient evil as to justify some bribery to procure abolition. 
Whether Bush would be right to bribe depends on what you think of his stance on 
cultural issues.

3. Sincerity matters. Seward was 
right because he was committed to abolition. Whether Bush is right depends 
on whether you think he is truly passionate about one man/one woman marriage, or 
whether he is hoping to gain votes on cultural issues to help the tax cuts, 
etc.

Of course, the claim that persons may 
violate certain norms in great causes seemingly privileges extremists, who think 
they have a monopoly on rectitude. But there is also a sense in which the 
law of self-defense will inspire more paranoids. At bottom, whether Bush 
(or a claim of self-defense) is justified depends on whether we think the cause 
was great enough and whether he sincerely thought the cause was great 
enough.

Mark A. Graber

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


Justice Thomas in Newdow

2004-06-17 Thread Rick Garnett
Dear all,
I apologize in advance, if I missed the list's discussion of Justice 
Thomas's views regarding the incorporation of the Establishment 
Clause.  For what it's worth, I've been surprised by the vigor with which 
several prominent scholars have disapproved these views.  Jack Balkin 
remarked, for example (www.balkin.blogspot.com), [n]ow we know what it 
would be like to have Judge Roy Moore on the Supreme Court.  Brian Leiter 
concludes that Justice Thomas has solidif[ied[ his status on the lunatic 
fringe (http://webapp.utexas.edu/blogs/archives/bleiter/001452.html).  And 
Doug Laycock states that Thomas's is a pretty astonishing view. . . . He 
acts as though the Civil War didn't happen, or it didn't matter 
(http://www.latimes.com/la-na-thomas17jun17,1,3892729.story).

It strikes me, though, that Thomas's observations, in Part II-A of his 
opinion, are not particularly astonishing, and certainly do nothing to put 
him on the lunatic fringe.  Does he say anything, in that Part of the 
opinion, that Steve Smith, Philip Hamburger, Gerry Bradley, Akhil Amar, and 
many others have not also said, namely, that the point of the Establishment 
Clause was to protect the States' then-existing establishments and 
perhaps also, more generally, to leave questions of church-state relations 
to the States?  And, with all due respect to Professor Laycock, I'm not 
sure it is fair to conclude that, because Justice Thomas agrees with those 
who believe that the Establishment Clause is particularly, and perhaps 
uniquely, unsuited for incorporation via the 14th Amendment (but see, e.g., 
Kurt Lash), he is therefore unmindful of the (obvious) sweeping changes 
that the post-Civil War Amendments worked in the constitutional law of 
individual rights.  (Recall, for example, his passionate concurrence in 
Zelman).

Now, I'm inclined to think that, merits aside, the matter is water under 
the bridge, and that Justice Thomas's views on this question -- like his 
views on the scope of the Commerce Clause -- are not likely to become 
governing constitutional law.  As Michael Perry likes to put it, the 
incorporation of the Establishment Clause has become bedrock.  Still, is 
there a reason why we should not concede that he is -- or, at least, MAY be 
-- correct?

Best,
Rick Garnett




At 04:26 AM 6/11/2004 -0500, you wrote:
Eugene, I agree that very global quid pro quo theories -- like broad
Establishment Clause, broad Free Exercise Clause -- do not spread their
benefits to all religions equally.  (For example, I think that broad
establishment clause, broad free exercise tends to protect or benefit
minority or outsider religions, although I'd qualify that statement in some
important ways.  I'm thinking about this now because I'm writing a piece
about minority religions.)
But more specific quid pro quo arguments, it seems to me, can rest on real
connections.  For example: Because public schools cannot include religious
teaching in their curriculum, there should be special concern to protect
religious private schools and families' ability to use them if they
conscientiously wish to have religoius instruction in their children's
education.  That connection is still not perfect -- not all families who
want religious instruction in education will belong to a denomination that
operates religious schools -- but the connection is real because there are
indeed many families who make such a choice between public education and
private religious schools.
As for more global quid pro quo notions:  although of course there are many,
many religious views, nevertheless there is a general category called
religion that is singled out for distinctive treatment in the Constitution
and therefore may require distinctive treatment by government actors.  Even
if a general quid pro quo approach doesn't benefit all faiths equally, it
seems to me that it can have the advantage of setting forth an approach that
doesn't treat religious activity just the same as every other activity, but
is principled in the ways it departs from that sameness treatment.  For
example, the Lee v. Weisman passage -- preservation and transmission of
religious beliefs and worship is a responsibility and a choice committed to
the private sphere, which itself is promised freedom to pursue that mission
-- gives a principled (though certainly disputable) reason for treating
religious activities distinctively in various legal situations.  When
someone asks, for example, Why should there be exemptions from law just for
religious conduct?, a possible answer is, It's part of this overall
approach to religion that is sensible and justifiable, for [X] reasons.  I
think that the fact that one can point to other places where religion is
treated differently helps make the overall approach more sensible and
justifiable (though, of course, still open to dispute).
Tom Berg
  _
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Wed 6/9/2004 11:29 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law 

Re: Justice Thomas in Newdow

2004-06-17 Thread Steven Jamar
bedrock.  Still, is there a reason why we should not concede that he 
is -- or, at least, MAY be -- correct?

Best,
Rick Garnett
The Civil War Amendments rewrote the Constitution.  People are entitled 
to protection against establishment period. Limiting the states is what 
happened with our second Constitution.  Broadening the federal power 
happened then and again with our third Constitution (New Deal-Warren 
Court).

While an academic may be excused for pondering parallel universes in 
writing, a Supreme Court Justice who does so in writing (as opposed to 
raising a point for discussion with law clerks and other judges) is 
perhaps not at the lunatic fringe, but is at at the very least near it.

What we may toss around as ideas on our listserve or in our classes or 
in person or even in serious scholarship is different from published 
opinions of the court.

Steve
--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8428
2900 Van Ness Street NW mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008  http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar
Lay not up for yourselves treasures upon earth, where moth and rust 
doth corrupt, and where thieves break through and steal; but lay up for 
yourselves treasures in heaven, where neither moth nor rust doth 
corrupt, and where thieves do not break through nor steal. For where 
your treasure is, there will your heart be also.

Matthew 6:19-21
___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


Re: Justice Thomas in Newdow

2004-06-17 Thread Douglas Laycock
The LA Times story is available on Westlaw for those who would 
like to read it without giving their phone number and income to the LA 
Times.  Expletives deleted.

Obviously the way you would explain what is wrong with Thomas's 
opinion on this list is different from how you would capsulize it in a 
sentence or two (selected by the reporter) for an explanation to the 
public.  But I do think that Thomas's opinion is both extreme and wrong.

He did not say merely that the clause does not apply against the 
states.  He also said that the clause creates no individual rights.  The 
only apparent application of this second pronouncement is that it creates 
no individual rights against the federal government either.  So every 
Establishment Clause case the Court has ever decided would be obliterated 
at a stroke.  He seems to assume that the free exercise clause would 
prevent coerced attendance at religious services -- unless, we have to 
assume, the service is rather short and is incorporated into some other 
official event that people attend for secular reasons.

I do not doubt that one meaning of the Clause in 1791 was that the 
federal government could not interfere with establishments in the 
states.  But I am equally sure that one meaning of the Clause in 1791 was 
that the federal government could take no steps toward a federal 
establishment of religion -- not in the states, and not in the federal 
district either.  Either a federal establishment or a federal interference 
with a state establishment would be a law respecting an establishment.

The debate in the First Congress did not focus on the federalism 
implications.  It focused on the meaning of establishment, and on how far 
the federal government should be restricted.  The argument for prohibiting 
only preferential aid to favored denominations was rejected; the most 
broadly worded draft proposed was adopted.  This of course goes to the 
debate over nonpreferentialism; but even before that, it goes to whether 
this Clause was only about federalism, or also about the proper 
relationship between religion and government.  The debate was plainly about 
the latter; I think the federalism-only interpretation is demonstrably wrong.

I'm not sure the federalism principle that can be derived from the 
verb respecting and the existence of state establishments is much 
different from the federalism principle that is implicit in the 
constitutional structure about other individual rights good only against 
the federal government.  Certainly the federal government in 1791 had no 
general power to protect individual liberties against state restrictions on 
free speech (blasphemy, defamation, perhaps others) or free exercise 
(voting confined to Christians, or to Protestants; the Lousiana law on 
Catholic funerals that got to the Supreme Court in 1845 and produced a 
repeat of Barron v. Baltimore); or any other individual right.  Any attempt 
to incorporate implicit and explicit rules that the federal government 
could not interfere with state restrictions on liberty would indeed lead to 
nonsense.

What is incorporated is the protection for individual liberty in 
each constitutional right.  The states cannot do to citizens what the feds 
could not do to citizens.  The restrictions on government sponsorship of 
religion play an essential role in protecting the religious liberty of 
individuals; I am entirely comfortable concluding that those restrictions 
are a privilege or immunity of citizens of the United States, just like the 
restrictions on government interference with free speech or free 
exercise.  I understand the argument that the Establishment Clause doesn't 
speak to what government can do to individuals in the same way as the other 
provisions of the Bill of Rights, but I think that badly underestimates the 
role of the Establishment Clause in protecting individual liberty.


At 02:25 PM 6/17/2004 -0500, you wrote:
Dear all,
I apologize in advance, if I missed the list's discussion of Justice 
Thomas's views regarding the incorporation of the Establishment 
Clause.  For what it's worth, I've been surprised by the vigor with which 
several prominent scholars have disapproved these views.  Jack Balkin 
remarked, for example (www.balkin.blogspot.com), [n]ow we know what it 
would be like to have Judge Roy Moore on the Supreme Court.  Brian Leiter 
concludes that Justice Thomas has solidif[ied[ his status on the lunatic 
fringe 
(http://webapp.utexas.edu/blogs/archives/bleiter/001452.html).  And Doug 
Laycock states that Thomas's is a pretty astonishing view. . . . He acts 
as though the Civil War didn't happen, or it didn't matter 
(http://www.latimes.com/la-na-thomas17jun17,1,3892729.story).

It strikes me, though, that Thomas's observations, in Part II-A of his 
opinion, are not particularly astonishing, and certainly do nothing to put 
him on the lunatic fringe.  Does he say anything, in 

Symposium on State Blaine Amendments

2004-06-17 Thread Paul Finkelman
I hope it is permissible to post this on the list-serve. I do so in my 
capacity as faculty advisor to the Tulsa Law Review.

--
Paul Finkelman
Chapman Distinguished Professor of Law
University of Tulsa College of Law
3120 East 4th Place
Tulsa, OK   74104-3189
918-631-3706 (office)
918-631-2194 (fax)
[EMAIL PROTECTED]

TULSA LAW REVIEW
CALL FOR SYMPOSIUM CONTRIBUTIONS
Blaine Amendments
Tulsa Law Review seeks contributions for its Winter 2004 issue dedicated 
to an off-site paper symposium discussing state Blaine Amendments and 
Blaine-like provisions. This discussion will be facilitated by the 
United States Supreme Courts decision in Locke v. Davey.

TLR seeks contributions of all typesincluding both articles and 
essaysfor inclusion in the symposium issue. Editing is expected to 
begin approximately September 13, 2004. TLR has provided a modest 
stipend for participation in past symposia and expects to be able to 
continue this practice.

Space in the symposium issue is limited. Interested authors are 
encouraged to contact TLR soon to reserve a place in the issue. Once the 
anticipated editing capacity has been reached, the issue must be closed.

For more information about the symposium issue or TLRs editing process, 
or to reserve a place in the symposium issue, please contact:

Dan Carsey, Editor-in-Chief
Tulsa Law Review
3120 E. Fourth Place
Tulsa, OK 74104
Phone: 918-631-3532
Email: [EMAIL PROTECTED]

-

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


RE: Justice Thomas in Newdow

2004-06-17 Thread marc stern
Isn't it the case that whether Thomas is correct or not depends in part on
whether only the text of the constitution (or the text and original intent)
is a relevant datum or whether accumulated cases law also counts as
constitutional law. On the text only vision of constitutional law, Thomas
has at least something to say, even if I think, with Doug, that he is wrong;
on the latter view, his opinion in the pledge case is simply an anomaly.
Marc Stern

-Original Message-
From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Thursday, June 17, 2004 4:21 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Justice Thomas in Newdow

 The LA Times story is available on Westlaw for those who would 
like to read it without giving their phone number and income to the LA 
Times.  Expletives deleted.

 Obviously the way you would explain what is wrong with Thomas's 
opinion on this list is different from how you would capsulize it in a 
sentence or two (selected by the reporter) for an explanation to the 
public.  But I do think that Thomas's opinion is both extreme and wrong.

 He did not say merely that the clause does not apply against the 
states.  He also said that the clause creates no individual rights.  The 
only apparent application of this second pronouncement is that it creates 
no individual rights against the federal government either.  So every 
Establishment Clause case the Court has ever decided would be obliterated 
at a stroke.  He seems to assume that the free exercise clause would 
prevent coerced attendance at religious services -- unless, we have to 
assume, the service is rather short and is incorporated into some other 
official event that people attend for secular reasons.

 I do not doubt that one meaning of the Clause in 1791 was that the 
federal government could not interfere with establishments in the 
states.  But I am equally sure that one meaning of the Clause in 1791 was 
that the federal government could take no steps toward a federal 
establishment of religion -- not in the states, and not in the federal 
district either.  Either a federal establishment or a federal interference 
with a state establishment would be a law respecting an establishment.

 The debate in the First Congress did not focus on the federalism 
implications.  It focused on the meaning of establishment, and on how far 
the federal government should be restricted.  The argument for prohibiting 
only preferential aid to favored denominations was rejected; the most 
broadly worded draft proposed was adopted.  This of course goes to the 
debate over nonpreferentialism; but even before that, it goes to whether 
this Clause was only about federalism, or also about the proper 
relationship between religion and government.  The debate was plainly about 
the latter; I think the federalism-only interpretation is demonstrably
wrong.

 I'm not sure the federalism principle that can be derived from the 
verb respecting and the existence of state establishments is much 
different from the federalism principle that is implicit in the 
constitutional structure about other individual rights good only against 
the federal government.  Certainly the federal government in 1791 had no 
general power to protect individual liberties against state restrictions on 
free speech (blasphemy, defamation, perhaps others) or free exercise 
(voting confined to Christians, or to Protestants; the Lousiana law on 
Catholic funerals that got to the Supreme Court in 1845 and produced a 
repeat of Barron v. Baltimore); or any other individual right.  Any attempt 
to incorporate implicit and explicit rules that the federal government 
could not interfere with state restrictions on liberty would indeed lead to 
nonsense.

 What is incorporated is the protection for individual liberty in 
each constitutional right.  The states cannot do to citizens what the feds 
could not do to citizens.  The restrictions on government sponsorship of 
religion play an essential role in protecting the religious liberty of 
individuals; I am entirely comfortable concluding that those restrictions 
are a privilege or immunity of citizens of the United States, just like the 
restrictions on government interference with free speech or free 
exercise.  I understand the argument that the Establishment Clause doesn't 
speak to what government can do to individuals in the same way as the other 
provisions of the Bill of Rights, but I think that badly underestimates the 
role of the Establishment Clause in protecting individual liberty.




At 02:25 PM 6/17/2004 -0500, you wrote:
Dear all,

I apologize in advance, if I missed the list's discussion of Justice 
Thomas's views regarding the incorporation of the Establishment 
Clause.  For what it's worth, I've been surprised by the vigor with which 
several prominent scholars have disapproved these views.  Jack Balkin 
remarked, 

Re: Justice Thomas in Newdow

2004-06-17 Thread Francis Beckwith
I don't think Thomas disbelieves that incorporation has occurred (or
happened), and that has included the establishment clause.  I think he is
questioning whether it is justified.  After all, in the same 1940s in which
Everson came down the pike so did the Japanese internment case. I don't
think anyone would accept as a justification of the latter the citation of
historical fact: broadening the federal power, including interning the
Japanese, happenend again with our third Constituiton (New Deal-Warren
Court. Yes, it happened. But was it justified?

I think there is another way to understand Thomas that is consistent with
establishment applied to the states but without incorporating the
Establishment Clause.  (I just read through his opinion in Newdow very
quickly; so I may be reading him wrong on this).  Thomas seems to be saying
that state disestablishment can be gotten through the free exercise clause,
which can be interpreted to mean that state power to curtail free exercise
is prima facie unjustified. This would mean that really egregious cases of
establishment--e.g., assessments that tax everyone to support a particular
church, indoctrinating students in public school classrooms, etc.--violate
free exercise. However, the Pledge of Allegience--from which kids can opt
out--violates no one's free exercise.

It does, of course, put the state in a position of claiming that the nation
is under God. But one could give a separationist account of this by
arguing that since the writer of the Danbury Letter (the sacred text of
separationism, so to speak), Jefferson, affirmed in the Declaration that our
rights, including religious liberty, are endowed to us by our Creator,
apparently he saw no inconsistency in maintaining both beliefs
simultaneously.  In this sense, we are under God.

Frank

On 6/17/04 3:48 PM, Steven Jamar [EMAIL PROTECTED] wrote:

 bedrock.  Still, is there a reason why we should not concede that he
 is -- or, at least, MAY be -- correct?
 
 Best,
 
 Rick Garnett
 
 The Civil War Amendments rewrote the Constitution.  People are entitled
 to protection against establishment period. Limiting the states is what
 happened with our second Constitution.  Broadening the federal power
 happened then and again with our third Constitution (New Deal-Warren
 Court).
 
 While an academic may be excused for pondering parallel universes in
 writing, a Supreme Court Justice who does so in writing (as opposed to
 raising a point for discussion with law clerks and other judges) is
 perhaps not at the lunatic fringe, but is at at the very least near it.
 
 What we may toss around as ideas on our listserve or in our classes or
 in person or even in serious scholarship is different from published
 opinions of the court.
 
 Steve

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


RE: Justice Thomas in Newdow

2004-06-17 Thread Volokh, Eugene
It seems to me that Justice Thomas's position -- or for that
matter, the Chief's similar position in Wallace v. Jaffree in the
mid-1980s -- is eminently credible.

The case for the Establishment Clause not being incorporated is
at least as strong, it seems to me, as the case for the Grand Jury
Presement Clause not being incorporated or the Seventh Amendment not
being incorporated.  It's true that there is indeed accumulated caselaw
to the contrary, and it surely counts as constitutional law.  But
calling for the reversal even of longstanding precedents also counts as
a legitimate constitutional argument -- in fact, that's how the process
of incorporation itself has often proceeded as to other Amendments.

Finally, I think Doug has a good point that the Establishment
Clause may well be seen as an important protection of individual
liberty.  But that strikes me as far from an open-and-shut obvious
point.  So on balance, Justice Thomas's position -- and the position of
scholars who have made similar arguments -- seems to me to be eminently
credible, and hardly deserving of the harsh condemnation that Rick
Garnett has quoted, even if one ultimately disagrees with Thomas
(whether on originalist grounds or because one thinks that something
else, such as precedent, should count more than original meaning).

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of marc stern
 Sent: Thursday, June 17, 2004 2:28 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Justice Thomas in Newdow
 
 
 Isn't it the case that whether Thomas is correct or not 
 depends in part on whether only the text of the constitution 
 (or the text and original intent) is a relevant datum or 
 whether accumulated cases law also counts as constitutional 
 law. On the text only vision of constitutional law, Thomas 
 has at least something to say, even if I think, with Doug, 
 that he is wrong; on the latter view, his opinion in the 
 pledge case is simply an anomaly. Marc Stern
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Douglas Laycock
 Sent: Thursday, June 17, 2004 4:21 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Justice Thomas in Newdow
 
  The LA Times story is available on Westlaw for those 
 who would 
 like to read it without giving their phone number and income 
 to the LA 
 Times.  Expletives deleted.
 
  Obviously the way you would explain what is wrong 
 with Thomas's 
 opinion on this list is different from how you would 
 capsulize it in a 
 sentence or two (selected by the reporter) for an 
 explanation to the 
 public.  But I do think that Thomas's opinion is both extreme 
 and wrong.
 
  He did not say merely that the clause does not apply 
 against the 
 states.  He also said that the clause creates no individual 
 rights.  The 
 only apparent application of this second pronouncement is 
 that it creates 
 no individual rights against the federal government either.  So every 
 Establishment Clause case the Court has ever decided would be 
 obliterated 
 at a stroke.  He seems to assume that the free exercise clause would 
 prevent coerced attendance at religious services -- unless, 
 we have to 
 assume, the service is rather short and is incorporated into 
 some other 
 official event that people attend for secular reasons.
 
  I do not doubt that one meaning of the Clause in 
 1791 was that the 
 federal government could not interfere with establishments in the 
 states.  But I am equally sure that one meaning of the Clause 
 in 1791 was 
 that the federal government could take no steps toward a federal 
 establishment of religion -- not in the states, and not in 
 the federal 
 district either.  Either a federal establishment or a federal 
 interference 
 with a state establishment would be a law respecting an establishment.
 
  The debate in the First Congress did not focus on 
 the federalism 
 implications.  It focused on the meaning of establishment, 
 and on how far 
 the federal government should be restricted.  The argument 
 for prohibiting 
 only preferential aid to favored denominations was rejected; the most 
 broadly worded draft proposed was adopted.  This of course 
 goes to the 
 debate over nonpreferentialism; but even before that, it goes 
 to whether 
 this Clause was only about federalism, or also about the proper 
 relationship between religion and government.  The debate was 
 plainly about 
 the latter; I think the federalism-only interpretation is 
 demonstrably wrong.
 
  I'm not sure the federalism principle that can be 
 derived from the 
 verb respecting and the existence of state establishments is much 
 different from the federalism principle that is implicit in the 
 constitutional structure about other individual rights good 
 only against 
 the federal government.  Certainly the federal 

RE: Justice Thomas in Newdow

2004-06-17 Thread Eastman, John
So its ok for the New Deal-Warren Court to re-write the Constitution to its 
pleasure, but somehow lunatic fringe for Justice Thomas even to ask the question 
what the Constitution as written and ratified actually meant?  Seems to me that the 
oath of office for him (and indeed every other officer in government) is to the 
Constitution, not what the Court said about it in dicta in 1947, particularly when the 
dictum was verifiably wrong.  Verifiable--else how can you explain the efforts to pass 
the Blaine Amendment, an effort that would not have been necessary had the 14th 
Amendment already accomplished what you think is so obvious that no discussion about 
it ever grace the pages of the U.S. Reports.
 
And I dont' see how state support of religion is any more an infringement on the 
liberty protected by the 14th Amendment than state indoctrination in public schools, 
or via the slanderous anti-tobacco ad campaigns that have run throughout the nation, 
etc. No one is compelled to adhere to a particular faith--that's the line between free 
exercise and establishment as originally understood.  The non-interference aspect of 
the First Amendment is a close call, but I think the stronger original understanding, 
and there is certainly nothing in the 14th Amendment's drafting or ratification 
history even to suggest, much less to dispositively determine, that the 14th Amendment 
was designed to confer on the Federal Courts the very power prohibited to Congress by 
the Establishment Clause itself.  The 14th Amendment wrought a monumental change in 
federal-state relations, to be sure, but that was not among them--at least, not on any 
evidence I have seen.
 
John Eastman
Chapman Law School



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Steven Jamar
Sent: Thu 6/17/2004 1:48 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: Re: Justice Thomas in Newdow



 bedrock.  Still, is there a reason why we should not concede that he
 is -- or, at least, MAY be -- correct?

 Best,

 Rick Garnett

The Civil War Amendments rewrote the Constitution.  People are entitled
to protection against establishment period. Limiting the states is what
happened with our second Constitution.  Broadening the federal power
happened then and again with our third Constitution (New Deal-Warren
Court).

While an academic may be excused for pondering parallel universes in
writing, a Supreme Court Justice who does so in writing (as opposed to
raising a point for discussion with law clerks and other judges) is
perhaps not at the lunatic fringe, but is at at the very least near it.

What we may toss around as ideas on our listserve or in our classes or
in person or even in serious scholarship is different from published
opinions of the court.

Steve

--
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8428
2900 Van Ness Street NW mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008  http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar

Lay not up for yourselves treasures upon earth, where moth and rust
doth corrupt, and where thieves break through and steal; but lay up for
yourselves treasures in heaven, where neither moth nor rust doth
corrupt, and where thieves do not break through nor steal. For where
your treasure is, there will your heart be also.

Matthew 6:19-21

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


winmail.dat___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


RE: Justice Thomas in Newdow

2004-06-17 Thread Scarberry, Mark
I was surprised by Justice Thomas's statements suggesting that it is not
entirely clear that the Establishment Clause prohibits Congress from
establishing a national religion. See his opinion at p. 6 (saying only that
the Est. Clause probably does so as a textual matter) and p. 7 (But even
assuming ...). Is this a slip of the pen, or does Justice Thomas really
entertain doubt whether the original meaning of the Establishment Clause
included such a prohibition?

Mark S. Scarberry
Pepperdine University School of Law
 

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, June 17, 2004 2:54 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: Justice Thomas in Newdow

It seems to me that Justice Thomas's position -- or for that
matter, the Chief's similar position in Wallace v. Jaffree in the
mid-1980s -- is eminently credible.

The case for the Establishment Clause not being incorporated is
at least as strong, it seems to me, as the case for the Grand Jury
Presement Clause not being incorporated or the Seventh Amendment not
being incorporated.  It's true that there is indeed accumulated caselaw
to the contrary, and it surely counts as constitutional law.  But
calling for the reversal even of longstanding precedents also counts as
a legitimate constitutional argument -- in fact, that's how the process
of incorporation itself has often proceeded as to other Amendments.

Finally, I think Doug has a good point that the Establishment
Clause may well be seen as an important protection of individual
liberty.  But that strikes me as far from an open-and-shut obvious
point.  So on balance, Justice Thomas's position -- and the position of
scholars who have made similar arguments -- seems to me to be eminently
credible, and hardly deserving of the harsh condemnation that Rick
Garnett has quoted, even if one ultimately disagrees with Thomas
(whether on originalist grounds or because one thinks that something
else, such as precedent, should count more than original meaning).

Eugene

 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of marc stern
 Sent: Thursday, June 17, 2004 2:28 PM
 To: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'
 Subject: RE: Justice Thomas in Newdow
 
 
 Isn't it the case that whether Thomas is correct or not 
 depends in part on whether only the text of the constitution 
 (or the text and original intent) is a relevant datum or 
 whether accumulated cases law also counts as constitutional 
 law. On the text only vision of constitutional law, Thomas 
 has at least something to say, even if I think, with Doug, 
 that he is wrong; on the latter view, his opinion in the 
 pledge case is simply an anomaly. Marc Stern
 
 -Original Message-
 From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of 
 Douglas Laycock
 Sent: Thursday, June 17, 2004 4:21 PM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: Re: Justice Thomas in Newdow
 
  The LA Times story is available on Westlaw for those 
 who would 
 like to read it without giving their phone number and income 
 to the LA 
 Times.  Expletives deleted.
 
  Obviously the way you would explain what is wrong 
 with Thomas's 
 opinion on this list is different from how you would 
 capsulize it in a 
 sentence or two (selected by the reporter) for an 
 explanation to the 
 public.  But I do think that Thomas's opinion is both extreme 
 and wrong.
 
  He did not say merely that the clause does not apply 
 against the 
 states.  He also said that the clause creates no individual 
 rights.  The 
 only apparent application of this second pronouncement is 
 that it creates 
 no individual rights against the federal government either.  So every 
 Establishment Clause case the Court has ever decided would be 
 obliterated 
 at a stroke.  He seems to assume that the free exercise clause would 
 prevent coerced attendance at religious services -- unless, 
 we have to 
 assume, the service is rather short and is incorporated into 
 some other 
 official event that people attend for secular reasons.
 
  I do not doubt that one meaning of the Clause in 
 1791 was that the 
 federal government could not interfere with establishments in the 
 states.  But I am equally sure that one meaning of the Clause 
 in 1791 was 
 that the federal government could take no steps toward a federal 
 establishment of religion -- not in the states, and not in 
 the federal 
 district either.  Either a federal establishment or a federal 
 interference 
 with a state establishment would be a law respecting an establishment.
 
  The debate in the First Congress did not focus on 
 the federalism 
 implications.  It focused on the meaning of establishment, 
 and on how far 
 the federal government should be restricted.  The argument 
 for prohibiting 
 only preferential aid to favored denominations was rejected; the most 
 

Re: RE: Justice Thomas in Newdow

2004-06-17 Thread Kurt Lash
Doug Laycock is right to suggest that the federalism case for the 
establishment clause is at least as strong in regard to other rights 
listed in the Bill.  For example, when Congress passed the alien and 
sedition acts, Madison argued that the acts, among other things, 
violated the rights of the states.  His point was a simple one of 
linking the first and tenth amendments--the powers not delegated to 
the federal government  (like the power to regulate speech) nor 
prohibited to the states, are reserved to the states respectively or 
to the people.  And, in fact, he cited the Tenth Amendment in his 
Report on the Acts.

But the Establishment Clause nevertheless remains unique even among 
the rest of the Bill of Rights.  When Madison (unsuccessfully) 
proposed an amendment that would apply important first amendment 
rights against the states, he included a version of the free exercise 
clause, but he left out the establishment clause.  Apparently Madison 
believed there was a difference between the two clauses and he sought 
to apply only one--the free exercise clause--against the states.

Whatever Madison's reasons for doing so, I believe that most scholars 
would agree that, in 1791, there was deep disagreement about the value 
of state religious establishments.  It is quite likely that many 
founders simultaneously believed that federal establishments were bad 
but state establishments were very important.  I don't think any 
historian working on this period would disagree.

But unlike John, I believe that a broad majority of the country came 
to embrace the principle of non-establishment in the period between 
1791 and 1868.  I agree with Doug that, by Reconstruction, privileges 
or immunities of US citizens were understood to include the right to 
non-establishment.  John raises the issue of the Blaine amendment, and 
he and I have discussed that Amendment in other forums.  Suffice to 
say that I think the Blaine Amendment is evidence which SUPPORTS the 
idea the P or I's included the principle of non-establishment.

But my and John's disagreement is wholly irrelevant to the Supreme 
Court.  The Court has steadfastly refused to consider 
Reconstruction understandings in its interpretation of the Bill of 
Rights in general and the religion clauses in particular.  Instead, 
there has been a continuous, and hopeless, debate over the original 
meaning of the establishment clause.  One can hardly fault Justice 
Thomas for joining the debate on the Court's own terms.  

Unfortunately, as Steve Smith might say, this debate is doomed to 
failure, for it seeks an answer that the people themselves were not 
prepared to give in 1791.

Kurt Lash
Loyola Law School, Los Angeles


___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw