Religious exemptions for the non-religious

2007-03-01 Thread Perry Dane


Doug
Laycock writes that the willingness to treat atheism as a religion
is very encouraging.
I agree
that, for certain purposes, including rights of _expression_, religious
views and anti-religious views need to be treated equally.

On the
other hand, it has always seemed to me that to extend the idea of
religion-based exemptions beyond the realm of specifically religious
norms conflicting with secular law would, in effect, create a universal
libertarian presumption that no law can be applied against a dissenting
individual unless that law is supported by a compelling governmental
interest. And that sort of universal libertarian presumption just
strikes me as implausible and inconsistent with our constitutional and
legal structure.
Doug is
right that some opponents of religion-based exemptions make something
like the following argument:
 1. We can't exempt only believers, because that would
discriminate against nonbelievers.
 2. But we can't exempt nonbelievers, because nonbelief is
not a religion.
 3. Therefore, we can't exempt anybody.

But I
think that we should be equally concerned about the following
argument:
 1. We can't exempt non-believers, because that would create
a universal libertarian presumption in the law, which is
implausible.
 2. But we can't exempt only believers, because that would
discriminate against nonbelievers.
 3. Therefore, we can't exempt anybody.

In both
cases, the flaw in the reasoning (which Doug agrees is a flaw) is the
notion that we can't exempt only believers. Of course
we can exempt only believers, and there are good, normatively compelling,
reasons to do so.




Perry


***
Perry Dane



Professor of Law
Rutgers University 
School of Law --
Camden

[EMAIL PROTECTED]

www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/

www.ssrn.com/author=48596
***



___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions for the non-religious

2007-03-01 Thread Brownstein, Alan
I think Perry is correct that there are good, normatively compelling
reasons for exempting only believers - but I wouldn't say of course
this is so. I often respond to the argument that there is no reason to
treat religion differently than secular beliefs for the purpose of
creating conscience based exemptions by asking whether there is a reason
for distinguishing between religious and secular beliefs for
Establishment Clause purposes --- and whether we should look at the
religion clauses holistically with regard to the distinctions they draw
between religion and secular beliefs.

 

But Doug's comment that it is encouraging for courts to treat atheism as
a religion should not be so easily dismissed. First, when Perry notes
that for certain purposes including rights of expression, religious and
anti-religious views need to be treated equally, that may be a very
large category. The exercise of religion often has a religious dimension
to it - and the Court has consistently declined the opportunities
presented to it to develop a working demarcation line between religious
exercise and speech.

 

Second, we have no working definition of religion for constitutional
purposes that will help us to distinguish conscientiously held moral and
ethical beliefs from conscientiously held religious beliefs. If a person
seeking an exemption contends that the ethical commitments he adheres to
are religious in nature - even though the person does not believe in G-d
-- because these moral precepts are inherent in nature or history or
whatever else the person uses as a foundation for his morality, does he
receive an exemption? 

 

Also, and this is probably only a semantic point, one of my problems
with talking about the judicial recognition of atheism as a religion
is that the only core belief of an atheist that he or she shares with
other atheists is that they do not believe in G-d. I am not sure that
there are all that many situations where a person's commitment to that
belief alone conflicts with law and requires special accommodation. The
harder question for me is evaluating the moral basis for the
conscientious decisions of atheists. I would probably call those beliefs
a non theistic moral code or philosophy - but I'm not sure the choice of
terminology makes much of a substantive difference. The argument would
be that denying the existence of G-d is a religious belief - but the
adherence to a non-theistic code of conduct is not religious.

 

Alan Brownstein

 

 

 



From: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Perry Dane
Sent: Thursday, March 01, 2007 9:05 AM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: Religious exemptions for the non-religious

 

Doug Laycock writes that the willingness to treat atheism as a
religion is very encouraging.

I agree that, for certain purposes, including rights of
expression, religious views and anti-religious views need to be treated
equally.  

On the other hand, it has always seemed to me that to extend the
idea of religion-based exemptions beyond the realm of specifically
religious norms conflicting with secular law would, in effect, create a
universal libertarian presumption that no law can be applied against a
dissenting individual unless that law is supported by a compelling
governmental interest.  And that sort of universal libertarian
presumption just strikes me as implausible and inconsistent with our
constitutional and legal structure.

Doug is right that some opponents of religion-based exemptions
make something like the following argument:

  1.  We can't exempt only believers, because that would discriminate
against nonbelievers.

  2.  But we can't exempt nonbelievers, because nonbelief is not a
religion.

  3.  Therefore, we can't exempt anybody.


But I think that we should be equally concerned about the
following argument:

  1.  We can't exempt non-believers, because that would create a
universal libertarian presumption in the law, which is implausible.

  2.  But we can't exempt only believers, because that would
discriminate against nonbelievers.

  3.  Therefore, we can't exempt anybody.


In both cases, the flaw in the reasoning (which Doug agrees is a
flaw) is the notion that we can't exempt only believers.  Of course we
can exempt only believers, and there are good, normatively compelling,
reasons to do so.

Perry





***
Perry Dane
Professor of Law

Rutgers University 
School of Law  -- Camden 

[EMAIL PROTECTED]
www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/
www.ssrn.com/author=48596
***

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 

Re: Religious exemptions for the non-religious

2007-03-01 Thread David E. Guinn
I must admit having some sympathy for Perry's position.

In my book FAITH ON TRIAL, I advanced the following argument supporting an 
expansive protection of religious exceptions that would justify attention to 
traditional religions:

1 Law regulates behavior based upon social utilitarian grounds (e.g taking 
drugs is bad for you and society.)

2  We reject pure claims of conscience as being anarchic (Scalia's each man a 
law unto himself)

3.  Behavior that is compelled by a religious community not only reflects 
religious values, it includes a demonstrated social utility -- that is, the 
behavior is not only endorsed by a group (ergo not an idiosyncratic assessment 
of merit) it must have also contributed to the ongoing viability of that group 
(such as the fact that use of peyote by the NA Church in Smith contributed to a 
community in which there was far less drug abuse than prevalent in the general 
native American population.)

4.  Therefore, the courts can and should incorporate an appreciation of this 
social endorsement under the First Amendment in considering objections.

While I continue to believe in the merits of this argument, I cannot point to 
any court that has agreed with me (outside of the YODER outlier that predated 
by work.)

David E. Guinn JD, PhD
 
Recent Publications Available from SSRN at 
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=199608





  - Original Message - 
  From: Perry Dane 
  To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu 
  Sent: Thursday, March 01, 2007 11:05 AM
  Subject: Religious exemptions for the non-religious


  Doug Laycock writes that the willingness to treat atheism as a 
religion is very encouraging.

  I agree that, for certain purposes, including rights of expression, 
religious views and anti-religious views need to be treated equally.  

  On the other hand, it has always seemed to me that to extend the idea 
of religion-based exemptions beyond the realm of specifically religious norms 
conflicting with secular law would, in effect, create a universal libertarian 
presumption that no law can be applied against a dissenting individual unless 
that law is supported by a compelling governmental interest.  And that sort of 
universal libertarian presumption just strikes me as implausible and 
inconsistent with our constitutional and legal structure.

  Doug is right that some opponents of religion-based exemptions make 
something like the following argument:

1.  We can't exempt only believers, because that would discriminate against 
nonbelievers.

2.  But we can't exempt nonbelievers, because nonbelief is not a religion.

3.  Therefore, we can't exempt anybody.


  But I think that we should be equally concerned about the following 
argument:

1.  We can't exempt non-believers, because that would create a universal 
libertarian presumption in the law, which is implausible.

2.  But we can't exempt only believers, because that would discriminate 
against nonbelievers.

3.  Therefore, we can't exempt anybody.


  In both cases, the flaw in the reasoning (which Doug agrees is a 
flaw) is the notion that we can't exempt only believers.  Of course we can 
exempt only believers, and there are good, normatively compelling, reasons to 
do so.

  Perry



  ***
  Perry Dane
  Professor of Law

  Rutgers University 
  School of Law  -- Camden 

  [EMAIL PROTECTED]
  www.camlaw.rutgers.edu/bio/925/
  www.ssrn.com/author=48596
  ***





--


  ___
  To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
  To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

  Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as 
private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; 
people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) 
forward the messages to others.___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions for the non-religious

2007-03-01 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
Atheism and agnosticism should be considered religions for free exercise
purposes because, as Doug has argued in print, we would regard them as
religions for establishment purpose -- if the government set up a Temple of
Atheism or schools taught officially that God does not exist.  If one takes
the constitutional text seriously, its use of religion only once for both
clauses demands this kind of symmetry -- and I think that in this case
textualism  performs a useful service in disciplining interpretation.

 

I agree with Alan that often it will be hard to tie the atheist or
agnostic's moral code to his or her non-belief in God.  But not always.  For
example, I think that Seeger, Welsh, and others like them could quite
plausibly ground their refusal to kill in their explicit non-belief or
profound doubt about God and the afterlife.  Believing that this life is all
there is can easily generate the belief that it is the highest value and
thus an absolute refusal to kill.  But conversely, this kind of argument
doesn't extend to all deeply held moral beliefs that might conflict with
law. 

 

Following up on another of Alan's points: The broader claim that deeply held
moral positions in general (not just non-theist religious positions like
atheism or agnosticism) must be treated the same as religion has several
problems.  One is that proponents of this claim typically do not carry it
through on the establishment side, where they advocate special limits on
government promotion of religion that do not apply to promotion of
non-religious moral positions.  Chris Eisgruber and Larry Sager's new book
is an example.  They reiterate their influential case against treating
freedom of religious exercise more favorably than freedom for deeply held
non-religious moral positions.  But then they defend the distinctive
establishment clause limits on government religious symbolism by arguing
that for government to endorse a religious view or views is especially
damaging to others because religious affiliation typically implicates an
expansive web of belief and conduct, individuals often feel and are seen
as either 'in' or 'out' of such webs, and the perceived and actual stakes
of being [in or out] can be very high, including being fulfilled and
redeemed or eternally damned.  It seems plain to me that every single one
of these rationales also supports special concern for freedom of religious
exercise and thus undercuts their position on the free exercise side.  .

 

Tom Berg, University of St. Thomas (Minnesota)

 

 

+++

 

I think Perry is correct that there are good, normatively compelling reasons
for exempting only believers - but I wouldn't say of course this is so. I
often respond to the argument that there is no reason to treat religion
differently than secular beliefs for the purpose of creating conscience
based exemptions by asking whether there is a reason for distinguishing
between religious and secular beliefs for Establishment Clause purposes ---
and whether we should look at the religion clauses holistically with regard
to the distinctions they draw between religion and secular beliefs.

 

But Doug's comment that it is encouraging for courts to treat atheism as a
religion should not be so easily dismissed. First, when Perry notes that for
certain purposes including rights of expression, religious and
anti-religious views need to be treated equally, that may be a very large
category. The exercise of religion often has a religious dimension to it -
and the Court has consistently declined the opportunities presented to it to
develop a working demarcation line between religious exercise and speech.

 

Second, we have no working definition of religion for constitutional
purposes that will help us to distinguish conscientiously held moral and
ethical beliefs from conscientiously held religious beliefs. If a person
seeking an exemption contends that the ethical commitments he adheres to are
religious in nature - even though the person does not believe in G-d --
because these moral precepts are inherent in nature or history or whatever
else the person uses as a foundation for his morality, does he receive an
exemption? 

 

Also, and this is probably only a semantic point, one of my problems with
talking about the judicial recognition of atheism as a religion is that
the only core belief of an atheist that he or she shares with other atheists
is that they do not believe in G-d. I am not sure that there are all that
many situations where a person's commitment to that belief alone conflicts
with law and requires special accommodation. The harder question for me is
evaluating the moral basis for the conscientious decisions of atheists. I
would probably call those beliefs a non theistic moral code or philosophy -
but I'm not sure the choice of terminology makes much of a substantive
difference. The argument would be that denying the existence of G-d is a
religious belief - but the adherence to a 

Re: Religious exemptions for the non-religious

2007-03-01 Thread RJLipkin
 
 
In a message dated 3/1/2007 4:06:41 P.M. Eastern Standard Time,  
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

Atheism  and agnosticism should be considered religions for free exercise 
purposes  because, as Doug has argued in print, we would regard them as 
religions 
for  establishment purpose 


It might be the right  approach to consider atheism a religion for FE and 
EC purposes, just as  long as we make it clear that, in fact, atheism is no 
more a religion than  the denial of physics is physics. Constitutional 
necessities might require  distorting ontology for important reasons, but it 
does not 
change ontology by  doing so.
 
Bobby

Robert Justin Lipkin
Professor of Law
Widener University School of  Law
Delaware


Ratio Juris,  Contributor: _  http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/_ 
(http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/) 
Essentially Contested  America, Editor: 
_http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/_ 
(http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/) 
BRBRBR**BR AOL now offers free 
email to everyone.  Find out more about what's free from AOL at 
http://www.aol.com.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Re: Religious exemptions for the non-religious

2007-03-01 Thread RJLipkin
Sure, one denies certain  propositions in physics, but as with any 
science--for that matter any field of  study--conceptual, paradigmatic 
propositions when 
denied eviscerate that field  either to replace it with another paradigm and 
field or to let it drift asunder  as in the case of alchemy.
 
Suppose an Alien comes to  Earth and tells us that his/her/its/? 
founding story is that the universe came  into being spontaneously. The 
founding 
story ends there with regard to ethics,  personal salvation, the meaning of 
life, and all those things sometimes  associated with earthly religions. The 
Alien doesn't view his founding story as  a negative answer to the religious 
questions we ask.  It never occurred to  Alien civilization to ask these 
religious questions.  Impoverished  civilization, some might say. Others 
might argue 
it beats ours.
 
I'm not sure why negative  answers must qualify as answers at 
all.  Indeed, it seems  question-begging to insist that they must. Common 
usage? 
Maybe some people use  religion this way, but others do not. 
 
If you mean that any deeply  felt perspective answering certain kinds 
of question is a religion, then   what happens to the secular? Indeed, as I 
have argued before I don't believe the  religion-secular dichotomy captures the 
view that some perspectives occupy a  fundamental place in human imagination 
and some don't. I would replace this  dichotomy with the 
dedicated-deliberative dichotomy. Some  belief-systems--whether religious or 
secular--are virtually 
closed, answering  all (or most) questions we ask about society and its 
origins. Marx's materialism  seems a good candidate for this type of dedicated 
perspective as does orthodox  Judaism--I would argue--and, of course, 
fundamentalism generally. By  contrast, certain kinds of pragmatism require 
deliberative 
debate as do certain  Protestant religions that friends have described to me. 
But perhaps we're  getting to far from the List's raisin d'etre.
 
Bobby

Robert Justin Lipkin.
Professor of Law
Widener  University School of Law
Delaware

Ratio Juris
, Contributor: _  http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/_ 
(http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/) 
Essentially Contested  America, Editor: 
_http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/_ 
(http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/) 
BRBRBR**BR AOL now offers free 
email to everyone.  Find out more about what's free from AOL at 
http://www.aol.com.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions for the non-religious

2007-03-01 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
I'm not sure what the denial of physics means.  Doesn't one deny (or
affirm) a particular proposition or set of propositions about physics?
Similarly, it seems to me that there is a recognizable usage of religion
that includes varying positions on the ultimate questions such as the
existence of a deity (deities) or the afterlife -- including the negative
answers -- although there's also a commonly used sense in which religion
includes only the positive answers of various sorts.  So I guess I'd say
that the first usage, in addition to being a better fit for the logic of the
two religion provisions, is also more than just a usage made up for that
purpose.  I agree that one is far less likely to exercise the
negative-answer beliefs, but as I said in the previous post I think there
are instances in which they too are exercised.
 
Tom Berg
 
__
 
 
 
In a message dated 3/1/2007 4:06:41 P.M. Eastern Standard Time,
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

Atheism and agnosticism should be considered religions for free exercise
purposes because, as Doug has argued in print, we would regard them as
religions for establishment purpose 

It might be the right approach to consider atheism a religion for
FE and EC purposes, just as long as we make it clear that, in fact, atheism
is no more a religion than the denial of physics is physics. Constitutional
necessities might require distorting ontology for important reasons, but it
does not change ontology by doing so.
 
Bobby

Robert Justin Lipkin
Professor of Law
Widener University School of Law
Delaware

Ratio Juris, Contributor:   http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/
http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/
Essentially Contested America, Editor:
http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/
http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/ 



  _  

AOL now offers free email to everyone. Find out more about what's free from
AOL at
http://pr.atwola.com/promoclk/1615326657x4311227241x4298082137/aol?redir=ht
tp%3A%2F%2Fwww%2Eaol%2Ecom AOL.com. 
application/ms-tnef___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

RE: Religious exemptions for the non-religious

2007-03-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
I am sitting out this discussion because I have an oral argument 
tomorrow (on a remedies case of no interest to this list).  I don't 
think that plausible claims to exemption by nonbelievers arise very 
often, and objections to killing may comprise all or most of the list.  
But neither do I think that one forfeits protection for his most deeply 
held moral commitments when he crosses a certain line in the evolution 
of theological views.  And I think that one role of the Religion 
Clauses is to mediate religious conflict in the society, and that today 
they must mediate the religious-secular conflict just as in the past 
they mediated the Protestant-Catholic conflict and the Anglican-Baptist 
conflict.  It is very hard for the Clauses to perform that function if 
one side of the conflict is outside the Clauses.


Back to silence.

Quoting Berg, Thomas C. [EMAIL PROTECTED]:


I'm not sure what the denial of physics means.  Doesn't one deny (or
affirm) a particular proposition or set of propositions about physics?
Similarly, it seems to me that there is a recognizable usage of religion
that includes varying positions on the ultimate questions such as the
existence of a deity (deities) or the afterlife -- including the negative
answers -- although there's also a commonly used sense in which religion
includes only the positive answers of various sorts.  So I guess I'd say
that the first usage, in addition to being a better fit for the logic of the
two religion provisions, is also more than just a usage made up for that
purpose.  I agree that one is far less likely to exercise the
negative-answer beliefs, but as I said in the previous post I think there
are instances in which they too are exercised.

Tom Berg

__



In a message dated 3/1/2007 4:06:41 P.M. Eastern Standard Time,
[EMAIL PROTECTED] writes:

Atheism and agnosticism should be considered religions for free exercise
purposes because, as Doug has argued in print, we would regard them as
religions for establishment purpose

   It might be the right approach to consider atheism a religion for
FE and EC purposes, just as long as we make it clear that, in fact, atheism
is no more a religion than the denial of physics is physics. Constitutional
necessities might require distorting ontology for important reasons, but it
does not change ontology by doing so.

Bobby

Robert Justin Lipkin
Professor of Law
Widener University School of Law
Delaware

Ratio Juris, Contributor:   http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/
http://ratiojuris.blogspot.com/
Essentially Contested America, Editor:
http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/
http://www.essentiallycontestedamerica.org/



 _

AOL now offers free email to everyone. Find out more about what's free from
AOL at
http://pr.atwola.com/promoclk/1615326657x4311227241x4298082137/aol?redir=ht
tp%3A%2F%2Fwww%2Eaol%2Ecom AOL.com.





Douglas Laycock
Yale Kamisar Collegiate Professor of Law
University of Michigan Law School
625 S. State St.
Ann Arbor, MI  48109-1215
 734-647-9713

___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.


RE: Religious exemptions for the non-religious

2007-03-01 Thread Volokh, Eugene
Doug Laycock writes:
 
 I am sitting out this discussion because I have an oral 
 argument tomorrow (on a remedies case of no interest to this 
 list).  I don't think that plausible claims to exemption by 
 nonbelievers arise very often, and objections to killing may 
 comprise all or most of the list.  

I'm wondering why this would be so.  I take it that
conscientious vegetarians may raise objections much like those of people
with religious dietary preferences, no?  (Perhaps that is an indirect
objection to killing, but quite indirect.)  Likewise, secular as well as
religious people may have conscientious objections to sitting in
judgment on others, conscientious objections to testifying against
family members, and so on, no?

 But neither do I think that one forfeits protection for his 
 most deeply held moral commitments when he crosses a certain 
 line in the evolution of theological views.  And I think that 
 one role of the Religion Clauses is to mediate religious 
 conflict in the society, and that today they must mediate the 
 religious-secular conflict just as in the past they mediated 
 the Protestant-Catholic conflict and the Anglican-Baptist 
 conflict.  It is very hard for the Clauses to perform that 
 function if one side of the conflict is outside the Clauses.
 
 Back to silence.
___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.