RE: Locke v. Davey Analysis

2006-10-02 Thread Conkle, Daniel O.








To the extent that the decision in Locke is
a product of general themes in Rehnquists constitutional jurisprudence,
I think the theme of states rightsmentioned earlier by Rick
Tepkershould not be overlooked. Rehnquist wrote a series of important
Establishment Clause opinions upholding indirect funding programs that included
religious beneficiaries (Mueller, Zobrest, Zelman), citing the importance of neutrality
and private choice. And yet he rejected the Free Exercise argument in Locke
even though the program at issue there was not neutral and did not honor the private
choice of those wishing to pursue religious careers. In each context,
however, Rehnquist was according discretion to the states by interpreting the First
Amendment narrowly. I analyze Rehnquists role in the indirect
funding cases--both the Establishment Clauses cases and Locke--in a book
chapter in The Rehnquist Legacy (Craig Bradley ed., Cambridge 2006). 

Daniel O. Conkle 
*** 
Daniel O. Conkle 
Robert H. McKinney Professor of Law 
Indiana University School of Law 
Bloomington, Indiana 47405 
(812) 855-4331 
fax (812) 855-0555 
e-mail [EMAIL PROTECTED] 
*** 





-Original Message-
From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED] [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of Douglas Laycock
Sent: Sunday, October
 01, 2006 2:29 PM
To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
Subject: RE: Locke v. Davey
Analysis



Locke v. Davey does not
announce a requirement of anti-religious motive, as I show in a
sentence-by-sentence parsing of the opinion in the Harvard Law Review in
2004. It is primarily a burden opinion: refusal to fund does not
impose a significant burden, which was indeed a longstanding Rehnquist
theme. There is also talk about the importance and narrowness of the
state's interest in not funding clergy -- at one point he says the
only interest at issue here is the interest in not funding the
training of clergy -- and other talk that would seem to make the state's
interests irrelevant and universalize the rule that refusal to fund is not a
burden.

Sherbert is distinguished as a
burden opinion, not as a motive opinion. It is true that judges deciding
or defending Employment Division v. Smith
have characterized Sherbert
as a discrimination case. But that is not at all the same as finding bad
motive behind that discrimination. Locke
v. Davey itself was clearly a discrimination case, and yet the
Court found no bad motive. Rehnquistalso distinguishes the case
striking down rules barring clergy from the legislature (Pate?), which were enacted in 1796; no
one has claimed that that was a motive case. Rehnquist takes up the
question of motive only in response to Scalia's dissent, and only after
distinguishing cases of burdensome regulation and of regulation that
intereferes with political rights.

Quoting Gary McCaleb [EMAIL PROTECTED]:

 I will weigh in but briefly--I'm spending my Saturday dealing with the
 Ninth Circuit's wayward First Amendment analyses on another case--but
 note this as background to Davey. I litigated the case at district
 court and on some of the appeal work before I left ACLJ.

 The scholarships were awarded based on satisfying three criteria: a
 defined level of academic success; a defined level of financial need
 based on family income; and intent to attend a qualifying Washington
 university (including private, pervasively sectarian universities).
 Davey could have taken exactly the same courses he would take as a
 theology major simply by selecting a major that would not have
made
 the nature of his coursework evident, but to put it simply, Mr. Davey
 wasn't that kind of guy. It was a classic situation
religion-neutral,
 need/performance driven scholarship system that was driven by a purpose
 statement of preparing Washington students for a productive future.
How
 the state's interest in non-appropriation of state funds for theology
 training plays into that, I don't know. Its hyper-separation on
 steroids.

 As to Rehnquist's apparent need to discern animus to justify a
free
 exercise claim, that seems to be far outside the four corners of the
 simple text of the free speech clause and leaves the government with
 rather broad authority to chill religious _expression_ based on little
 more than notional interests. Certainly, I think animus in Davey
could
 be properly inferred from the program's purpose statement, as the state
 was making a value judgement that being a pastor would not be a
 productive role for a Washington citizen.

 Anyway, this is off the top of my head--gotta get back to briefing.
 Sour grapes here? Well...sure. I could barely recognize the
case when
 I read the opinion.my sense is the Court picked the wrong vehicle to
 draw a line, and ran over both the Constitutiona and a sterling young
 man in the process.

 /S/ Gary S. McCaleb
 



   Gary S. McCaleb
   Senior Counsel
   (480) 444-0020 ext. 8046
   (480

RE: Locke v. Davey Analysis

2006-10-01 Thread Douglas Laycock
Locke v. Davey does not announce a requirement of anti-religious
motive, as I show in a sentence-by-sentence parsing of the opinion in the
Harvard Law Review in 2004.  It is primarily a burden opinion:  refusal to fund
does not impose a significant burden, which was indeed a longstanding Rehnquist
theme.  There is also talk about the importance and narrowness of the state's
interest in not funding clergy -- at one point he says the only
interest at issue here is the interest in not funding the training of clergy --
and other talk that would seem to make the state's interests irrelevant and
universalize the rule that refusal to fund is not a
burden.Sherbert is distinguished as a burden opinion, not as a
motive opinion.  It is true that judges deciding or defending Employment
Division v. Smith have characterized Sherbert as a discrimination
case.  But that is not at all the same as finding bad motive behind that
discrimination.  Locke v. Davey itself was clearly a discrimination
case, and yet the Court found no bad motive.  Rehnquist also distinguishes the
case striking down rules barring clergy from the legislature (Pate?),
which were enacted in 1796; no one has claimed that that was a motive case. 
Rehnquist takes up the question of motive only in response to Scalia's dissent,
and only after distinguishing cases of burdensome regulation and of regulation
that intereferes with political rights.Quoting Gary McCaleb
[EMAIL PROTECTED]: I will weigh in but briefly--I'm
spending my Saturday dealing with the Ninth Circuit's wayward First
Amendment analyses on another case--but note this as background to
Davey.  I litigated the case at district court and on some of the
appeal work before I left ACLJ. The scholarships were
awarded based on satisfying three criteria:  a defined level of
academic success; a defined level of financial need based on family
income; and intent to attend a qualifying Washington university
(including private, pervasively sectarian universities). Davey could
have taken exactly the same courses he would take as a theology
major simply by selecting a major that would not have made the
nature of his coursework evident, but to put it simply, Mr. Davey
wasn't that kind of guy.  It was a classic situation religion-neutral, need/performance driven scholarship system that was driven by a
purpose statement of preparing Washington students for a productive
future.  How the state's interest in non-appropriation of state funds
for theology training plays into that, I don't know.  Its
hyper-separation on steroids. As to Rehnquist's
apparent need to discern animus to justify a free
exercise claim, that seems to be far outside the four corners of the
simple text of the free speech clause and leaves the government with
rather broad authority to chill religious _expression_ based on little
more than notional interests.  Certainly, I think animus in Davey could be properly inferred from the program's purpose statement, as the
state was making a value judgement that being a pastor would not be
a productive role for a Washington citizen.
Anyway, this is off the top of my head--gotta get back to briefing.
Sour grapes here?  Well...sure.  I could barely recognize the case when I read the opinion.my sense is the Court picked the wrong vehicle
to draw a line, and ran over both the Constitutiona and a sterling
young man in the process. /S/  Gary S. McCaleb  
    Gary S. McCaleb      Senior Counsel      (480) 444-0020
ext. 8046      (480) 444-0028 fax      [EMAIL PROTECTED]
mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
 CONFIDENTIALITY
NOTICE This electronic mail message and any accompanying documents
contain information belonging to the sender which is confidential and
legally privileged. This information is intended only for the use of
the individual or entity to whom it was sent as indicated above. If
you are not the intended recipient, any disclosure, copying,
distribution, or action taken in reliance on the contents of the
information contained in this electronic mail message is strictly
prohibited. If you have received this message in error, please delete
it immediately, and call (480-444-0020) to advise me that you received
it. Thank you. PRIVILEGED AND CONFIDENTIAL - ATTORNEY CLIENT
COMMUNICATION/ATTORNEY WORK PRODUCT          From:
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] On Behalf Of
[EMAIL PROTECTED]         Sent: Saturday, September 30, 2006 8:10
AM         To: religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu         Subject:
Re: Locke v. Davey Analysis         I
think this is not a persuasive reading of either the opinion or any
opinion onto which the author, Rehnquist, would have signed on.
Rehnquist always looked for the dispositive element in a case, and was rarely interested in multifactorial tests, or the kind of intuitive weighing they require.   If you trace Rehnquist's free exercise
opinions whether maj or diss, he had a consistent

RE: Locke v. Davey Analysis

2006-09-29 Thread Tepker, Rick



Locke is a mystery to me. It seems to be a triumph of Chief Justice Rehnquist's quest for a wide deference in the name of states' rights. 

On the other hand,WHR's analysis of discrimination is impossible to support. He seems to say that discrimination (a plain and open disparate treatment) is okay as long as it doesn't involve criminal consequences, substantial civil or other legal "penalties." Because onlybenefits are at stake, the disparate treatment isn't constitutionally significant. This seems athrowback to the old discredited "rights-privileges" distinction.

For the most part, I agree with Justice Scalia's analysis, although I think his hypothetical about Western Europe and France is a stretch at best. But Chief Justice Rehnquist's rationale leads to another hypo that is, I think, more telling. WHR cites US v American Library Association in favor of a broad managerial discretion of public libraries, extending to a variety of choices about what goes into libraries and what does not (thanks to internet filters). The comparison is way off point. Suppose the managers of a public library said no theology students may use the library, or the stacks, or the computers, or the copying machines? WHR's analysis seems to lead to the conclusion that there's no discrimination because there's no "penalty." Scalia's analysis seems far more persuasive -- and far more consistent with the bulk of civil rights / civil liberties precedent: any adverse treatment that leaves an individual worse off than the "baseline" defined by statute or other legal authority is discrimination, and if it is based on a prohibited ground (race, sex, religion etc.), it is constitutionally or legally problematic.


From: [EMAIL PROTECTED] on behalf of Greg BaylorSent: Fri 9/29/2006 1:54 PMTo: 'Law  Religion issues for Law Academics'Subject: Locke v. Davey Analysis

I am curious as to how those on this list wouldcharacterize the analysis used by the majority inLocke v. Davey.

The Court obviously rejected the notion that non-neutral laws essentially always violate the Free Exercise Clause, (presumably) without regard to the magnitude of the burden imposed on the claimant's religious exercise.

At the same the Court did not apply a straightforward substantial burden/compelling state interest/least restrictive means analysis. As I read the majority opinion, after acknowledging the non-neutrality of the law in question, the Court looked at the magnitude of the burden not in isolation, but rather in the context of other factors, including the character of the law that caused the burden on Davey and the importance of the state's interest. 

[When I say "the character of the law that caused the burden on Davey," I am referring to the Court's observations about the otherwise religion-friendly character of Washington's education aid law (e.g., Davey could have kept his scholarship and majored in something other than devotional theology at the seriously religious Northwest College).]

In other words, the Court seemed to be applying a multifactorial approach, under which a claimant's weakness on one factor (e.g., burden) theoretically might be rehabilitated by his or her strength on others (e.g., the magnitude of the state's interest).

Do you agree or disagree? Thanks.

Greg Baylor

Gregory S. BaylorDirector, Center for Law  Religious FreedomChristian Legal Society8001 Braddock Road, Suite 300Springfield, VA 22151(703) 642-1070 x 3502(703) 642-1075 fax[EMAIL PROTECTED]http://www.clsnet.org ___
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.