RE: The quid pro quo theory

2004-06-16 Thread Newsom Michael
I apologize for responding to this post at this late date.  However, I
want to refer everybody to Lupu's piece (the name of which escapes me)
in which he establishes a grid analysis of the two clauses.

If I understand him aright, it goes something like this:

(1) Strong EC, Strong FE
(2) Strong EC, Weak FE
(3) Weak EC, Strong FE
(4) Weak EC, Strong FE.

Those interested in protecting minority rights might find themselves in
group (1).

Those interested in protecting the prerogatives of the majority might
find themselves in group (4).

Those interested in promoting religious values, and the role of religion
in public life might find themselves in group (3).

Those interested in keeping religion at bay or in check might find
themselves in group (2).

These four pairings capture rather nicely the dynamic and the dilemma of
the Religion Clauses.  Add a dash of Protestant Empire (or any other
large historical construct if this one doesn't work), a pinch of race
(particularly as it intersects with religion), and we are off and
running. 

-Original Message-
From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Thursday, June 10, 2004 12:30 AM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: The quid pro quo theory

I've always been puzzled about this quid pro quo theory of the
Religion Clauses.  There is no religion as a source of values and
beliefs; there are *religions* (or denominations) as a source of values
and beliefs.  Many of them may share many values, but they will also
differ on many values and goals.  The members of the religions will be
different, too.  True, there are some cultural battles in which
secularists are aligned on one side and religious observers of many
faiths on another.  But those are only a small fraction of all potential
battles over values and beliefs, it seems to me; and even in those, a
person's religious denomination is likely to be as important as his felt
religiosity.
 
Is there much reason to believe that the religions -- or, perhaps more
importantly, religious believers -- benefited by rigorous Free Exercise
Clause protection will be the same as the ones burdened by a rigorously
enforced Establishment Clause?  Historically, Catholics have been quite
burdened by a rigorous Establishment Clause, and have gotten very few
benefits from the Free Exercise Clause, even when it was relatively
rigorous.  (They might have gotten some benefits from religious
accommodations, such as the sacramental wine exemption, but not from the
Free Exercise Clause as such.)  On the other hand, the Amish have gotten
some benefits from a rigorous Free Exercise Clause, but it's not clear
that they have been much burdened by the Establishment Clause, even when
it was relatively rigorous.
 
I'm not even sure that the benefits of a rigorous Free Exercise Clause
and the burdens imposed by a rigorous Establishment Clause will even out
if you aggregate the effects on all the religions.  But I don't see how
such an aggregation would be proper.  Or am I mistaken?
 
Eugene
 
 

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


RE: The quid pro quo theory

2004-06-16 Thread Lupu
The piece to which Michael Newsom refers is The Trouble with 
Accommodation, 60 GW L Rev. 743, 779-781(1992). But the 4th 
category is Weak EC, Weak FE (Michael accidentally wrote the 4th 
one as a repeat of the third).

Chip Lupu

 On 16 Jun 2004 at 16:26, Newsom Michael wrote:

 I apologize for responding to this post at this late date.  However, I
 want to refer everybody to Lupu's piece (the name of which escapes me)
 in which he establishes a grid analysis of the two clauses.
 
 If I understand him aright, it goes something like this:
 
 (1) Strong EC, Strong FE
 (2) Strong EC, Weak FE
 (3) Weak EC, Strong FE
 (4) Weak EC, Strong FE.
 
 Those interested in protecting minority rights might find themselves
 in group (1).
 
 Those interested in protecting the prerogatives of the majority might
 find themselves in group (4).
 
 Those interested in promoting religious values, and the role of
 religion in public life might find themselves in group (3).
 
 Those interested in keeping religion at bay or in check might find
 themselves in group (2).
 
 These four pairings capture rather nicely the dynamic and the dilemma
 of the Religion Clauses.  Add a dash of Protestant Empire (or any
 other large historical construct if this one doesn't work), a pinch of
 race (particularly as it intersects with religion), and we are off and
 running. 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Thursday, June 10, 2004 12:30 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: The quid pro quo theory
 
 I've always been puzzled about this quid pro quo theory of the
 Religion Clauses.  There is no religion as a source of values and
 beliefs; there are *religions* (or denominations) as a source of
 values and beliefs.  Many of them may share many values, but they will
 also differ on many values and goals.  The members of the religions
 will be different, too.  True, there are some cultural battles in
 which secularists are aligned on one side and religious observers of
 many faiths on another.  But those are only a small fraction of all
 potential battles over values and beliefs, it seems to me; and even in
 those, a person's religious denomination is likely to be as important
 as his felt religiosity.
 
 Is there much reason to believe that the religions -- or, perhaps more
 importantly, religious believers -- benefited by rigorous Free
 Exercise Clause protection will be the same as the ones burdened by a
 rigorously enforced Establishment Clause?  Historically, Catholics
 have been quite burdened by a rigorous Establishment Clause, and have
 gotten very few benefits from the Free Exercise Clause, even when it
 was relatively rigorous.  (They might have gotten some benefits from
 religious accommodations, such as the sacramental wine exemption, but
 not from the Free Exercise Clause as such.)  On the other hand, the
 Amish have gotten some benefits from a rigorous Free Exercise Clause,
 but it's not clear that they have been much burdened by the
 Establishment Clause, even when it was relatively rigorous.
 
 I'm not even sure that the benefits of a rigorous Free Exercise Clause
 and the burdens imposed by a rigorous Establishment Clause will even
 out if you aggregate the effects on all the religions.  But I don't
 see how such an aggregation would be proper.  Or am I mistaken?
 
 Eugene
 
 
 
 ___
 To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
 http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
 



Ira C. (Chip) Lupu
F. Elwood  Eleanor Davis Professor of Law 
The George Washington University Law School 
2000 H St., NW
Washington D.C 20052

(202) 994-7053

[EMAIL PROTECTED]
[EMAIL PROTECTED]

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


RE: The quid pro quo theory

2004-06-16 Thread Sisk, Gregory C.
The grid or integrated approach to the Religion Clauses (or more
accurately, singular Clause) articulated by Chip Lupu is a most valuable way
to explore the clauses.

With acknowledgement of our considerable indebtedness to Chip, our
forthcoming Ohio State Law Journal empirical study of religious liberty
decisions in the lower federal courts further develops each of those four
grids as models -- Pro-Religion (Weak EC, Strong FE), Anti-Political (Strong
EC, Strong FE), Judicial-Restraint (Weak EC, Weak FE), and Pro-Secular
(Strong EC, Weak FE) -- and tests them in practice.  The results were rather
interesting (i.e., Catholic judges almost significant on the Pro-Religion
Model, while Jewish judges were signficantly correlated with the
Anti-Political Model).  Although the reprints have been slow to arrive, a
link is set out below:

http://personal2.stthomas.edu/GCSISK/Siskwebpagestuff/Sisk.Searching.Soul.pd
f

(Note that if the link breaks across a line in your e-mail, you may need to
cut and paste it into your browser for it to work.)

Michael's description of where a person with a particular interest would be
located among those models strikes me as correct, with the exception of
describing those in the Weak EC, Weak FE category as only interested in
protecting the prerogatives of the majority.  Although this is not the
category into which I would place myself (while the models are by nature
somewhat crude, I'd probably fall into the Pro-Religion category), I cannot
imagine that those who adopt the Weak EC, Weak FE approach on principle
would see themselves merely as endorsing the tyranny of the majority.
Rather, giving each position its full due, this is best understood as a
Judicial-Restraint approach that reflects a distrust of the judiciary and an
attendant preference for democratic institutions including the capacity of
those institutions to provide protection to minorities.

Greg Sisk

-Original Message-
From: Lupu [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
Sent: Wednesday, June 16, 2004 3:42 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: RE: The quid pro quo theory

The piece to which Michael Newsom refers is The Trouble with 
Accommodation, 60 GW L Rev. 743, 779-781(1992). But the 4th 
category is Weak EC, Weak FE (Michael accidentally wrote the 4th 
one as a repeat of the third).

Chip Lupu

 On 16 Jun 2004 at 16:26, Newsom Michael wrote:

 I apologize for responding to this post at this late date.  However, I
 want to refer everybody to Lupu's piece (the name of which escapes me)
 in which he establishes a grid analysis of the two clauses.
 
 If I understand him aright, it goes something like this:
 
 (1) Strong EC, Strong FE
 (2) Strong EC, Weak FE
 (3) Weak EC, Strong FE
 (4) Weak EC, Strong FE.
 
 Those interested in protecting minority rights might find themselves
 in group (1).
 
 Those interested in protecting the prerogatives of the majority might
 find themselves in group (4).
 
 Those interested in promoting religious values, and the role of
 religion in public life might find themselves in group (3).
 
 Those interested in keeping religion at bay or in check might find
 themselves in group (2).
 
 These four pairings capture rather nicely the dynamic and the dilemma
 of the Religion Clauses.  Add a dash of Protestant Empire (or any
 other large historical construct if this one doesn't work), a pinch of
 race (particularly as it intersects with religion), and we are off and
 running. 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] 
 Sent: Thursday, June 10, 2004 12:30 AM
 To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
 Subject: The quid pro quo theory
 
 I've always been puzzled about this quid pro quo theory of the
 Religion Clauses.  There is no religion as a source of values and
 beliefs; there are *religions* (or denominations) as a source of
 values and beliefs.  Many of them may share many values, but they will
 also differ on many values and goals.  The members of the religions
 will be different, too.  True, there are some cultural battles in
 which secularists are aligned on one side and religious observers of
 many faiths on another.  But those are only a small fraction of all
 potential battles over values and beliefs, it seems to me; and even in
 those, a person's religious denomination is likely to be as important
 as his felt religiosity.
 
 Is there much reason to believe that the religions -- or, perhaps more
 importantly, religious believers -- benefited by rigorous Free
 Exercise Clause protection will be the same as the ones burdened by a
 rigorously enforced Establishment Clause?  Historically, Catholics
 have been quite burdened by a rigorous Establishment Clause, and have
 gotten very few benefits from the Free Exercise Clause, even when it
 was relatively rigorous.  (They might have gotten some benefits from
 religious accommodations, such as the sacramental wine exemption, but
 not from the Free Exercise Clause as such.)  On the other

RE: The quid pro quo theory

2004-06-11 Thread Berg, Thomas C.
Eugene, I agree that very global quid pro quo theories -- like broad
Establishment Clause, broad Free Exercise Clause -- do not spread their
benefits to all religions equally.  (For example, I think that broad
establishment clause, broad free exercise tends to protect or benefit
minority or outsider religions, although I'd qualify that statement in some
important ways.  I'm thinking about this now because I'm writing a piece
about minority religions.)
 
But more specific quid pro quo arguments, it seems to me, can rest on real
connections.  For example: Because public schools cannot include religious
teaching in their curriculum, there should be special concern to protect
religious private schools and families' ability to use them if they
conscientiously wish to have religoius instruction in their children's
education.  That connection is still not perfect -- not all families who
want religious instruction in education will belong to a denomination that
operates religious schools -- but the connection is real because there are
indeed many families who make such a choice between public education and
private religious schools.
 
As for more global quid pro quo notions:  although of course there are many,
many religious views, nevertheless there is a general category called
religion that is singled out for distinctive treatment in the Constitution
and therefore may require distinctive treatment by government actors.  Even
if a general quid pro quo approach doesn't benefit all faiths equally, it
seems to me that it can have the advantage of setting forth an approach that
doesn't treat religious activity just the same as every other activity, but
is principled in the ways it departs from that sameness treatment.  For
example, the Lee v. Weisman passage -- preservation and transmission of
religious beliefs and worship is a responsibility and a choice committed to
the private sphere, which itself is promised freedom to pursue that mission
-- gives a principled (though certainly disputable) reason for treating
religious activities distinctively in various legal situations.  When
someone asks, for example, Why should there be exemptions from law just for
religious conduct?, a possible answer is, It's part of this overall
approach to religion that is sensible and justifiable, for [X] reasons.  I
think that the fact that one can point to other places where religion is
treated differently helps make the overall approach more sensible and
justifiable (though, of course, still open to dispute).
 
Tom Berg
 

  _  

From: Volokh, Eugene [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Wed 6/9/2004 11:29 PM
To: Law  Religion issues for Law Academics
Subject: The quid pro quo theory



I've always been puzzled about this quid pro quo theory of the Religion
Clauses.  There is no religion as a source of values and beliefs; there
are *religions* (or denominations) as a source of values and beliefs.  Many
of them may share many values, but they will also differ on many values and
goals.  The members of the religions will be different, too.  True, there
are some cultural battles in which secularists are aligned on one side and
religious observers of many faiths on another.  But those are only a small
fraction of all potential battles over values and beliefs, it seems to me;
and even in those, a person's religious denomination is likely to be as
important as his felt religiosity.


Is there much reason to believe that the religions -- or, perhaps more
importantly, religious believers -- benefited by rigorous Free Exercise
Clause protection will be the same as the ones burdened by a rigorously
enforced Establishment Clause?  Historically, Catholics have been quite
burdened by a rigorous Establishment Clause, and have gotten very few
benefits from the Free Exercise Clause, even when it was relatively
rigorous.  (They might have gotten some benefits from religious
accommodations, such as the sacramental wine exemption, but not from the
Free Exercise Clause as such.)  On the other hand, the Amish have gotten
some benefits from a rigorous Free Exercise Clause, but it's not clear that
they have been much burdened by the Establishment Clause, even when it was
relatively rigorous.


I'm not even sure that the benefits of a rigorous Free Exercise Clause and
the burdens imposed by a rigorous Establishment Clause will even out if you
aggregate the effects on all the religions.  But I don't see how such an
aggregation would be proper.  Or am I mistaken?


Eugene 


application/ms-tnef___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


Re: The quid pro quo theory

2004-06-10 Thread Steven Jamar
Sorry, but I don't see any of this as demonstrable or even as really very relevant to the interpretation of or to a consideration of the value of the religion clauses.

1.	Free exercise is a valuable thing regardless of a law insuring it which affects various groups differently.  The different impacts could well have a lot more to do with the content of the religion than the content of the guarantee of freedom to do it.  Some beliefs and practices are simply going to be less likely to be affected by state actions, and therefore less likely to need protection from those state actions.  To say one group benefits more than another seems to me to be worse than irrelevant -- it seems to be  missing the essential point and seems to be likely to stir up trouble.  Equality-thinking gone nuts.  Or govt-focused thinking gone way too far.  Or even construing an insuring provision as a grant.

2.	Non-establishment similarly affects various groups in various ways.  But the only way to say one group benefits more is to posit that there is a normal group against which one can or should measure.  

3.	How can one compare religious freedom in one state against another, except in some very crude ways, or except by a priori defining one's values into the equation?  Does Italy not have religious freedom?  Are  non-Christian religions harmed by Swiss law (at least pre-reform law)?  

Simply non-starters for me.

Gathering info and discussing things in context is one thing.  Positing general theories strikes me as beyond sensible.  But I still have those old practice roots which have not fully withered away despite two decades in academia.

Steve

-- 
Prof. Steven D. Jamar vox:  202-806-8017
Howard University School of Law   fax:  202-806-8428
2900 Van Ness Street NW	mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED]
Washington, DC  20008   http://www.law.howard.edu/faculty/pages/jamar

Rarely do we find men who willingly engage in hard, solid thinking. There is an almost universal quest for easy answers and half-baked solutions. Nothing pains some people more than having to think.

- Martin Luther King Jr., Strength to Love, 1963


___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw


The quid pro quo theory

2004-06-09 Thread Volokh, Eugene
I've always been puzzled about this quid pro quo theory of the Religion Clauses.  
There is no religion as a source of values and beliefs; there are *religions* (or 
denominations) as a source of values and beliefs.  Many of them may share many values, 
but they will also differ on many values and goals.  The members of the religions will 
be different, too.  True, there are some cultural battles in which secularists are 
aligned on one side and religious observers of many faiths on another.  But those are 
only a small fraction of all potential battles over values and beliefs, it seems to 
me; and even in those, a person's religious denomination is likely to be as important 
as his felt religiosity.
 
Is there much reason to believe that the religions -- or, perhaps more importantly, 
religious believers -- benefited by rigorous Free Exercise Clause protection will be 
the same as the ones burdened by a rigorously enforced Establishment Clause?  
Historically, Catholics have been quite burdened by a rigorous Establishment Clause, 
and have gotten very few benefits from the Free Exercise Clause, even when it was 
relatively rigorous.  (They might have gotten some benefits from religious 
accommodations, such as the sacramental wine exemption, but not from the Free Exercise 
Clause as such.)  On the other hand, the Amish have gotten some benefits from a 
rigorous Free Exercise Clause, but it's not clear that they have been much burdened by 
the Establishment Clause, even when it was relatively rigorous.
 
I'm not even sure that the benefits of a rigorous Free Exercise Clause and the burdens 
imposed by a rigorous Establishment Clause will even out if you aggregate the effects 
on all the religions.  But I don't see how such an aggregation would be proper.  Or am 
I mistaken?
 
Eugene
 
 
Alan Brownstein writes:
 
There are two religion clauses.
They should not be interpreted in isolation from each other without regard
to their impact on religion as a source of values and beliefs and as a
cultural and political influence on society. Proponents of a rigorously
enforced Establishment clause ought to recognize the limits placed on
religion by this mandate and should support rigorous free exercise
protection for religious institutions and practice. Similarly, proponents
of a vigorously enforced free exercise jurisprudence should appreciate the
advantages constitutional protection provides and accept Establishment
Clause restrictions on the state promotion of religion. That's only part of
the picture in interpreting the religion clauses, but it is certainly an
important part.

___
To post, send message to [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw