-Caveat Lector-

On May 2, 2004, at 9:05 PM, Kris Millegan wrote:


Like Nazism, Communism, and Prussianism, groups, like S & B and Bohemian Grove are based on statist Hegelian idealism, the precise opposite of our ideal of Constitutional liberty and individual rights. The Owl of Minerva is the symbol of Bohemian Grove and the Owl of Minerva is also the title of the Hegelian Society Journal in the United States.

http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/en/magee.htm


Glenn Magee (2001)

Hegel and the Hermetic Tradition

Published: Cornell University Press, 2001.

Introduction

God is God only so far as he knows himself. his self-knowledge is,
further, a self-consciousness in man and man’s knowledge of God, which
proceeds to man’s self-knowledge in God.
 — Hegel, Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences

1. Hegel as Hermetic Thinker

Hegel is not a philosopher. He is no lover or seeker of wisdom — he
believes he has found it. Hegel writes in the preface to the
Phenomenology of Spirit, “To help bring philosophy closer to the form
of Science, to the goal where it can lay aside the title of ‘love of
knowing’ and be actual knowledge — that is what I have set before me”
(Miller, 3; PC, 3). By the end of the Phenomenology, Hegel claims to
have arrived at Absolute Knowledge, which he identifies with wisdom.

Hegel’s claim to have attained wisdom is completely contrary to the
original Greek conception of philosophy as the love of wisdom, that is,
the ongoing pursuit rather than the final possession of wisdom. His
claim is, however, fully consistent with the ambitions of the Hermetic
tradition, a current of thought that derives its name from the
so-called Hermetica (or Corpus Hermeticum), a collection of Greek and
Latin treatises and dialogues written in the first or second centuries
A.D. and probably containing ideas that are far older. The legendary
author of these works is Hermes Trismegistus (“Thrice-Greatest
Hermes”). “Hermeticism” denotes a broad tradition of thought that grew
out of the “writings of Hermes” and was expanded and developed through
the infusion of various other traditions. Thus, alchemy, Kabbalism,
Lullism, and the mysticism of Eckhart and Cusa — to name just a few
examples — became intertwined with the Hermetic doctrines. (Indeed,
Hermeticism is used by some authors simply to mean alchemy.)
Hermeticism is also sometimes called theosophy, or esotericism; less
precisely, it is often characterized as mysticism, or occultism.

It is the thesis of this book that Hegel is a Hermetic thinker. I shall
show that there are striking correspondences between Hegelian
philosophy and Hermetic theosophy, and that these correspondences are
not accidental. Hegel was actively interested in Hermeticism, he was
influenced by its exponents from boyhood on, and he allied himself with
Hermetic movements and thinkers throughout his life. I do not argue
merely that we can understand Hegel as a Hermetic thinker, just as we
can understand him as a German or a Swabian or an idealist thinker.
Instead, I argue that we must understand Hegel as a Hermetic thinker,
if we are to truly understand him at all.

Hegel’s life and works offer ample evidence for this thesis.

There are references throughout Hegel’s published and unpublished
writings to many of the leading figures and movements of the Hermetic
tradition. These references are in large measure approving. This is
particularly the case with Hegel’s treatment of Eckhart, Bruno,
Paracelsus, and Boehme. Boehme is the most striking case. Hegel accords
him considerable space in his Lectures on the History of Philosophy —
more space, in fact, than he devotes to many significant mainstream
thinkers in the philosophic tradition.

There are, furthermore, numerous Hermetic elements in Hegel’s writings.
These include, in broad strokes, a Masonic subtext of “initiation
mysticism” in the Phenomenology of Spirit; a Boehmean subtext to the
Phenomenology’s famous preface; a Kabbalistic-Boehmean-Lullian
influence on the Logic; alchemical-Paracelsian elements in the
Philosophy of Nature; an influence of Kabbalistic and Joachimite
millennialism on Hegel’s doctrine of Objective Spirit and theory of
world history; alchemical and Rosicrucian images in the Philosophy of
Right; an influence of the Hermetic tradition of pansophia on the
system as a whole; an endorsement of the Hermetic belief in philosophia
perennis; and the use of perennial Hermetic symbolic forms (such as the
triangle, the circle, and the square) as structural, architectonic
devices.

Hegel’s library included Hermetic writings by Agrippa, Boehme, Bruno,
and Paracelsus. He read widely on Mesmerism, psychic phenomenal
dowsing, precognition, and sorcery. He publicly associated himself with
known occultists, like Franz von Baader. He structured his philosophy
in a manner identical to the Hermetic use of ‘Correspondences!’ He
relied on histories of thought that discussed Hermes Trismegistus, Pico
della Mirandola, Robert Fludd, and Knorr von Rosenroth alongside Plato,
Galileo, Descartes, and Newton. He stated in his lectures more than
once that the term “speculative” means the same thing as “mystical.” He
believed in an “Earth Spirit” and corresponded with colleagues about
the nature of magic. He aligned himself, informally, with “Hermetic”
societies such as the Freemasons and the Rosicrucians. Even Hegel’s
doodles were Hermetic, as we shall see in chapter 3 when I discuss the
mysterious “triangle diagram”.

There are four major periods in Hegel’s life during which he seems to
have been strongly under the influence of Hermeticism, or to have
actively pursued an interest in it. First, there is his boyhood in
Stuttgart, from 1770 to 1788. As I shall discuss in detail in chapter
2, during this period Württemberg was a major center of Hermetic
interest, with much of the Pietist movement influenced by Boehmeanism
and Rosicrucianism (Württemberg was the spiritual center of the
Rosicrucian movement). The leading exponents of Pietism, J. A. Bengel
and, in particular, F. C. Oetinger were strongly influenced by German
mysticism, Boehmean theosophy, and Kabbalism.

Most Hegel scholars have not thought it necessary to consider the
intellectual milieu of his boyhood. Hegel is almost universally
understood simply within the context of the German philosophical
tradition — as responding to Kant, Fichte, and Schelling. Needless to
say, the influence of Kant, Fichte, and Schelling was important, but it
was not the only influence on Hegel. Part of the reason other sources
of influence are missed or ignored is that few scholars are familiar
with the complexities of religious life in eighteenth-century Germany.
Those who are familiar are almost always from disciplines other than
philosophy, and almost always German. (The study of German Pietism is
almost exclusively the province of German-speaking scholars.) The
religious and intellectual life of Württemberg is, however, the obvious
place to begin to understand Hegel’s own intellectual origins,
characteristic ideas, and aims.

Hegel has to be understood in terms of the theosophical Pietist
tradition of Württemberg — he cannot be seen simply as a critic of
Kant. Indeed Hegel, as I will argue, was always a critic of Kant and
never a wholehearted admirer precisely because he was “imprinted” early
on by the tradition of pansophia, which was very much alive in
Württemberg, and by Oetinger’s ideal of the truth as the Whole (see
chapter 2). He could not accept Kant’s scepticism, nor could Schelling,
and for identical reasons. Yet they both recognized the power of Kant’s
thought and labored hard to move from his premises to their own
conclusions, to circumvent his scepticism at all costs, in the name of
the speculative ideal of their youth.

From 1793 to 1801 Hegel worked as a private tutor, first at Berne, then
at Frankfurt. As I shall discuss in chapter 3, Hegel’s biographer Karl
Rosenkranz referred to this period as a “theosophical phase” in Hegel’s
development. During this time, Hegel appears to have become conversant
with the works of Boehme, as well as Eckhart and Johannes Tauler. Also
during this period Hegel became involved in Masonic circles.

In Jena (1801-7), Hegel’s interest in theosophy continued. He lectured
at length, and approvingly, on Boehme and Bruno. He composed several
pieces, which have only come down to us in fragmentary form, employing
Hermetic language and symbolism (see chapters 3 and 4). His lectures on
the Philosophy of Nature during this time reflect an ongoing interest
in alchemy. It is likely that Schelling, who had come to Jena sometime
earlier, introduced Hegel to his circle of friends, which included a
number of Romantics who were heavily interested in Hermeticism.
Schelling himself was an avid reader of Boehme and Oetinger, and likely
encouraged Hegel’s interest.

The final “Hermetic” period of Hegel’s life is his time in Berlin, from
1818 until his death on November 14, 1831. This is contrary to what one
might expect. It might be assumed that Hegel’s “Hermeticism” was merely
an aberration of youth, which the “arch rationalist” moved away from as
he matured. Surprisingly, precisely the reverse seems to be the case.
In Berlin, Hegel developed a friendship with Franz von Baader, the
premiere occultist and mystic of the day. Together they studied Meister
Eckhart. The preface to Hegel’s 1827 edition of the Encyclopedia of the
Philosophical Sciences in Outline makes prominent mention of Boehme and
Baader. His revised 1832 edition of the Science of Logic corrects a
passage so as to include a reference to Boehme. His preface to the 1821
Philosophy of Right includes alchemical and Rosicrucian imagery. His
1831 Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion show the influence of the
mystic Joachim of Fiore, as well as certain structural correspondences
to the thought of Boehme. In sum, all the evidence indicates that in
the last period of his life, Hegel’s interest in the mystical and
Hermetic traditions intensified, and that he became more bold about
publicly aligning himself with Hermetic thinkers and movements.

The divisions of Hegel’s philosophy follow a pattern that is typical of
many forms of mystical and Hermetic philosophy. The Phenomenology
represents an initial stage of “purification” of raising the mind above
the level of the sensory and the mundane, a preparation for the
reception of wisdom. The Logic is equivalent to the Hermetic “ascent”
to the level of pure form, of the eternal, of “Universal Mind”
(Absolute Idea). The Philosophy of Nature describes an “emanation"’ or
“othering'’ of Universal Mind in the form of the spatio-temporal world.
Its categories accomplish a transfiguration of the natural: we come to
see the world as a reflection of Universal Mind. The Philosophy of
Spirit accomplishes a “return of created nature to the Divine by means
of man, who can rise above the merely natural and “actualize” God in
the world through concrete forms of life (e.g., the state and religion)
and through speculative philosophy.

2. Scholarship on Hegel and the Hermetic Tradition

It is important to note that these claims would not have been
particularly controversial in the decades after Hegel’s death. In the
1840s, Schelling publicly accused Hegel of having simply borrowed much
of his philosophy from Jakob Boehme. One of Hegel’s disciples,
Friedrich Theodor Vischer once asked, “Have you forgotten that the new
philosophy came forth from the school of the old mystics, especially
from Jacob Boehme?” Another Hegelian, Hans Martensen, author of one of
the first scholarly studies of Meister Eckhart, remarked that “German
mysticism is the first form in which German philosophy revealed itself
in the history of thought” (“philosophy” for Hegelians generally means
Hegel’s Philosophy). Wilhelm Dilthey noted the same continuity between
German mysticism and speculative philosophy.

Perhaps the most famous nineteenth-century study of Hermetic aspects in
Hegel was Ferdinand Christian Bauer’s Die christliche Gnosis (1835).
Bauer's was one of the first works to attempt to define Gnosticism and
to distinguish between its different forms. The term Gnostic is used
very loosely even in our own time, and very often what would more
properly be termed “Hermetic” is labeled “Gnostic” instead. (I will
discuss the differences between the two in the next section.) After a
lengthy discussion of Gnosticism in antiquity, Bauer argues that Jakob
Boehme was a modern Gnostic, and that Schelling and Hegel can be seen
as Boehme’s intellectual heirs, and thus as Gnostics themselves. Die
christliche Gnosis is about the closest thing to a book on Hegel and
the Hermetic tradition that has yet been published, though, as I have
said, Bauer’s focus is on gnosticism, not Hermeticism. In 1853, Ludwig
Noack published a two-volume work, Die Christlich Mystik nach ihrem
geschichtlichen Entwicklungsgange im Mittelalter und in der neueren
Zeit dargestellt, in which he dealt with the Idealists as modern
representatives of mysticism.

Later discussions of Hegel’s connection to Hermeticism are often
coupled with similar discussions of Schelling. This is the case with
Ernst Benz’s Mystical Sources of German Romantic Philosophy, a brief
but indispensable text by the leading scholar in this highly
specialized field. In 1938, a German scholar named Robert Schneider
published Schellings und Hegels scbwäbische Geistesahnen in Würzburg.
Most of the copies of Schneider’s book were destroyed during the allied
firebombing of Würzburg on March 16, 1945. Schneider was destroyed
along with them. His book is a valuable study of the theosophical
Pietism prevalent in Württemberg during Hegel and Schelling’s youth.

Other works by German scholars dealing with the relationship of
mysticism or Hermeticism to German Idealism and Hegel include Josef
Bach’s Meister Eckhart der Vater der Deutschen Spekulation. Ein Beitrag
zu einer Geschichte der deutschen Theologie und Philosophie der
mittleren Zeit (1864); Gottfried Fischer’s Geschichte der Entdeckung
der deutschen Mystiker, Eckhart, Tauler u. Seuse im 19. Jahrhundert
(1931); Emanuel Hirsch’s Die idealistische Philosophie und das
Christentum (1926); Fritz Leese’s Philosophie und Theologie im
Spätidealismus, Forschungen zur Auseinandersetzung von Christentum und
idealistischer Philosophie im 19.Jahrhundert (1919), and Von Jakob
Boehme zu Schelling. Zur Metaphysik des Gottesproblems (1927); Wilhelm
Lütgert’s Die Religion des Deutschen Idealismus und ihr Ende (1923);
and Heinrich Maier’s Die Anfange der Philosophie des deutschen
Idealismus (1930). There has also been a fair amount of Dutch
literature on the topic, including G. J. R J. Bolland’s Schelling,
Hegel, Fechner en de nieuwere theosophic (1910); J. d'Aulnis de
Bourrouill’s Het mystieke karakter van Hegel’s logica; and H. W. Mook’s
Hegeliaansch-theosofische opstellen (1913).

In French, Jacques d'Hondt’s Hegel Secret (1968) is an extremely
important study of Hegel’s relationship to Hermetic secret societies
such as the Masons, Illuminati, and Rosicrucians.

There is also an important body of English-language literature on Hegel
and mysticism, beginning with George Plimpton Adams’s The Mystical
Element in Hegel’s Early Theological Writings (1910). Frederick
Copleston authored a useful article, “Hegel and the Rationalization of
Mysticism” in 1971. Perhaps the most widely read English-speaking
interpreter of Hegel, J. N. Findlay was himself a theosophist, and his
interpretation of Hegel is attuned to its mystic-Hermetic aspects. In
Findlay’s Hegel: A Re-Examination (1958), he suggests tantalizingly
that Hegel was a “nineteenth-century representative of some philosophia
Germanica perennis.” H. S. Harris’s two-volume intellectual biography
of Hegel, Hegel’s Development (1972/1983), contains asides regarding
Hegel’s relationship to Eckhart, Boehme, Baader, and alchemy. Recently,
Cyril O'Regan has published a massive and groundbreaking study of the
mystical roots of Hegel’s philosophy of religion, The Heterodox Hegel
(1994).

Thus far, however, the most influential English-language account of
Hegel’s Hermeticism is Eric Voegelin’s. In his essay, “Response to
Professor Altizer’s ‘A New History and a New but Ancient God’” Voegelin
admits that “For a long time I studiously avoided any serious criticism
of Hegel in my published work, because I simply could not understand
him.” The turning point came with Voegelin’s study of gnosticism, and
the discovery that, “by his contemporaries Hegel was considered a
gnostic thinker:” Voegelin goes on to claim that Hegel’s thought
“belongs to the continuous history of modern Hermeticism since the
fifteenth century."’ Voegelin’s principal statement on Hegel’s
Hermeticism is a savagely polemical essay, “On Hegel: A Study in
Sorcery,” referring to the Phenomenology of Spirit as a “grimoire”
which “must be recognized as a work of magic — indeed, it is one of the
great magic performances.”

Voegelin’s claims are unique in that he does not simply claim that
Hegel was influenced by the Hermetic tradition. He claims that Hegel
was part of the Hermetic tradition and cannot be adequately understood
apart from it. Unfortunately, however, Voegelin never adequately
developed his thesis. He never spelled out, in detail, how Hegel is a
Hermetic thinker. Voegelin has, however, encouraged other scholars to
develop his thesis more systematically (and more soberly). David Walsh,
for instance, has written an important doctoral dissertation entitled
The Esoteric Origins of Modern Ideological Thought: Boehme and Hegel
(1978), in which he makes strong claims about Hegel’s indebtedness to
Boehme. Gerald Hanratty has also published an extensive two-part essay,
entitled “Hegel and the Gnostic Tradition” (1984-87).

Yet for all this scholarly activity, there has never been a systematic,
book-length study of Hegel as Hermetic thinker that takes into account
not only his intellectual development but also the entirety of his
mature system until the present book.

I consider this work not only a continuation of the tradition of
scholarship I have sketched out above but also as a contribution to an
ongoing project in the history of ideas pioneered by such writers as
Voegelin, Frances Yates, Antoine Faivre, Richard Popkin, Allan Debus,
Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, Paul Oskar Kristeller, D. P. Walker, Stephen
McKnight, and Alison Coudert (see bibliography). These scholars argue
that Hermeticism has influenced such mainstream rationalist thinkers as
Bacon, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, and Newton and has played a
hitherto unappreciated role in the formation of the central ideas and
ambitions of modern philosophy and science, particularly the modern
project of the progressive scientific investigation and technological
mastery of nature.

It is surely one of the great ironies of history that the Hermetic
ideal of man as magus, achieving total knowledge and wielding Godlike
powers to bring the world to perfection, was the prototype of the
modern scientist. Yet, as Gerald Hanratty writes, “the widespread
recourse to magical and alchemical techniques inspired a new confidence
in man’s operational powers. In contrast with the passive and
contemplative attitudes which generally prevail during earlier
centuries, Renaissance alchemists and Magi asserted their dominion over
all levels of being.” Hermeticism replaces the love of wisdom with the
lust for power. As we shall see, Hegel’s system is the ultimate
expression of this pursuit of mastery.

3. What is Hermeticism?

Whether or not Hegel can be understood as “Hermetic” depends on how
Hermeticism is defined. In truth, Hermeticism is difficult to define
rigorously. Its adherents all tend to share certain interests — often
classed as “occult” or “esoteric” — which are held together merely by
family resemblances. In part, my argument for Hegel’s Hermeticism
depends on demonstrating that Hegel’s interests coincide with the
curious mixture of interests typical of Hermeticists. These include
alchemy, Kabbalism, Mesmerism, extrasensory perception, spiritualism,
dowsing, eschatology, prisca theologia, philosophia perennis, Lullism,
Paracelcism, Joachimism, Rosicrucianism, Masonry, Eckhartean mysticism,
“correspondences” secret systems of symbolism, vitalism, and “cosmic
sympathies:”

There is, however, one essential feature that I shall take as
definitive of Hermeticism. Ernest Lee Tuveson, in his The Avatars of
Thrice Greatest Hermes: An Approach to Romanticism suggests that
Hermeticism constitutes a middle position between pantheism and the
Judaeo-Christian conception of God. According to traditional
Judaeo-Christian thought, God utterly transcends and is infinitely
distant from creation. Furthermore, God is entirely self-sufficient and
therefore did not have to create the world, and would have lost nothing
if He had not created it. Thus the act of creation is essentially
gratuitous and unmotivated. God creates out of sheer abundance, not out
of need. This doctrine has proved dissatisfying and even disturbing to
many, for it makes creation seem arbitrary and absurd. Pantheism, by
contrast, so thoroughly involves the divine in the world that
everything becomes God, even mud, hair, and dirt — which drains the
divine of its exaltedness and sublimity. Thus, pantheism is equally
dissatisfying.

Hermeticism is a middle position because it affirms both God’s
transcendence of the world and his involvement in it. God is
metaphysically distinct from the world, yet God needs the world to
complete Himself. Thus the act of creation is not arbitrary or
gratuitous, but necessary and rational. Consider these lines from the
“Discourse of Hermes to Tat: The mixing bowl or the monad” (Corpus
Hermeticum 4): “If you force me to say something still more daring, it
is [God’s] essence to be pregnant with all things and to make them. As
it is impossible for anything to be produced without a maker, so also
is it impossible for this maker [not] to exist always unless he is
always making everything.... He is himself the things that are and
those that are not.” Consider also Corpus Hermeticum 10: “God’s
activity is will, and his essence is to will all things to be.”
Finally, consider Corpus Hermeticum 14: “For the two are all there is,
what comes to be and what makes it, and it is impossible to separate
the one from the other. No maker can exist without something that comes
to be:” Thus, according to Hermeticism, God requires creation in order
to be God. This Hermetic account of creation is central to Hegel’s
thought as well.

But there is more. Hermeticists not only hold that God requires
creation, they make a specific creature, man, play a crucial role in
God’s selfactualization. Hermeticism holds that man can know God, and
that man’s knowledge of God is necessary for God’s own completion.
Consider the words of Corpus Hermeticum 10: “For God does not ignore
mankind; on the contrary, he recognizes him fully and wishes to be
recognized. For mankind this is the only deliverance, the knowledge of
God. It is ascent to Olympus.” Corpus Hermeticum 11 asks, “Who is more
visible than God? This is why he made all things: so that through them
all you might look on him.” As Garth Fowden notes, what God gains from
creation is recognition: “Man’s contemplation of God is in some sense a
two-way process. Not only does Man wish to know God, but God too
desires to be known by the most glorious of His creations, Man:” In
short, it is man’s end to achieve knowledge of God (or “the wisdom of
God,” theosophy). In so doing, man realizes God’s own need to be
recognized. Man’s knowledge of God becomes God’s knowledge of himself.
Thus the need for which the cosmos is created is the need for
selfknowledge, attained through recognition. Variations on this
doctrine are to be found throughout the Hermetic tradition.

It is important to understand the significance of this doctrine in the
history of ideas. On the standard Judaeo-Christian account of creation,
the creation of the world and God’s command that mankind seek to know
and love him seem arbitrary, because there is no reason why a perfect
being should want or need anything. The great advantage of the Hermetic
conception is that it tells us why the cosmos and the human desire to
know God exist in the first place.

This Hermetic doctrine of the “circular” relationship between God and
creation and the necessity of man for the completion of God is utterly
original. It is not to be found in earlier philosophy. But it recurs
again and again in the thought of Hermeticists, and it is the chief
doctrinal identity between Hermeticism and Hegelian thought.

Hegel is often described as a mystic. Indeed, even he describes himself
as one (see chapter 4). But mysticism is a broad concept that subsumes
many radically different ideas. All forms of mysticism aim at some kind
of knowledge of, experience of, or unity with the divine. If we ask
what kind of mystic Hegel is, the answer is that he is a Hermeticist.
Hermeticism is often confused with another form of mysticism,
Gnosticism (particularly in recent Hegel scholarship). Gnosticism and
Hermeticism both believe that a divine “spark” is implanted in man, and
that man can come to know God. However, Gnosticism involves an
absolutely negative account of creation. It does not regard creation as
a part of God’s being, or as “completing” God. Nor does Gnosticism hold
that God somehow needs man to know Him. Hermeticism is also very often
confused with Neoplatonism. Like the Hermeticists, Plotinus holds that
the cosmos is a circular process of emanation from and return to the
One. Unlike the Hermeticists, Plotinus does not hold that the One is
completed by man’s contemplation of it. (Centuries later, however, the
Neoplatonism of Proclus and of the Renaissance was influenced by
Hermeticism.)

Another parallel between Hermeticism and Hegel concerns the initiation
process through which the intuitive portion of the intellect is trained
to see the Reason inherent in the world. As Fowden notes, Hermetic
initiation seems to fall into two parts, one dealing with
self-knowledge, the other with knowledge of God. It can easily be
shown, simply on a theoretical level, that these two are intimately
wedded. To really know one’s self is to be able to give a complete
speech about the conditions of one’s being, and this involves speaking
about God and His entire cosmos. As Pico della Mirandola puts it, “he
who knows himself knows all things in himself.” Also, in the Near East
it was typical to portray God as hovering strangely between
transcendence and immanence. The attainment of enlightenment involved
somehow seeing the divine in oneself, indeed becoming divine.

We do not really know anything about the Hermes cult that may have
employed the Hermetic texts as its sacred writings. We know little or
nothing of their rites of initiation or how they lived. We can,
however, say that Hermetic initiation differed from initiation into,
for example, the Eleusinian mysteries in classical Greece. We also
happen to know quite little about what happened at Eleusis, but it does
seem to be the case that illumination there consisted in the
participation in some kind of arresting experience which was intended
to change the initiate permanently. We do not know what that experience
was, but we do know that it could be had by young and old, rich and
poor, educated and uneducated. This is not the case with Hermetic
initiation. Salvation for the Hermeticists was, as we have seen,
through gnosis, through understanding. This could be attained only
through hard work, and then it could be attained only by some. Hermes
is quoted in Corpus Hermeticum 16 as stating that his teaching “keeps
the meaning of its words concealed,” hidden from the discernment of the
unworthy.

However, it would be a mistake to treat the Hermetic initiation as
purely intellectual. Enlightenment does not occur simply by learning a
set of doctrines. One must not only know doctrine, but have the
real-life experience of the truth of the doctrine. One must be led up
to illumination carefully; one must actually explore the blind alleys
that promise illumination but do not deliver. Only in this way will the
true doctrine mean anything; only in this way will the initiate’s life
actually change. Fowden writes that Hermetic initiation is envisaged as
“a real experience, stretching all the capacities of those who embark
upon it,” and he quotes Corpus Hermeticum 4, stating that “it is an
extremely tortuous way, to abandon what one is used to and possesses
now, and to retrace one’s steps towards the old primordial things.” We
will see in chapter 4 that Hegel preserves both the intellectual and
emotional moments of this Hermetic conception of initiation.

Enlightenment, for the authors of the Hermetica and for Hegel, is not
just an intellectual event; it is expected to change the life of the
enlightened one. Philosophy, for Hegel, is about living. In brief, the
man who achieves Selbstbewusstsein is the man who becomes
selbstbewusst: confident, self-actualized, no longer an ordinary human
being. Klaus Vondung writes that “The Hermeticist does not need to
escape from the world in order to save himself, he wants to gain
knowledge of the world in order to expand his own self, and utilize
this knowledge to penetrate into the self of God. Hermeticism is a
positive Gnosis, as it were, devoted to the world. To know everything
is to in some sense have control over everything. This is what I term
the ideal of man as magus, and it is unique to the Hermetica. See, for
example, Corpus Hermeticum 4: “All those who heeded the proclamation
and immersed themselves in mind [nous] participated in knowledge and
became perfect [or “complete,” teleioi] people because they received
mind. But those who missed the point of the proclamation are people of
reason [or “speech,” logikon] because they did not receive [the gift
of] mind as well and do not know the purpose or the agents of their
coming to nous. In other words, the men of complete self-understanding
who know even the “purpose or the agents of their coming to be” are
perfect human beings. If Hegel did not believe that man could literally
become God, he certainly believed that the wise man is daimonic: a
more-than-merely-human participant in the divine life.

In the Corpus Hermeticum we find a kind of “bridge position” between
Egyptian occultism and the modern Hermeticism of Hegel and others.
Instead of conceiving words as carrying literal occult power, words
come to be seen as carrying a kind of existential empowerment. The
ideal of Hermetic theosophy becomes the formulation of a “complete
speech” (teleeis logos, “perfect discourse” or perhaps “Encyclopedic
discourse,” which means, of course, “circular” discourse). When
acquired, the complete speech, which concerns the whole of reality,
will radically transform and empower the life of the enlightened one.
So Hegel writes in a fragment preserved by Rosenkranz:

Every individual is a blind link in the chain of absolute necessity,
along which the world develops. Every individual can raise himself to
domination over a great length of this chain only if he realizes the
goal of this great necessity and, by virtue of this knowledge, learns
to speak the magic words which evoke its shape. The knowledge of how to
simultaneously absorb and elevate oneself beyond the total energy of
suffering and antithesis that has dominated the world and all forms of
its development for thousands of years — this knowledge can be gathered
from philosophy alone,

Another parallel between Hermeticism and Hegel is the analysis of the
divine into a set of “modes” or “moments” Hermeticists do not rest
content with the idea of an unknowable God. instead, they seek to
penetrate the divine mystery. They hold that it is possible to know God
in a piecemeal fashion, by coming to understand the different aspects
of the divine. The best example is Kabbalism, both in its Jewish and
Christian forms. Lull, Bruno, Paracelsus, Boehme, Oetinger, and many
others in the Hermetic tradition hold this belief.

Another parallel between Hermeticism and Hegel is the doctrine of
internal relations. For the Hermeticists, the cosmos is not a loosely
connected, or to use Hegelian language, externally related set of
particulars. Rather, everything in the cosmos is internally related,
bound up with everything else. Even though the cosmos may be
hierarchically arranged, there are forces that cut across and unify all
the levels. Divine powers understood variously as “energy” or “light”
pervade the whole. This principle is most clearly expressed in the
so-called Emerald Tablet of Hermes Trismegistus, which begins with the
famous lines “As above, so below.” This maxim became the central tenet
of Western occultism, for it laid the basis for a doctrine of the unity
of the cosmos through sympathies and correspondences between its
various levels. The most important implication of this doctrine is the
idea that man is the microcosm, in which the whole of the macrocosm is
reflected. Self-knowledge, therefore, leads necessarily to knowledge of
the whole.

To summarize, the doctrines of the Hermetica that became enduring
features of the Hermetic tradition can be enumerated as follows:

1. God requires creation in order to be God.

2. God is in some sense “completed” or has a need fulfilled through
man’s contemplation of Him.

3. Illumination involves capturing the whole of reality in a complete,
encyclopedic speech.

4. Man can perfect himself through gnosis: he becomes empowered through
the possession of the complete speech.

5. Man can know the aspects or “moments” of God.

6. An initial stage of purification in which the initiate is purged of
false intellectual standpoints is required before the reception of the
true doctrine.

7. The universe is an internally related whole pervaded by cosmic
energies.

To make clear the parallels between these doctrines and Hegel’s, here
is a preview of what I will be arguing in the rest of this book:

1. Hegel holds that God’s being involves “creation,” the subject matter
of his Philosophy of Nature. Nature is a moment of God’s being.

2. Hegel holds that God is in some sense “completed” or actualized
through the intellectual activity of mankind: “Philosophy” is the final
stage in the actualization of Absolute Spirit. Hegel holds the
“circular” conception of God and of the cosmos I referred to earlier,
involving God “returning to Himself” and truly becoming God through
man.

3. Hegel’s philosophy is encyclopedic: he aims to end philosophy, for
all intents and purposes, by capturing the whole of reality in a
complete, circular speech.

4. Hegel believes that we rise above nature and become masters of our
own destiny through the profound gnosis provided by his system.

5. Hegel’s Logic is an attempt to know the aspects or “moments” of God
as a system of ideas. In a famous passage of the Science of Logic,
Hegel states that the Logic “is to be understood as the system of pure
reason, as the realm of pure thought. This realm is truth as it is
without veil and in its own absolute nature. It can therefore be said
that this content is the exposition of God as He is in his eternal
essence before the creation of nature and a finite Spirit” (Miller, 50;
WL 1, 33-34).

6. Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit represents, in the Hegelian system,
an initial stage of purification in which the would-be philosopher is
purged of false intellectual standpoints so that he might receive the
true doctrine of Absolute Knowing (Logic-Nature-Spirit).

7. Hegel’s account of nature rejects the philosophy of mechanism. He
upholds what the followers of Bradley would later call a doctrine of
“internal relations” as against the typical, modern mechanistic
understanding of things in terms of “external relations.”

4. Hegel: A Metaphysical View

Given the evidence for Hegel’s place in the Hermetic tradition, it
seems surprising that so few Hegel scholars acknowledge it. The topic
is often dismissed as unimportant or uninteresting (it is neither).
Usually, it is treated as relevant only to Hegel’s youth (which is
false). Surely one reason for this attitude is disciplinary
specialization. Few scholars of the history of philosophy ever study
Hermetic thinkers. Another reason is the recent tendency among
influential Hegel scholars to argue that it is wrong-headed to treat
Hegel as having any serious interest in metaphysics or theology at all,
let alone the sort of exotic metaphysics and theology that we find in
Hermeticism. This is the so-called “non-metaphysical reading” of Hegel.
As Cyril O'Regan has pointed out, it goes hand in hand with an
“anti-theological” reading. For instance, David Kolb writes, “I want
most of all to preclude the idea that Hegel provides a cosmology
including the discovery of a wondrous new superentity, a cosmic self or
a world soul or a supermind.” But this is exactly what Hegel does.

The phrase “non-metaphysical reading” seems to have originated with
Klaus Hartmann who, in his influential 1972 article “Hegel: A
NonMetaphysical View,” identified Hegel’s system as a “hermeneutic of
categories.” Other well-known proponents of Hartmann’s approach include
Kenley Royce Dove, William Maker, Terry Pinkard, and Richard Dien
Winfield.

The non-metaphysical/anti-theological reading relies on ignoring or
explaining away the many frankly metaphysical, cosmological,
theological, and theosophical passages in Hegel’s writings and
lectures. Thus the non-metaphysical reading is less an interpretation
of Hegel than a revision. Its advocates sometimes admit this —
Hartmann, for instance — but more often than not they offer their
“reading” in opposition to other interpretations of what Hegel meant.
It is, furthermore, no accident that the same authors finish out their
“interpretation” by tacking a left-wing politics onto Hegel, for they
are, in fact, the intellectual heirs of the nineteenth-century “Young
Hegelians” who also gave non-metaphysical, anti-theological
“interpretations” of Hegel. The non-metaphysical reading is simply
Hegel shorn of everything offensive to the modern, secular, liberal
mind. This does not, however, imply that I am offering an alternative
“right Hegelian” reading of Hegel. I am simply reading Hegel. In so
doing, I hope to contribute to the “nonpartisan, historical and textual
analysis” of Hegel’s thought called for by Louis Dupré.

Such a reading, I am convinced, places Hegel’s philosophy squarely in
the tradition of classical metaphysics. In this view, I am in accord
with the broadly “ontotheological” interpretation of Hegel offered by
Martin Heidegger, who coined the term, and by such scholars as
Walterjaeschke, Emil Fackenheim, Cyril O'Regan, Malcolm Clark, Albert
Chapelle, Claude Bruaire, and Iwan Iljin. “Ontotheology” refers to the
equation of Being, God, and logos. Hegel’s account of the Absolute is
structurally identical to Aristotle’s account of Being as Substance
(ousia): it is the most real, independent, and self-sufficient thing
that is. Hegel identifies the Absolute with God, and does so both in
his public statements (his books and lectures) and in his private notes
— and with a straight face, without winking at us. Hegel does not offer
the categories of his Logic as mere “hermeneutic devices” but as
eternal forms, moments or aspects of the Divine Mind (Absolute Idea).
He treats nature as “expressing” the divine ideas in imperfect form. He
speaks of a “World Soul” and uses it to explain how dowsing and animal
magnetism work. He structures his entire philosophy around the
Christian Trinity, and claims that with Christianity the “principle” of
speculative philosophy was revealed to mankind.” He tells us — again
with a straight face — that the state is God on earth.

I see no reason not to take Hegel at his word on any of this. I am
interested only in what Hegel thought, not in what he ought to have
thought. To be sure, Hegel’s appropriation of classical metaphysics and
Christianity is transformative; Hegel is no ordinary believer. But his
metaphysical and religious commitments are not exoteric. He believes
that his Absolute and World Soul, and so forth, are real beings; they
are just not real in the sense in which traditional, pious
“picture-thinking” conceives of them. If Hegel departs from the
metaphysical tradition in anything, it is in dispensing with its false
modesty. Hegel does not claim to be merely searching for truth. He
claims that he has found it.

5. The Plan of This Book

In this book I will be concerned to do two things:

1) To demonstrate the influence of the Hermetic tradition on Hegel — by
way of remarks made in his texts and lectures, works he is known to
have had access to, and individuals he is known to have corresponded
with or met.

2) To situate Hegel’s thought within the Hermetic tradition; to show
that Hegel self-consciously appropriated and aligned himself with
Hermeticism; to show that Hegel’s thought can best be understood as
Hermetic. This is the most radical element of my thesis.

What will emerge from my discussion is, I hope, a radically new picture
of Hegel’s thought. It will no longer be possible to treat him as an
“arch rationalist” as many still do, let alone to read him in a
non-metaphysical or anti-theological manner.

Chapter 1 is devoted to an overview of the Hermetic tradition up until
the seventeenth century, dealing mainly with Germany. Chapter 2 starts
with the early seventeenth century and covers up to and including
Hegel’s youth. I will be concerned in chapter 2 mainly with the
intellectual milieu Hegel was born into. Chapter 3 is central to my
account. It presents an overall interpretation of Hegel’s thought in
light of his Hermetic connections. Chapters 4 through 7 cover Hegel’s
major writings.

In these chapters, I will not be concerned to present an “intellectual
biography” of Hegel. Such a work has already been written by H. S.
Harris, and I do not intend to try to surpass it. The study is
text-centered, although I have sketched — in important details about
Hegel’s life throughout. In terms of my treatment of Hegel’s
intellectual development, I have not made fine distinctions between
“stages” in his thinking. Developmental readings which speak of “early”
and “late” periods in a thinker’s life very often stem from an
inability to see the underlying identity or common tie between texts
which are superficially different (e.g., in their use of different
philosophical vocabularies). In the case of great thinkers — like
Plato, Aristotle, and Hegel — I think that there is very little
development. Great minds do not, for the most part, change (though in
chapter 7 I will discuss one important way in which I believe Hegel did
change his mind, and his allegiances). The different works produced by
great philosophers over a lifetime are usually variations on a theme,
or themes. To borrow Hegel’s language, one must learn to see the
identity in difference.

www.ctrl.org
DECLARATION & DISCLAIMER
==========
CTRL is a discussion & informational exchange list. Proselytizing propagandic
screeds are unwelcomed. Substance—not soap-boxing—please!   These are
sordid matters and 'conspiracy theory'—with its many half-truths, mis-
directions and outright frauds—is used politically by different groups with
major and minor effects spread throughout the spectrum of time and thought.
That being said, CTRLgives no endorsement to the validity of posts, and
always suggests to readers; be wary of what you read. CTRL gives no
credence to Holocaust denial and nazi's need not apply.

Let us please be civil and as always, Caveat Lector.
========================================================================
Archives Available at:

http://www.mail-archive.com/[EMAIL PROTECTED]/
<A HREF="http://www.mail-archive.com/[EMAIL PROTECTED]/">ctrl</A>
========================================================================
To subscribe to Conspiracy Theory Research List[CTRL] send email:
SUBSCRIBE CTRL [to:] [EMAIL PROTECTED]

To UNsubscribe to Conspiracy Theory Research List[CTRL] send email:
SIGNOFF CTRL [to:] [EMAIL PROTECTED]

Om

Reply via email to