-Caveat Lector- ACADEMIC FREEDOM ENDED IN U.K. -- How 'publisher' Wiley and Scotland's top 'university' threw to the wolves the psychologist who wrote about IQ and race. -- 'The g Factor', a product of Brand's thirty years in the psychology of intelligence and personality, was published in the UK by Wiley (Chichester) in February 1996 and met with expert approval. While commending the book, Britain's leading psychologist, Hans Eysenck, particularly remarked (in Personality & Individual Differences 26, 1996): "Apart from being accurate, Brand is also courageous; he deals with 'sensitive' problems in a straightforward, accurate fashion, without treading unnecessarily on vulnerable toes." However, the politically correct exponents of 1990's multiculturalism thought otherwise. They urged Wiley to withdraw the book from publication -- the modern form of censorship (applied similarly in 1997 to ex-Governor of Hong Kong, Chris Patten, when his then publisher, HarperCollins, discovered that his book criticized Red China). Interviewed by the press in April 1996, Brand agreed there would tend to be racial differences in children's speeds of school progress. Brand cheerfully accepted he would be what critics of IQ standardly called a 'scientific racist' -- though Brand preferred the term 'race realist.' (For use of the term 'scientific racist' see, for example, Steven Fraser et al., 1995, The Bell Curve Wars, New York : Basic. The term had become used by such extremist critics of IQ as Stephen Jay Gould, Leon Kamin, Richard Lewontin and Steven Rose to describe academic psychologists like Hans Eysenck, Art Jensen, Richard Lynn and Phil Rushton who did race research and came to hereditarian conclusions.) Brand believed 'The g Factor' would vindicate his position and expose critics as hysterical 'ignoracists' whose ideology had rendered them incapable of examining evidence; but Brand was due for a long wait. De-published by Wiley (on orders from their New York head office), slated by his University Principal, and replying in kind, Brand found himself under attack from all quarters. 'Feminists' took a special interest as it emerged that Brand sympathized with Freud and believed in biologically-based sex differences as well as race differences. Through 1996/7, Brand was witch-hunted, censored by his University, thrown to the tabloid press for writing his censorship-lambasting NewsLetter in defence of his book, sent before a three-month disciplinary Tribunal by his University and fired. Precisely why he was fired still remains a mystery. The facts are as follows. 1. Brand had refused to grovel when Edinburgh University's Principal Stewart Sutherland told the press in April, 1996, that his apparent views on IQ Were "false and personally obnoxious." The Principal's comments were given wide publicity (e.g. in the London broadsheet press). After the Principal refused to withdraw his unprecedented condemnation, and refused to read Brand's book, Brand began criticizing the University on the Internet in 'The 'g' Factor NewsLetter.' (This newsletter was issued almost daily and gave news of, and support to victims of political correctness. It castigated social-environmentalist ideas that people are easily conditioned, shaped or driven into psychopathology by their experiences with people.) 2. On October 16 1996, Brand e-mailed colleagues and supporters one page of comment which ridiculed the prosecution of a 73-year-old Nobel Laureate, Carleton Gajdusek, who faced a 30-year jail term for non-violent paedophilia in Maryland c. 1985. (Gajdusek's work on 'laughing brain rot' [kuru] in Papua New Guinea had helped the West crack bovine spongiform encephalopathy [BSE, or Mad Cow Disease]. Gajdusek had adopted (peadophile)some forty children from Papua New Guinea and educated them in the United States at his own expense. Suspension from teaching and nine months of investigation by An E.U. Tribunal culminated, on 8 August 1997, in Brand being dismissed, after 27 years of service, for his "gross misconduct." Just what Edinburgh University found "disgraceful" in Brand's conduct remains to be clarified. From the University's prosecution case to its own Tribunal, the main alleged problem was that Brand had upset his Psychology colleagues by his realistic and humorous observations on a range of psychological topics, and especially on 'feminist issues' like whether women find their greatest satisfaction in maternity. Brand's colleagues in psychology also did not like him achieving publicity for his views. Thus for him to have articulated the long-standing (though little publicised) expert consensus that some forms of paedophilia are empirically harmless (when involving intelligent and uncoerced adolescents) was, for his colleagues, 'the last straw.' Yet what exactly was "disgraceful" in Brand's pointing to the empirical evidence about paedophilia -- or to the empirical evidence about race -- and indicating his conclusion that mercy should be shown to the accused Nobelist who had pioneered the way to public understanding of BSE? The University's final position, after nine months of work on the subject, was that it objected not so much to what Brand had said as to the way he had said it. -- But the same complaint could be made retrospectively against *any* statement by an academic that finally fell foul of the tabloid newspapers. Essentially, Edinburgh University is requiring that no academic should make any controversial views intelligible to the public that pays academics' salaries. On 24 March 1998, Brand's Appeal against his dismissal was rejected By a Scottish High Court judge who had been selected by the University. Mr T. Gordon Coutts, QC, ruled that, under the UK's 1988 Education Act, British academics -- whatever the disciplinary codes of their own universities might actually say -- do not need to be guilty of anything as serious as "gross misconduct" for their universities to be entitled to sack them without warning. Since 1988, academics can be dismissed for "good cause" -- a term deriving from general UK employment protection legislation, but certainly permitting dismissal for expressing views that are merely embarrassing to an employer.* Brand's battle with Edinburgh University has thus revealed, so far, that 'academic freedom', as usually understood,** was ended in Britain in 1988. R.I.P. Yet the Coutts verdict is far from being the end of the matter. For example, it remains unclear how Brand's conduct was "disgraceful" -- even without the requirement that the degree of disgrace should amount to "gross misconduct." Brand's defence of his book certainly lacked modern piety, political correctness and any undue deference to Edinburgh University's Principal. Yet what action of Brand's was truly "disgraceful" or "scandalous" or "immoral"? (Such are the legal ways of sacking ordinary British workers -- operatives at biscuit factories etc.*** -- without warning) In contrast, it is perfectly clear how to punish today a British academic who says genes are substantially involved in causing the empirical link between race and IQ: he is de-published, hounded by self-styled 'anti-racists', condemned by his university, thrown to the tabloid press so they can rake through his sex life, and fired for the slightest hint of departure from media morality in any of his opinions. Brand had not even called for change in the law when denying that the typical intelligent paedophile did demonstrable harm. He had offended ideologues and hysterics merely by pointing out that scientists know much that contradicts the press and popular opinion -- whether about race or paedophilia. Above all, Brand had challenged the politically correct formulation that all human inequalities are the result of the downtrodden having suffered 'disadvantages' which utopians should be employed by the state to rectify. Brand had disputed the environmentalistic view that society is full of 'victims' of capitalism, imperialism, racism or male chauvinism -- a view that would express itself in the Dianamania of 1997 and in many claims for 'recovered memories' of childhood abuse. Though modern research unfailingly shows the environments imposed upon people to account for rather little -- and their own choices of environment to count for much -- Brand's challenge could not be tolerated by those who enjoy their roles as the paid champions of state welfarism. The West's new piety demands that universities return to their pre-twentieth-century condition in which religious belief could not be seriously challenged;**** and Edinburgh University has agreed. Those who hope British academics will help them explain controversial truths to the public will hope in vain. Until the Edinburgh verdict is overturned, every British academic will know he is not seriously free -- even in e-mail -- to mention unpopular facts. Britons have liked to sing in the twentieth century that they "never, never, never shall be slaves"; but their universities will now remain enslaved to American campus speech codes until Brand and 'The g Factor' are vindicated. Chapter 12 Population Differences in g: Causal Hypotheses The relationship of the g factor to a number of biological variables and its relationship to the size of the white-black differences on various cognitive tests (i.e., Spearman's hypothesis) suggests that the average white-black difference in g has a biological component. Human races are viewed not as discrete, or Platonic, categories, but rather as breeding populations that, as a result of natural selection, have come to differ statistically in the relative frequencies of many polymorphic genes. The "genetic distances" between various pop-ulations form a continuous variable that can be measured in terms of differences in gene frequencies. Racial populations differ in many genetic characteristics, some of which, such as brain size, have behavioral and psychometric correlates, particularly g. What I term the default hypothesis states that the causes of the phenotypic differences between contemporary populations of recent African and European descent arise from the same genetic and environmental factors, and in approximately the same magnitudes, that account for individual differences within each population. Thus genetic and en-vironmental variances between groups and within groups are viewed as essentially the same for both populations. The default hypothesis is able to account for the present evidence on the mean white-black difference in g. There is no need to invoke any ad hoc hypothesis, or a Factor X, that is unique to either the black or the white population. The environmental component of the average s difference between groups is primarily attributable to a host of microenvironmental factors that have biological effects. They result from non-genetic variation in prenatal, perinatal, and neonatal conditions and specific nutritional factors. The many studies of Spearman's hypothesis using the method of correlated vectors show a strong relationship between the g loadings of a great variety of cognitive tests and the mean black-white differences on those tests. The fact that the same g vectors that are correlated with W-B differences are also correlated (and to about the same degree) with vectors composed of various cognitive tests' correlations with a number of genetic, anatomical, and physiological variables suggests that certain biological factors may be related to the average black-white population difference in the level of g. The degree to which of each of many different psychometric tests is correlated with all of the other tests is directly related to the magnitude of the test's g loading. What may stem surprising, however, is the fact that the degree to which a given test is correlated with any one of the following variables is a positive function of that test's s loading: Hereditability of test scores Amount of inbreeding depression of test scores. Heterosis (hybrid vigor, that is, raised test scores, due to outbreeding). Head size (also, by inference, brain size). Average evoked potential (AEP) habituation and complexity. Glucose metabolic rate as measured by PET scan. Average reaction time to elementary cognitive tasks Size of The mean W-B difference on various cognitive tests. The one (and probably the only) common factor that links all of these non- psychometric variables to psychometric test scores and also links psychometric test scores to the magnitude of the mean W-B difference is the s factor. The critical role of g in these relationships is shown by the fact that the magnitude of a given test's correlation with any one of the above-listed variables is cor-related with the magnitude of the W-B difference on that test. For example, Rushton"' reported a correlation (r = +-.48) between the magnitudes of the mean W-B differences (in the American standardization sample) on eleven subtests of the WISC-R and the effect of inbreeding depression on the eleven subtest scores of the Japanese version of the WISC. Further, the subtests' 6 loadings in the Japanese data predicted the American W-B differences on the WISC-R sub-tests with r = .69-striking evidence of the 6 factor's robustness across different cultures. Similarly, the magnitude of the mean W-B difference on each of sev-enteen diverse psychometric tests was predicted (with r = .71, p < .01) by the tests' correlations with head size (a composite measure of length, width, and circumference)." This association of psychometric tests' g loadings, the tests' correlations with genetic and other biological variables, and the mean W-B differences in test scores cannot be dismissed as happenstance. The failure of theories of group 420 differences in IQ that are based exclusively on attitudinal, cultural, and experiential factors to predict or explain such findings argues strongly that biological factors, whether genetic or environmental in origin, must be investigated. Before examining possible biological factors in racial differences in mental abilities, however, we should be conceptually clear about the biological meaning of the term "race." THE MEANING OF RACE Nowadays one often reads in the popular press (and in some anthropology textbooks) that the concept of human races is a fiction (or, as one well-known anthropologist termed it, a "dangerous myth"), that races do not exist in reality, but are social constructions of politically and economically dominant groups for the purpose of maintaining their own status and power in a society. It naturally follows from this premise that, since races do not exist in any real, or biological, sense, it is meaningless even to inquire about the biological basis of any racial differences. I believe this line of argument has five main sources, none of them scientific: Heaping scorn on the concept of race is deemed an effective way of combating racism-here defined as the belief that individuals who visibly differ in certain characteristics deemed "racial" can be ordered on a dimension of "human worth" from inferior to superior, and that therefore various civil and political rights, as well as social privileges, should be granted or denied according to a person's supposed racial origin. Neo-Marxist philosophy (which still has exponents in the social sciences and the popular media) demands that individual and group differences in psychologically and socially significant traits be wholly the result of economic inequality, class status, or the oppression of the working classes in a capitalist society. It therefore excludes consideration of genetic or biological factors (except those that are purely exogenous) from any part in explaining behavioral differences among humans. It views the concept of race as a social invention by those holding economic and political powers to justify the division and oppression of unprivileged classes. * The view that claims that the concept of race (not just the misconceptions about it) is scientifically discredited is seen as a way to advance more harmonious relations among the groups in our society that are commonly perceived as "racially" different. * The universal revulsion to the Holocaust, which grew out of the racist doctrines of Hitler's Nazi regime, produced a reluctance on the part of democratic societies to sanction any inquiry into biological aspects of race in relation to any behavioral variables, least of all socially important ones. * Frustration with the age-old popular wrong-headed conceptions about race has led some experts in population genetics to abandon the concept instead of attempting candidly to make the public aware of how the concept of race is viewed by most present-day scientists. Wrong Conceptions of Race. The root of most wrong conceptions of race is the Platonic view of human races ;is distinct types, that is, discrete, mutually 421 exclusive categories. According to this view, any observed variation among the members of a particular racial category merely represents individual deviations from the archetype, or ideal type, for that "race." Since, according to this Platonic view of race, every person can be assigned to one or another racial category, it naturally follows that there is some definite number of races, each with its unique set of distinctive physical characteristics, such as skin color, hair texture, and facial features. The traditional number has been three: Caucasoid, Mongoloid, and Negroid, in part derived from the pre-Darwinian creationist view that "the races of mankind" could be traced back to the three sons of Noah-Shem, Ham, and Japheth. The Cause of Biological Variation. All that is known today about the world wide geographic distribution of differences in human physical characteristics can be understood in terms of the synthesis of Darwinian evolution and population genetics developed by R. A. Fisher, Sewall Wright, Theodosius Dobzhansky, and Ernst Mayr. Races are defined in this context as breeding populations that differ from one another in gene frequencies and that vary in a number of intercorrelated visible features that are highly heritable. Racial differences are a product of the evolutionary process working on the human genome, which consists of about 100,000 polymorphic genes (that is, genes that contribute to genetic variation among members of a species) located in the twenty-three pairs of chromosomes that exist in every cell of the human body. The gents, each with its own locus (position) on a particular chromosome, contain all of the chemical information needed to create an organism. In addition to the polymorphic genes, there are also a great many other gents that are not polymorphic (that is, are the same in all individuals in the species) and hence do not contribute to the normal range of human variation. Those genes that do product variation are called polymorphic genes, as they have two or more different forms called alleles, whose codes differ in their genetic information. Different alleles, therefore, produce different effects on the phenotypic characteristic determined by the gene at a particular chromosomal locus. Genes that do not have different alleles (and thus do not have variable phenotypic effects) are said to have gone to fixation; that is, alternative alleles, if any, have long since been eliminated by natural selection in the course of human or mammalian evolution. The physiological functions served by most basic "housekeeping" genes are so crucial for the organism's development and viability that almost any mutation of them proves lethal to the individual who harbors it; hence only one form of the gene is possessed by all members of a species. A great many such essential genes are in fact shared by closely related species; the number of genes that are common to different species is inversely related to the evolutionary distance between them. For instance, the two living species closest to Homo sapiens in evolutionary distance, chimpanzees and gorillas, have at least 97 percent of their genes (or total genetic code) in common with present-day humans, scarcely less than chimps and gorillas have in common with each other. This means that even the very small percentage of genes (<3 percent) that differ between humans and 422 the great apes is responsible for all the conspicuous and profound phenotypic differences observed between apes and humans. The genetic difference appears small only if viewed on the scale of differences among all animal species. New alleles created by mutation are subject to pleural natural selection according to the degree of fitness they confer in a particular environment. Changed environmental conditions can alter the selection pressure for a certain allele, depending on the nature of its phenotypic expression, thereby either increasing or decreasing its frequency in a breeding population. Depending on its fitness in a given environment, it may go to extinction in the population or it may go to fixation (with every member of the population eventually possessing the allele).' Many polymorphic gene loci harbor one or another allele of a balanced polymorphism where in two or more alleles with comparable fitness values (in a particular environment) are maintained at equilibrium in the population. Thus spontaneous genetic mutation and recombination, along with differential selection of new alleles according to how their phenotypic expression affects inclusive fitness, are crucial mechanisms of the whole evolutionary process. The variation in all inherited human characteristics has resulted from this process, in combination with random changes caused by genetic drift and gene frequency changes caused by migration and intermarriage patterns. Races as Breeding Populations with Fuzzy Boundaries. Most anthropologists and population geneticists today believe that the preponderance of evidence from both the dating of fossils and the analysis of the geographic distribution of many polymorphic genes in present-day indigenous populations argues that genus Homo originated in Africa. Estimates are that our direct distant hominid precursor split off from the great apes some four to six million years ago. The consensus of human paleontologists (as of 1997) accept the following basic scenario of human evolution. Austropalithecus afarensiss was a small (about 3'6"), rather apt-like hominid that appears to have been ancestral to all later hominids. It was bipedal, walking more or less upright, and had a cranial capacity of 350 to 520 cm' (about the same as that of the chimpanzee, but relatively larger for its overall body size). Branching from this species were at least two lineage's, one of which led to a new genus, Homo. Homo also had several branches (species). Those that were precursors of modern humans include HOMO habilis, which lived about 2.5 to I .5 million years ago. It used tools and even made tools, and had a cranial capacity of 510 to 750 cm3 (about half the size of modern humans). Homo erectus lived about 1.5 to 0.3 million years ago and had a cranial capacity of 850 to 1100 cm' (about three-fourths the size of modern humans). The first hominid whose fossil remains have been found outside .4frica. Homo erectus. migrated as far as the Middle East, Europe, and Western and Southeastern Asia. No Homo erectus remains have been found in Northern Asia, whose cold climate probably was too severe for their survival skills. Homo sapiens branched off the Homo erectus line in Africa at least 100 thousand years ago. During a period from about seventy to ten thousand years ago they spread from Africa to the Middle East, Europe, all of Asia, Australia, and North and South America. To distinguish certain archaic subspecies of Homo sapiens (e.g., Neanderthal man) that became extinct during this period from their contemporaries who were anatomically modern humans, the latter are now referred to as Homo sapiens sapiens (or Homo s. sapiens); it is this line that branched off Homo erectus in Africa and spread to every continent during the last 70.000 years. These prehistoric humans survived as foragers living in small groups that frequently migrated in starch of food. GENETIC DISTANCE As small populations of Homo s. sapiens separated and migrated further away from Africa, genetic mutations kept occurring at a constant rate, as occurs in all living creatures. Geographic separation and climatic differences, with their different challenges to survival, provided an increasingly wider basis for populations to become genetically differentiated through natural selection. Genetic mutations that occurred after each geographic separation of a population had taken place were differentially selected in each subpopulation according to the fitness the mutant gent conferred in the respective environments. A great many mutations and a lot of natural selection and genetic drift occurred over the course of the five or six thousand generations that humans were gradually spreading over the globe. The extent of genetic difference, termed genetic distance, between separated populations provides an approximate measure of the amount of time since their separation and of the geographic distance between them. In addition to time and distance, natural geographic hindrances to gene flow (i.e., the interchange of genes between populations), such as mountain ranges, rivers, seas, and deserts, also restrict gene flow between populations. Such relatively isolated groups are termed breeding populations, because a much higher frequency of mating occurs between individuals who belong to the same population than occurs between individuals from different populations. (The ratio of the frequencies of within/ between population matings for two breeding populations determines the degree of their genetic isolation from one another.) Hence the combined effects of geographic separation, genetic mutation, genetic drift, and natural selection for fitness in different environments result in population differences in the frequencies of different alleles at many gene loci. There are also other causes of relative genetic isolation resulting from language differences as well as from certain social, cultural, or religious sanctions against persons mating outside their own group. These restrictions of gene flow may occur even among populations that occupy the same territory. Over many generations these social forms of genetic isolation produce breeding populations (including certain ethnic groups) that evince relatively slight differences in allele frequencies from other groups living in the same locality. When two or more populations differ markedly in allele frequencies at a great many gene loci whose phenotypic effects visibly distinguish them by a particular configuration of physical features, these populations are called subspecies. Virtually every living species on earth has two or more subspecies. The human species is no exception, but in this case subspecies are called races. Like all other subspecies, human races are interfertile breeding populations whose individuals differ on average in distinguishable physical characteristics. Because all the distinguishable breeding populations of modern humans were derived from the same evolutionary branch of the genus HOMO, namely homo s. sapiens, and because breeding populations have relatively permeable (non biological) boundaries that allow gene how between them, human races can be considered as genetic "fuzzy sets." That is to say, a race is one of a number of statistically distinguishable groups in which individual membership is not mutually exclusive by any single criterion, and individuals in a given group differ only statistically from one another and from the group's central tendency on each of the many imperfectly correlated genetic characteristics that distinguish between groups as such. The important point is that the average difference on all of these characteristics that differ among individuals with the group is less than the average difference between the groups on these genetic characteristics What is termed a dine results where groups overlap at their fuzzy boundaries in some characteristic, with intermediate gradations of the phenotypic characteristic, often making the classification of many individuals ambiguous or even impossible, unless they are classified by some arbitrary rule that ignores biology. The fact that there are intermediate gradations or blends between racial groups, however, does not contradict the genetic and statistical concept of race. The different colors of a rainbow do not consist of discrete bands but are a perfect continuum, yet we readily distinguish different regions of this continuum as blue, green, yellow, and red, and we effectively classify many things according to these colors. The validity of such distinctions and of the categories based on them obviously need not require that they form perfectly discrete Platonic categories. It must be emphasized that the biological breeding populations called races can only be defined statistically, as populations that differ in the central tendency (or mean) on a large number of different characteristics that are under some degree of genetic control and that are correlated with each other through descent from common ancestors who are relatively recent in the time scale of evolution (i.e., those who lived about ten thousand years ago, at which time all of the continents and most of the major islands of the world were inhabited by relatively isolated breeding populations of Homo s. sapiens). Of course, any rule concerning the number of gene loci that must show differences in allele frequencies (or any rule concerning the average size of differences in frequency) between different breeding populations for them to be considered races is necessarily arbitrary, because the distribution of average absolute differences in allele frequencies in the world's total population is a 426 perfectly continuous variable. Therefore, the number of different categories, or races, into which this continuum can be divided is, in principle, wholly arbitrary, depending on the degree of genetic difference a particular investigator chooses as the criterion for classification or the degree of confidence one is willing to accept with respect to correctly identifying the area of origin of one's ancestors. Some scientists have embraced all of Homo sapiens in as few as two racial categories, while others have claimed as many as seventy. These probably represent the most extreme positions in the "lumper" and "splitter" spectrum. Logically, we could go on splitting up groups of individuals on the basis of their genetic differences until WE reach each pair of monozygotic twins, which are genetically identical. But as any pair of MZ twins are always of the same sex, they of course cannot constitute a breeding population. (If hypothetically they could, the average genetic correlation between all of the offspring of any pair of MZ twins would be 2/3; the average genetic correlation between the offspring of individuals paired at random in the total population is 1/2; the offspring of various forms of genetic relatedness, such as cousins [a preferred match in some parts of the world], falls somewhere between 2/3 and 1/2.) However, as I will explain shortly, certain multivariate statistical methods can provide objective criteria for deciding on the number and composition of different racial groups that can be reliably determined by the given genetic data or that may be useful for a particular scientific purpose. But one other source of genetic variation between populations must first be explained. Genetic Drift. In addition to mutation, natural selection, and migration, another means by which breeding population may differ in allele frequencies is through a purely stochastic (that is, random) process termed genetic drift. Drift is most consequential during the formation of new populations when their numbers are still quite small. Although drift occurs for all gene loci, Mendelian characters (i.e., phenotypic traits), which are controlled by a single gene locus, are more noticeably affected by drift than are polygenic traits (i.e., those caused by many genes). The reason is purely statistical. Changes in a population's allele frequencies attributable to genetic drift can be distinguished from changes due to natural selection for two masons: (1) Many genes are neutral in the sense that their allele frequencies have remained unaffected by natural selection, because they neither increase nor decrease fitness; over time they move across the permeable boundaries of different breeding populations. (2) When a small band of individuals emigrates from the breeding population of origin to found a new breeding population, it carries with it only a random sample of all of the alleles, including neutral alleles, that existed in the entire original population. That is, the allele frequencies at all gene loci in the migrating band will not exactly match the allele frequencies in the original population. The band of emigrants, and of course all its descendants (who may eventually form a large and stable breeding population), therefore differs genetically from its parent population as the result of a purely random process. This random process is called founder effect. It applies to all gene loci. All during the time that genetic drift was occurring, gene mutations steadily continued, and natural selection continued to product changes in allele frequencies at many loci. Thus the combined effects of genetic drift, mutation, and natural selection ensure that a good many alleles are maintained at different frequencies in various relatively isolated breeding populations. This process did not happen all at once and then cease. It is still going on, but it takes place too slowly to be perceived in the short time span of a few generations. It should be noted that the phenotypic differences between populations that were due to genetic drift are considerably smaller than the differences in those phenotypic characteristics that were strongly subject to natural selection, especially those traits that reflect adaptations to markedly different climatic conditions, such as darker skin color (thought to have evolved as protection from the tropical sun's rays that can cause skin cancer and to protect against folate decomposition by sunlight), light skin color (to admit more of the ultraviolet rays needed for the skin's formation of vitamin D in northern regions; also because clothing in northern latitudes made dark skin irrelevant selectively and it was lost through random mutation and drift), and globular versus elongated body shape and head shape (better to conserve or dissipate body heat in cold or hot climates, respectively).' Since the genetic drift of neutral genes is a purely random process, and given a fairly constant rate of drift, the differing allele frequencies of many neutral genes in various contemporary populations can be used as a genetic clock to determine the approximate time of their divergence. The same method has been used to estimate the extent of genetic separation, termed genetic distance, between populations. Measurement and Analysis of Genetic Distance between Groups. Modern genetic technology makes it possible to measure the genetic distance between different populations objectively with considerable precision, or statistical reliability. This measurement is based on a large number of genetic polymorphisms for what are thought to be relatively neutral genes, that is, genes whose allele frequencies therefore differ across populations more because of mutations and genetic drift than be cause of natural selection. Population allele frequencies can be as low as zero or as high as 1.0 (as there are certain alleles that have large frequencies in some populations but are not found at all in other populations). Neutral genes are preferred in this work be cause they provide a more stable and accurate evolutionary "clock" than do genes whose phenotypic characters have been subjected to the kinds of diverse external conditions that are the basis for natural selection. Although neutral genes provide a more accurate estimate of populations' divergence times, it should be noted that, by definition, they do not fully reflect the magnitude of genetic differences between populations that are mainly attributable to natural selection. The technical rationale and formulas for calculating genetic distance are fully explicated elsewhere. For present purposes, the genetic distance, D, between two groups can be thought of here simply as the average difference in allele 428 frequencies between two populations, with D scaled to range from zero (i.e., no allele differences) to one (i.e., differences in all alleles). One can also think of D as the complement of the correlation coefficient r (i.e., D = I - r, and r = I - D). This conversion of D to r is especially useful, because many of the same objective multivariate statistical methods that were originally devised to analyze large correlation matrices (e.g., principal components analysis, factor analysis. hierarchical cluster analysis, multidimensional scaling) can also be used to analyze the total matrix of genetic distances (although they are converted to correlations) between a large number of populations with known allele frequencies based on some large number of genes. The most comprehensive study of population differences in allele frequencies to date is that of the Stanford University geneticist Luigi Luca Cavalli-Sforza and his co-workers.".' Their recent 1046-page hook reporting the detailed results of their study is a major contribution to the science of population genetics. The main analysis was based on blood and tissue specimens obtained from representative samples of forty-two populations, from every continent (and the Pacific islands) in the world. All the individuals in these samples were aboriginal OI indigenous to the areas in which they were selected samples; their ancestors have lived in the same geographic area since no later than 1492, a familiar date that generally marks the beginning of extensive worldwide European explorations and the consequent major population movements. In each of the Stanford study's population samples, the allele frequencies of 120 alleles at forty-nine gene loci were determined. Most of these genes determine various blood groups, enzymes, and proteins involved in the immune system, such as human lymphocyte antigens (HLA) and immunoglobulins. These data were then used to calculate the genetic distance (D) between each group and every other group. (DNA sequencing was also used in separate analyses of some groups; it yields finer genetic discrimination between certain groups than can the genetic polymorphisms used in the main analysis.) From the total matrix of (42 X 41)/2 = 861 D values, Cavalli-Sforza et al. constructed a genetic linkage tree. The D value between any two groups is represented graphically by the total length of the line that connects the groups in the branching tree. (Set Figure 12.1.) The greatest genetic distance, that is, the largest D, is between the five African groups (listed at the top of Figure 12.1) and all the other groups. The next largest D is between the Australian + New Guinean groups and the remaining other groups; the next largest split is between the South Asians + Pacific Islanders and all the remaining groups, and so on. The clusters at the lowest level (i.e., at far right in Figure 12.1) can also be clustered to show the D values between larger groupings, as in Figure 12.2. Note that these clusters product much the same picture as the traditional racial classifications that were based on skeletal characteristics and the many visible physical features by which nonspecialists distinguish "races."' It is noteworthy, but perhaps not too surprising, that the grouping of various human populations in terms of invisible genetic polymorphisms for many relatively ¦-------------------.---------------------------------San (Bushmen) ¦ ¦ __________________ Mbuli Pygmy ¦ ¦ ¦ __+------Bantu ¦ ¦---¦-------------------¦ ¦ -----Nilotic ¦ ¦---¦ ¦----¦------W African ¦ ¦------------------------- Ethiopian ¦ ¦---------------------SE Indian ¦ ¦------------¦ ¦-----------------Lapp ¦ ¦ ¦--¦ ¦--------------Berber ¦ ¦ ¦--¦ ¦-----------Sardinian ¦ ¦ ¦--¦ ¦----------Indian -¦ ¦ ¦--¦ ¦--------SW Asian ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦---+--Iranian ¦ ¦---¦ ¦--¦ ¦-Greek ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦__ ¦----Basque ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦--¦---Italian ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦-¦--Danish ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦-English ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦---------Samoyed ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦--------¦--------Mongol ¦ ----¦ ¦ ¦-------¦ .------Tibetan ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦------¦___¦--Korean ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦-----¦ ¦---¦ ¦--Japanese ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦-----------Ainu ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦-----------------------N. Turkic ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦---¦-------+_______ Eskimo ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦------------Chukchi ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦__¦ ¦------------S Amerind ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦-----+---¦---------C Amerind ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦---------¦ ¦------------ N Amerind ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦___________N.W. American ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦------¦----------S Chinese ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦--------¦--Mon Khymer ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦-¦ ¦--Thai ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦-----¦ ¦-----¦-------------Indonesian ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦_______Philipline ¦ ¦ ¦----------------¦ ¦------------------Malaysian ¦ ¦ ¦----¦---------------------Polynesian ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦---------------Micronesian ¦ ¦ ¦----+---------------------Melaesian ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦--------------------------------New Guinean ¦-----------¦----------¦___________________ Australian Genetic Distance---------------------------? Fig 12.11 Genetic Distance . The genetic linkage tree for forty-two populations. The genetic distance between any two groups is represented by the total length of the line separating them. (Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., Menozzi, P. & Piazza, A., The history and geography of human genes. Copyright @ 1994 by Princeton University Press. Reprinted by permission of Princeton University Press.) ¦------------------African ¦ ¦ ____¦----------- Caucasoid ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦ ¦---¦--North east Asia ¦ ¦---¦ ¦____¦ ¦--Arctic Asia ¦--------------------------------------¦ ¦ ¦___America ¦ ¦-------------------Southeast Asia ¦____________ New Guinea & Australia Fig. 12.2. A linkage tree based on the average genetic distances between the major clusters among the groups shown in Figure 12.1. (Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., Menozzi, P. & Piaza, A., T., The history and geography of human genes. Copyright @ 1994 by Princeton University African-Americans. The first Africans arrived in North America in 1619 and for more than two centuries thereafter, mostly between 1700 and 1800, the 432 majority of Africans were brought to America as slaves. The end to this involuntary migration came between 1863 and 1865, with the Emancipation Proclamation. Nearly all of the Africans who were enslaved came from sub-Sahara11 West Africa, specifically the coastal region from Senegal to Angola. The populations in this area are often called West African or North West and Central West Bantu.'"' Steadily over time, the real, but relatively low frequency of cross-mating between blacks and whites produced an infusion of Caucasoid genes into the black gene pool. As a result, the present-day population of black Americans is genetically different from the African populations from whom they descended. Virtually 100 percent of contemporary black Americans have some Caucasian ancestry. Most of the Caucasian genes in the present day gene pool of black Americans entered the black gene pool during the period of slavery. Estimates of the proportion of Caucasoid genes in American blacks are based on a number genetic polymorphisms that have fairly high allele frequencies in the European population but zero or near zero frequencies in the West African population. or vice versa. For any given allele, the estimated proportion (M) of white European ancestry in American blacks is obtained by the formula M =(qb - qaf)/(qw - qaf) where qb is the given allele's frequency in the black American population, qaf is its frequency in the African population, and q, is its frequency in the white European population. The average value of M is obtained over each of twenty or so genes with alleles that are unique either to Africans or to Europeans. The largest studies, which yield estimates with the greatest precision, p(Give mean values of M close to 25 percent, with a standard error of about 3percent. This is probably the best estimate for the African-American population overall. However, M varies across different regions of the United States, being as low as 4 percent to 10 percent in some southeastern States and spreading out in a fan-shaped gradient toward the north and the west to reach over 40 percent in some northeastern and northwestern states. Among the most typical and precise estimates of M are those for Oakland, California (22.0 percent) and Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania (25.2 percent). This regional variation in M reflects the pattern of selective migration of blacks from the Deep South since the mid-nineteenth century. Gene flow, of course, goes in both directions. In every generation there has been a small percentage of persons who have some African ancestry but whose ancestry is predominantly Caucasian and who permanently "pass as white." The white American gene pool therefore contains some genes that can be traced to Africans who were brought over as slaves (estimated by analysts of genetic polymorphisms to be less than 1 percent)."" Genetic Distance and Population Differences in g. The preceding discourse on the genetics of populations is germane to any discussion of population differences in g. The differences in gene frequencies that originally created different breeding populations largely explain the physical phenotypic differences observed between populations called races. Most of these differences in visible phenotypic characteristics are the result of natural selection working over the course of human evolution. Selection changes gene frequencies in a population by acting directly on any genetically based phenotypic variation that affects Darwinian fitness for a given environment. This applies not only to physical characteristics, but also to behavioral capacities, which are necessarily to some degree a function of underlying physical structures. Structure and function are intimately related, as their evolutionary origins are inseparable. The behavior-al capacities or traits that demonstrate genetic variation can also be viewed from an evolutionary perspective. Given the variation in allele frequencies between populations for virtually every known polymorphic gene, it is exceedingly improbable that populations do not differ in the alleles that affect the structural and functional basis of heritable behavioral traits. The empirical generalization that every polygenic physical characteristic that shows differences between individuals also shows mean differences between populations applies to behavioral as well as physical characteristics. Given the relative genetic distances between the major racial populations, one might expect some behavioral differences between Asians and Europeans to be of lesser magnitude than those between these groups and sub-Saharan Africans. . The behavioral, psychological, or mental characteristics that show the highest g loadings are the most heritable and have the most biological correlates (see Chapter 6) and are therefore the most likely to show genetic population differences . Because of the relative genetic distances, they are also the most likely to show such differences between Africans (including predominantly African descendants) and Caucasians or Asians. Of the approximately 100,000 human polymorphic genes, about 50,000 are functional in the brain and about 30,000 are unique to brain functions." The brain is by far the structurally and functionally most complex organ in the human body and the greater part of this complexity resides in the neural structures of the cerebral hemispheres, which, in humans, are much larger relative to total brain size than in any other species. A general principle of neural organization states that, within a given species, the size and complexity of a structure reflect the behavioral importance of that structure. The reason, again, is that structure and function have evolved conjointly as an integrated adaptive mechanism. But as there are only some 50,000 genes involved in the brain's development and there are at least 200 billion neurons and trillions of synaptic connections in the brain, it is clear that any single gene must influence some huge number of neurons not just any neurons selected at random, but complex systems of neurons organized to serve special functions related, to behavioral capacities. It is extremely improbable that the evolution of racial differences since the advent Homo Sapiens excluded allelic changes only in those 50,000 gents that are involved with the brain. Brain size has increased almost threefold during the course of human evolution, from about 500 cm' in the Australopithecenes to about 1,350 cm3 (the present estimated worldwide average) in Homo sapiens. Nearly all of this in 434 crease in brain volume has occurred in connection with those parts of the cerebral hemispheres associated with cognitive processes, particularly the prefrontal lobes and the posterior association areas, which control foresight, planning, goal directed behavior, and the integration of sensory information required for higher levels of information processing. The parts of the brain involved in vegetative and sensorimotor functions per se differ much less in size, relative to total brain size, even between humans and chimpanzees than do the parts of the brain that subserve cognitive functions. Moreover, most of the evolutionary increase in brain volume has resulted not from a uniform increase in the total number of cortical neurons per se, but from a much greater increase in the number and complexity of the interconnections between neurons, making possible a higher level of interneuronal communication on which complex information processing depends. Although the human brain is three times larger than the chimpanzee brain, it has only 1.25 times as many neurons; the much greater difference is in their degree of arborization, that is, their number of synapses and interconnecting branches. No other organ system has evolved as rapidly as the brain of Homo sapiens, a species that is unprecedented in this respect. Although in hominid evolution there was also an increase in general body size, it was not nearly as great as the increase in brain size. In humans, the correlation between individual differences in brain size and in stature is only about +.20. One minus the square of this relatively small correlation, which is .96, reflects the proportion of the total variance in brain size that cannot be accounted for by variation in overall body size. Much of this residual variance in brain size presumably involves cognitive functions. Bear in mind that, from the standpoint of natural selection, a larger brain size (and its corresponding larger head size) is its many ways decidedly disadvantageous. A large brain is metabolically very expensive, requiring a high calorie diet. Though the human brain is less than 2 percent of total body weight, it accounts for some 20 percent of the body's basal metabolic rate (BMR). In other primates, the brain accounts for about 10 percent of the BMR, and for most carnivores, less than 5 percent. A larger head also greatly increases the difficulty of giving birth and incurs much greater risk of perinatal trauma or even fetal death, which are much more frequent in humans than in any other animal species. A larger head also puts a greater strain on the skeletal and muscular support. Further, it increases the chances of being fatally hit by an enemy's club or missile. Despite such disadvantages of larger head size, the human brain, in fact, evolved markedly in size, with its cortical layer accommodating to a relatively lesser increase in head size by becoming highly convoluted in the endocranial vault. In the evolution of the brain, the effects of natural selection had to have reflected the net selective pressures that made an increase in brain size disadvantageous versus those that were advantageous. The advantages obviously outweighed the disadvantages to some degree or the increase in hominid brain size would not have occurred. I The only conceivable advantage to an increase in the size and complexity of the brain is the greater behavioral capacity this would confer. This would include: the integration of sensory information, fine hand-eye coordination, quickness of responding or voluntary response inhibition and delayed reaction depending on the circumstances, perceiving functional relationships between two things when only one or neither is physically present, connecting past and future events, learning from experience, generalization, far transfer of learning, imagery, intentionality and planning, short-term and long-term memory capacity, mentally manipulating objects without need to handle them physically, Foresight, problem solving, use of denotative language in vocal communication, as well as all of the information processes that are inferred from performance on what were referred to in Chapter 8 as "elementary cognitive tasks." These basic information processes are involved in coping with the natural exigencies and the contingencies of humans' environment. An increase in these capabilities and their functional efficiency are, in fact, associated with allometric differences in brain size between various species of animals, those with greater brain volume in relation to their overall body size generally displaying more of the kinds of capabilities listed above.1'31 The functional efficiency of the various behavioral capabilities that are common to all members of a given species can be enhanced differentially by natural selection, in the same way (though probably not to the same degree) that artificial selection has made dogs of various breeds differ in propensities and trainability for specific types of behavior.'" What kinds of' environmental pressures encountered by Homo erectus and early Homo sapiens would have selected for increased size and complexity of the brain? Evolutionists have proposed several plausible scenarios. Generally, a more complex brain would be advantageous in hunting skill, cooperative social interaction, and the development of tool use, followed by the higher-order skill of using tools to make other tools, a capacity possessed by no contemporary species other than Homo sapiens. The environmental forces that contributed to the differentiation of' major populations and their gene pools through natural selection were mainly climatic, but parasite avoidance and resistance were also instrumental. Homo sapiens evolved in Africa from earlier species of Homo that originated there. In migrating from Africa and into Europe and Asia, they encountered highly diverse climates. These migrants, like their parent population that remained in sub-Saharan Africa, were foragers, but they had to forage for sustenance under the highly different conditions of their climatically diverse habitats. Foraging was possible all during the year in the tropical and subtropical climates of equatorial regions, while in the more northern climate of Eurasia the abundance of food that could be obtained by hunting and gathering greatly fluctuated with the seasons. This necessitated the development of more sophisticated techniques for hunting large game, requiring vocal communication and cooperative efforts (e.g., by ambushing, trapping. or corralling), along with foresight in planning a head for the preservation, storage, and rationing of food in order to survive the severe winter 436 months when foraging is practically impossible. Extreme seasonal changes and the cold climate of the northern regions (now inhabited by Mongoloids and Caucasians) also demanded the ingenuity and skills for constructing more permanent and sturdy dwellings and designin,0 substantial clothing to protect against the elements. Whatever bodily and behavioral adaptive differences between populations were wrought by the contrasting conditions of the hot climate of sub-Saharan Africa and the cold seasons of northern Europe and northeast Asia would have been markedly intensified by the last glaciation, which occurred approximately 30,000 to 10,000 years ago, after Homo .sapiens had inhabited most of the globe. During this long period of time, large regions of the Northern Hemisphere were covered by ice and the north Eurasian winters were far more severe than they have ever been For over 10,000 years. It seems most plausible, therefore, that behavioral adaptations of a kind that could be described as complex mental abilities were more crucial for survival of the populations that migrated to the northern Eurasian regions, and were therefore under greater selection pressure as fitness characters, than in the populations that remained in tropical or subtropical regions."" Climate has also influenced the evolution of brain size apparently indirectly through its direct effect on head size, particularly the shape of the skull. Head size and shape are more related to climate than is the body as a whole. Because the human brain metabolizes 20 percent of the body's total energy supply, it generates more heat in relation to its size than any other organ. The resting rate of energy output of the average European adult male's brain is equal to about three-fourths that of a 100-watt light bulb. Because temperature changes in the brain of only four to five degrees Celsius are seriously adverse to the normal functioning of the brain, it must conserve heat (in a cold environment) or dissipate heat (in a hot environment). Simply in terms of solid geometry, a sphere contains a larger volume (or cubic capacity) for its total surface area than does than any other shape. Conversely, a given volume can be contained in a sphere that has a smaller surface area than can be contained by a nonspherical shape with the same surface area (an elongated oval shape, for instance). Since heat radiation takes place at the surface, more spherical shapes will radiate less heat and conserve more heat for a given volume than a nonspherical shape, and less spherical shapes will lose more heat by radiation. Applying these geometric principles to head size and shape, one would predict that natural selection would favor a smaller head with a less spherical (dolichocephalic) shape because of its better heat dissipation in hot climates, and would favor a more spherical (brachycephalic) head to accommodate a larger volume of brain matter with a smaller surface area because of its better heat conservation in cold climates. (The dolichocephalic-brachycephalic dimension is related to the head's width: Length ratio, known as the cephalic index.) In brief, a smaller, dolichocephalic cranium is advantageous for thermoregulation of the brain in a hot climate, whereas a larger, brachycephalic cranium is advantageous in a cold climate. In 437 the world's populations, head breadth is correlated about +.8 with cranial capacity; head length is correlated about +.4. Evidence that the average endocranial volume of various populations is related to cranial shape and that both phenomena are, in some part, adaptations to climatic conditions in different regions has been shown by physical anthropologist Kenneth Beals and his co-workers. i They amassed measurements of endocranial volume in modern humans from some 20,000 individual crania collected from every continent, representing 122 ethnically distinguishable populations. They found that the bglobal mean cranial capacity for populations in hot climates is 1,297 +- 10.5 cm'; for populations in cold and temperate climate it is 1,386 +- 6.7 cm', a highly significant (p < 10-4") difference of 89 cm'. Beals also plotted a correlation scatter diagram of the mean cranial capacity in cm' of each of 122 global populations as a function of their distance from the equator (in absolute degrees north or south latitude). The Pearson correlation between absolute distance from the equator and cranial capacity was r = +.62 p < l0-5). (The regression equation is: cranial capacity = 2.5 cm3 X Degrees latitude1 + 1257.3 cm': that is, an average increase of 2.5 cm' in cranial capacity for every 1 degree increase in latitude.) The same analysis applied to populations of the African-Eurasian landmass showed a cranial capacity X latitude correlation of +.76 (17 < 10-4) and a regression slope of 3.1 cm' increase in cranial capacity per every 1degree of absolute latitude in distance from the equator. The indigenous populations of North and South American continents show a correlation of +.44 and a regression slope of 1.5; the relationship of cranial capacity to latitude is less pronounced in the New World than in the Old World, probably because Homo Sapiens inhabited the New World much more recently, having migrated from Asia to North America only about 15,000 years ago, while Homo Sapiens have inhabited the African and Eurasian continents for a much longer period. Are the climatic factors associated with population differences in cranial capacity, as summarized in the preceding, section, reflected in the average cranial or brain-size measurements of the three broadest contemporary population groups, generally termed Caucasoid (Europeans and their descendants), Negroid (Africans and descendants), and Mongoloid (Northeast Asians and descendants)? A recent comprehensive review summarized the worldwide literature on brain volume in cm3 as determined from four kinds of measurements: (a) direct measurement of the brain obtained by autopsy, (b) direct measurement of endocranial volume of the skull, (c) cranial capacity estimated from external head measurements, and (d) cranial capacity estimated from head measurements and corrected for body size. The aggregation of data obtained by different methods, based on large samples, from a number of studies tends to average-out the sampling error and method effects and provides the best overall estimates of the racial group 438 Table 12.1 Mean Cranial Capacity (cm") of Three Racial Populations Determined from Four Types of Measurements Measurement East Asian European African Autopsy 1351 1356 1223 Endocranial volume 1415 1362 1268 External head measurements 1335 1341 1284 Corrected for body size 1356 1329 1294 Mean 1364 1347 1267 Source: Based on data summarized by Rushton & Ankney. 1996. Other evidence of a systematic relationship between racial differences in cranial capacity and IQ comes from an "ecological" correlation, which is commonly used in epidemiological research. It is simply the Pearson r between the means of three or mom defined groups, which disregards individual variation within the groups.Z" Referring back to Table 12.1, I have plotted the median IQ of each of the three populations as a function of the overall mean cranial capacity of each population. The median IQ is the median value of all of the mean values of IQ reported in the world literature for Mongoloid, Caucasoid, and Negroid populations. (The source of the cranial capacity means for each group was explained in connection with Table 12. 1 .) The result of this plot is shown in Figure 12.4. The regression of median IQ on mean cranial capacity is almost perfectly linear, with a Pearson r = +.998. Unless the data points in Figure 12.4 are themselves highly questionable, the near-perfect linearity of the regression indicates that IQ can be regarded as a true interval scale. No mathematical transformation of the IQ scale would have yielded a higher correlation. Thus it appears that the central tendency of IQ for different populations is quite accurately predicted by the central tendency of each population's cranial capacity. 110 ¦ ¦ . * m ¦ c . 100 ¦ . * ¦ . ¦ . 90 ¦ . ¦ . ¦ n . 80 ¦ . * ¦ ¦ 70 ¦ ------------------------------------------- 1250 1300 1350 1400 Cranial Capacity (cm') figure 12.4. Median IQ of three populations (Mongoloid, Caucasoid, and Negroid) plotted as a function of the mean cranial capacity in each population. (Regression: IQ = ,262 X cranial capacity- 252.6; r = ,998.) CONTROLLING THE ENVIRONMENT :TRANSRACIAL ADOPTION Theoretically, a transracial adoption study should provide a strong test of the default hypothesis. In reality, however. a real-life adoption study can hardly meet the ideal conditions necessary to make it definitive. Such conditions can be perfectly met only through the cross-fostering methods used in animal behavior genetics, in which probands can be randomly assigned to foster parents. Although adoption in infancy is probably the most comprehensive and powerful environmental intervention possible with humans, under natural conditions the adoption design is unavoidably problematic because the investigator cannot experimentally control the specific selective factors that affect transracial adoptions-the adopted children themselves, their biological parents, or the adopting parents. Prenatal and perinatal conditions and the preadoption environment are largely uncontrolled. So, too, is the willingness of parents to volunteer their adopted children for such a study, which introduces an ambiguous selection factor into the subject sampling of any adoption study. It is known that individuals who volunteer as subjects in studies that involve the measurement of mental ability generally tend to be somewhat above-average in ability. For these reasons, and given the scarcity of transracial adoptions, few such studies have been reported in the literature. Only one of these, known as the Minnesota Transracial Adoption Study, is based on large enough samples of black and white adoptees to permit statistical analysis. While even the Minnesota Study dots not meet the theoretically ideal conditions, it is nevertheless informative with respect to the default hypothesis. Initiated and conducted by Sandra Starr and several colleagues the Minnesota Transracial Adoption Study examined the same groups of children when they were about age 7 and again in a IO-year follow-up when they were about age 17. The follow-up study is especially important, because it has been found in other studies that family environmental influences on IQ decrease from early childhood to late adolescence, while there is a corresponding increase in the phenotypic expression of the 3Ocnetic component of IQ variance. Therefore, one would have more confidence in the follow-up data (obtained at age 17) as a test of the default hypothesis than in the data obtained at age 7. Four main groups were compared on IQ and scholastic performance: 1 Biological offspring of the white adoptive parents. 2. Adopted children whose biological father and mother were both white (WW). 3. Adopted interracial children whose biological fathers were black and whose mothers were white (BW). 4. Adopted children whose biological father and mother were both black (BB). (A group of twelve children, consisting of Asian and Amerindian adoptees who took part in both the first study and the follow-up, were not included in the main statistical analyses.) The adoptive parents were all upper-middle class, employed in proffesional and managerial occupations, with an average educational level of about sixteen years (college graduate) and an average WAIS IQ of about 120. The biological parents of the BB and BW adoptees averaged 11.5 years and 12.5 years of education, respectively. The IQs of the adoptees' biological parents were not known. Few of the adoptees ever lived with their biological parents; some lived briefly in foster homes before they were legally adopted. The average age of adoption was 32 months for the BB adoptees, 9 months for the BW adoptees, and 19 months for the WW adoptees. The adoptees came mostly from the North Central and North Eastern regions of the United States. The Stanford-Binet and the Wechsler Intelligence Scale for Children (WISC) were used in the first study (at age seven), the Wechler Adult Intelligence Scale (WAIS) was used in the follow-up study (at age seventeen).5z The investigators hypothesized that the typical W-B IQ difference results from the lesser relevance of the specific information content of IQ tests to the blacks' typical cultural environment. They therefore suggest that if black children were reared in a middle or upper-middle class white environment they would perform near the white average on IQ tests and in scholastic achievement. This cultural difference hypothesis therefore posits no genetic effect on the mean W-B IQ difference; rather, it assumes equal black and white means in genotypic g. The default hypothesis, on the other hand, posits both genetic and environmental factors as determinants of the mean W-B IQ difference. It therefore predicts that groups of black and white children reared in highly similar environments typical of the white middle-class culture would still differ in IQ to the extent expected from the heritability of IQ within either population. The data of the Minnesota Study also allow another prediction based on the default hypothesis, namely, that the interracial children (BW) should score, on average, nearly (but not necessarily exactly) halfway between the means of the WW and BB groups. Because the alleles that enhance IQ are genetically dominant, we would expect the BW group mean to be slightly closer to the mean of the WW group than to the mean of the BB group. That is, the heterosis (outbreeding enhancement of the trait) due to dominance deviation would raise the BW group's mean slightly above the midpoint between the BB and WW groups. (This halfway point would be the expected value if the heritability of IQ reflected only the effects of additive genetic variance.) Testing this predicted heterotic effect is unfortunately debased by the fact that the IQs of the biological parents of the BB and BW groups were not known. As the BB biological parents 474 Table 12.5 IQ Mean and Standard Deviation of Groups in the Minnesota Transracial Adoption Study Tested at Two Ages Group Age 7 Age 17 N Mean SD Mean SD Adoptive Father 74 121.7 9.5 117.1 11.5 Adoptive Mother 84 119.1 9.7 113.6 10.5 Biological Offspring 104 116.4 13.5 109.4 13.5 ---------------------------------------------------------------------------- ------------------------------------------------------ Adopted White (W/W) 16 117.6 11.3 105.6 14.9 Adopted Interracial(B/W) 55 109.5 11.9 98.5 10.6 Adopted Black (B/B) 21 95.4 13.3 89.4 11.7 "The number of individuals tested both in 1975 and 1986. Source: Data from Weinberg et al., 1992. had about one year less education than the BW parents, given the correlation between IQ and education, it is likely that the mean IQ of the BB parents was somewhat lower than the mean IQ of the BW parents, and so would produce a result similar to that predicted in terms of heterosis. It is also possible, though less likely, that the later age of adoption (by twenty-one months) of the BB adoptees than of the BW adoptees would produce an effect similar to that predicted in terms of heterosis. The results based on the subjects who were tested on both occasions are shown in Table 12.5. Because different tests based on different standardization groups were used in the first testing than were used in the follow-up testing, the overall average difference of about eight IQ points (evident for all groups) between the two test periods is of no theoretical importance for the hypothesis of interest. The only important comparisons are those between the WW, BW, and BB adopted groups within each age level. They show that: ??The biological offspring have about the same average IQ as has been reported for children of upper-middle-class parents. Their IQs are lower, on average than the average IQ of their parents, consistent with the expected genetic regression toward the population mean (mainly because of genetic dominance, which is known to affect IQ-see Chapter 7, pp. 189-91). The above-average environment of these adoptive families probably counteracts the predicted genetic regression effect to some extent, expectably more at age seven than at age seventeen. ??The BB adoptees' mean IQ is close to the mean IQ of ninety for blacks in the same North Central area (from which the BB adoptees came) reared by their own parents. At age seventeen the BB group's IQ is virtually identical to the mean IQ of blacks in the North Central part of the United States. Having been reared from two years of age in a white upper-middle-class environment has apparently had little or no effect on their expected IQ, that is, the average IQ of black children reared in the average black environment. This finding specifically contradicts the expectation of the cultural-difference explanation of the W-B IQ difference but is consistent with the default hypothesis. The BB group is more typical of the U.S. black population than is the BW group. The BB group's IQ at age seventeen is sixteen points below that of the whim adoptees and thirteen points below the mean IQ of whites in the national standardization sample of the WAIS. Thus the BB adoptees' IQ is not very different frown what would be expected if they were reared in the average environment of blacks in general (i.e. IQ eighty-five). The mean IQ of the interracial adoptees (BW), both at ages seven and seventeen, is nearly intermediate between the WW and BB adoptees, but falls slightly closer to the WW mean. This is consistent with, but does not prove, the predicted heterotic effect of outbreeding on IQ. The intermediate IQ at age seven is (WW + BB)/2 = (117.6 + 95.4)/2 = 106..5, or three points below the observed IQ of the BW group; at age seventeen the intermediate IQ is 97.5, or one point below the observed IQ of the BW group. Of course, mean deviations of this magnitude, given the sample sizes in this study, are not significant. Hence no conclusion can be drawn from these data regarding the predicted heterotic effect. But all of the group IQ means do differ significantly from one another, both at age seven and at age seventeen, and the fact that the BW adoptees are so nearly intermediate between the WW and BB groups is hard to explain in purely environmental or cultural terms. But it is fully consistent with the genetic prediction. An ad hoc explanation would have to argue for the existence of some cultural effects that quantitatively simulate the prediction of the default hypothesis, which is derived by simple arithmetic from accepted genetic theory. Results similar to those for IQ were also found for scholastic achievement measured at age seventeen, except that the groups differed slightly less on the scholastic achievement measures than on IQ. This is probably because the level of scholastic achievement is generally more susceptible to family influences than is the IQ. The mean scores based on the average of five measures of scholastic achievement and aptitude expressed on the same scale as the IQ (with l.t = 100, G = 15) were: Nonadopted biological offspring = 107.2, WW adoptees = 103. I, BW adoptees = 100. I, BB adoptees = 95.1. Again, the BW group's mean is but one point above the midpoint between the means of the WW and BB groups. In light of what has been learned from many other adoption studies, the results of this transracial adoption study are hardly surprising. As was noted in Chapter 7 (pp. 177-79) adoption studies have shown that the between-family (or shared) environment is the smallest component of true-score IQ variance by late adolescence. It is instructive to consider another adoption study by Starr and Weinberg,p57I based on nearly 200 white children who, in their first year of life, were adopted into 104 white families. Although the adoptive families ranged rather widely in socioeconomic status, by the time the adoptees were adolescents there were nonsignificant and near-zero correlations between the adoptees IQs and the characteristics of their adoptive families, such as the parents' education, IQ, occupation, and income. Starr and Weinberg concluded that, within the range of "humane environments," variations in family socioeconomic characteristics and in child-rearing practices have little or no effect on IQ measured in adolescence. Most "humane environments," they claimed, are functionally equivalent For the child's mental development. In the transracial adoption study, therefore, one would not expect that the large differences between the mean IQs of the WW, BW, and BB adoptees would have been mainly caused by differences in the unquestionably humane and well-above-average adoptive family environments in which these children grew up. Viewed in the context of adoption studies in which race is not a factor, the group differences observed in the transracial adoption study would be attributed to genetic factors. There is simply no good evidence that social environmental factors have a large effect on IQ, particularly in adolescence and beyond, except in cases of extreme environmental deprivation. In the Texas Adoption Study, for example, adoptees whose biological mothers had IQs of ninety-five or below were compared with adoptees whose biological mothers had IQs of 120 or above. Although these children were given up by their mothers in infancy and all were adopted into good homes, the two groups differed by 15.7 IQ points at age 7 years and by 19 IQ points at age 17. These mean differences, which are about one-half of the mean difference between the low-IQ and high-IQ biological mothers of these children, are close to what one would predict from a simple genetic model according to which the standardized regression of offspring on biological parents is .50. In still another study, Turkheimeris used a quite clever adoption design in which each of the adoptee probands was compared against two non adopted children, one who was reared in the same social class as the adopted proband's Biological mother, the other who was reared in the same social class as the proband's adoptive mother. (In all cases, the proband's biological mother was of lower SES than the adoptive mother.) This design would answer the question of whether a child born to a mother of lower SES background and adopted into a family of higher SES background would have an IQ that is closer to children who were born and reared in a lower SES background than to children born and reared in a higher SES background. The result: the proband adoptees' mean IQ was nearly the same as the mean IQ of the nonadopted children of mothers of lower SES background but differed significantly (by more than 0.50) from the mean IQ of the nonadopted children of mothers of higher SES background. In other words, the adopted probands, although reared by adoptive mothers of higher SES than that of the probands' biological mothers, turned out about the same with respect to IQ as if they had been reared by their biological mothers, who were of lower SES. Again, it appears that the family social environment has a surprisingly weak influence on IQ. This broad factor therefore would seem to carry little explanatory weight for the IQ differences between the WW, BW, and BB groups in the transracial adoption study. DECLARATION & DISCLAIMER ========== CTRL is a discussion and informational exchange list. Proselyzting propagandic screeds are not allowed. Substance—not soapboxing! These are sordid matters and 'conspiracy theory', with its many half-truths, misdirections and outright frauds is used politically by different groups with major and minor effects spread throughout the spectrum of time and thought. That being said, CTRL gives no endorsement to the validity of posts, and always suggests to readers; be wary of what you read. CTRL gives no credeence to Holocaust denial and nazi's need not apply. Let us please be civil and as always, Caveat Lector. ======================================================================== Archives Available at: http://home.ease.lsoft.com/archives/CTRL.html http:[EMAIL PROTECTED]/ ======================================================================== To subscribe to Conspiracy Theory Research List[CTRL] send email: SUBSCRIBE CTRL [to:] [EMAIL PROTECTED] To UNsubscribe to Conspiracy Theory Research List[CTRL] send email: SIGNOFF CTRL [to:] [EMAIL PROTECTED] Om