Maybe there should be criteria for evaluating criteria. For instance, FARCS doesn’t pass the laugh test.

I consulted my JoAnn Q. Citizen consultant.

I said, “I’m going to tell you two criterion definitions. They’re supposed to be very similar, but they don’t sound at all alike. Tell me which one makes you laugh harder.”

I told her the definitions of SDSC, and then Minimal Defense with FARCS. Well, I should say I _tried_ to tell her the definition of Minimal Defense with FARCS. I must admit she didn’t let me finish the FARCS definition.

Here’s what I old her, quoted reasonably accurately:
:
SDSC:

[quote]

If a majority of the voters prefer X to Y, then they should have a way of voting that ensures that Y won’t win, without any member of that majority having to vote a less-liked candidate equal to or over a more-liked one.

[unquote]

Then I told her about Minimal Defense with FARCS:

[quote]

If a majority of the voters rank X over Y, and don’t rank Y, then Y shouldn’t win.

Now, you might say, that only applies to rank methods. Oh no, you’re wrong. It can apply to nonrank methods too. For instance, it can apply to Pluralty. All we have to do is assume that the voters come to that Plurality election intending to vote rankings. Rankings that have, in first place, the candidate that the voter wants to vote for in the Plurality election.

You might ask why these voters, on their way to a Plurality election, are intending to vote rankings. We aren’t supposed to ask that. I don’t have to explain that to you.

Now, the actual use of a criterion is in writing a failure example, an example in which a method fails that criterion. The failure example writer can derive an actual ballot from a particular voter’s intended ranking as follows:

1. The actual ballot must not vote X over Y if the ranking ranks Y over X.

2. If the ranking ranks X over Y, then voting X over Y is “voting an ordering in the ranking”

The actual ballot must not fail to vote any ordering in the ranking that the balloting system in use would have allowed it to vote in addition to whatever orderings in the ranking it actually did vote.

[Note that I left out, for brevity, the definition of voting X over Y]

The example writer can contrive, for a particular voter, any actual ballot that complies with those two rules. If he can thereby write a ballot set that violates the criterion’s requirement, then he has found a failure example.

[unquote]

Actually, I didn’t get that far. When I was trying to tell her how the example writer can derive an actual vote from a ranking, she stopped me and said that no one wants to hear that.

Kevin and Chris can, of course, use FARCS criteria among themselves, or with others who are willing to listen to the definition of FARCS. But just try using them in a speech to political or reform activists. Well, looking on the bright side, it could be the beginning of your career in stand-up comedy.

“But the professors don’t like us to speak of preference. They prefer FARCS. They’re professors. Doesn’t that mean that they’re right and that we should follow them?

Now I’m not saying that this is really for sure the explanation, but voting system academics seem to be acting as if their goal were to obfuscate the subject. As if their goal were to never give you anything that you could take to the public without getting laughed or booed out of the room.

“But they’re professors. Don’t they know something we don’t?”

Yes, it would seem so. Maybe they know that they’re making a fool of anyone who trusts and follows them.

Mike Ossipoff


----
election-methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

Reply via email to