My previous message, attached below, didn't get to the Peirce list but only 
apparently to Ben Novak and Jerry Rhee.  The latest exchange, especially 
attacking Edwina for her personal beliefs about the EXISTENCE of God, i.e., the 
minority view of that small segment of the inhabitants of the 7th Rock from the 
Sun, does not interfere with her accepting the REALITY of THAT God, as Peirce 
apparently did.  But there is a persistent confusion on the part of those who 
apparently believe in the EXISTENCE of that God, which there is no evidence 
that Peirce ever did, with HIS REALITY.  Perhaps the list members might read 
Peirce's agreement, clearly  expressed on more than one occasion for his 
youthful friend, Francis E. Abbot's view on the matter.  Or of that of James, 
Dewey and Mead.

Harold L. Orbach

Sent from my iPhone

Begin forwarded message:

From: <h...@ksu.edu<mailto:h...@ksu.edu>>
Date: September 14, 2016 at 1:20:31 AM CDT
To: Ben Novak <trevriz...@gmail.com<mailto:trevriz...@gmail.com>>
Cc: Jerry Rhee <jerryr...@gmail.com<mailto:jerryr...@gmail.com>>, Peirce-L 
<peirce-L@list.iupui.edu<mailto:peirce-L@list.iupui.edu>>
Subject: Re: [PEIRCE-L] Peirce's Theory of Thinking

Pardon my intrusion into this unending mishmash:

1.  Peirce's neglected argument is for the REALITY of God  not  the EXISTENCE 
of God.

2. Anselm's ontological argument for the EXISTENCE of God is not "pretty nearly 
the most famous argument in the history of philosophy," only in the history of 
a small segment of the so-called WESTERN world, a minor part of the total areas 
and populations of what is termed "the earth" that came to dominate and 
"discover" most of the other areas for a few hundred years up to the present 
compared with other civilizations or empires that had dominance over larger and 
smaller areas for thousands of years.

3.  Other lands and peoples have and have had different views on the nature of 
God or Gods or Goddesses or if there are any that EXIST and how anyone might 
come to know this.  They also have and have had different kinds of "things" 
that were believed to be gods or sacred.

Harold L. Orbach
PhD, University of Minnesota Sociology, Philosophy, Psychology
Emeritus, Kansas State University
Sent from my iPhone

On Sep 13, 2016, at 10:32 PM, Ben Novak 
<trevriz...@gmail.com<mailto:trevriz...@gmail.com>> wrote:

Dear Jerry, List:

You ask two questions. First, what is Anselm's ontological argument. 
Thankfully, that is easy to answer. It is short, and I append it to this email 
at the end.

Your second question is why "you are imposing the question on us, which 
includes me [Jerry Rhee]?

First. let me clarify for the record: I am not from Missouri, and only used 
that phrase assuming everyone is familiar with it, in order to get to the "show 
me" part. Further, I do not know whether everyone in Missouri has heard of 
Anselm's ontological argument, though I assume not.

However, I would expect (silly me!) that anyone with a Ph.D. would have heard 
of it, since it is pretty nearly the most famous argument about God's existence 
in the history of philosophy, and would be expected to be brought up in any 
introductory, or history of, philosophy course or in any conversation or study 
anytime anyone questions whether God exists.

Further, since we are talking about Peirce's "Neglected Argument for the 
Reality of God," Anselm's argument would naturally come to mind as soon as 
anyone inquires into why Peirce thought his argument had been "neglected." In 
other words, the very title of Peirce's paper points to other arguments for 
God's existence in the context of which he is placing his. But it is worth 
noting that Peirce did not claim that he had a new argument, but suggests by 
his title that it may have arisen before and was merely "neglected." So he was 
bringing a long neglected argument back into view. At least I take that to be 
one possible interpretation of the suggestion in his title.(On the other hand, 
I take Peirce's title to imply that he felt his argument had been neglected 
because it was so simple!!!! that no one thought to dignify it previously. 
Silly me.)

Since the original questions that commenced this chain include "How exactly is 
"this theory of thinking" logically connected with "the hypothesis of God's 
reality"? I assumed that that was to be one of the major questions dealt with 
in the discussion, which Jon thought to begin by asking his four questions.

Now, the ontological argument has evoked a stupendous literature in philosophy 
and logic, because it seems to prove the existence of God by a purely logical 
and non-empirical method. That is why it is called ontological, i.e., the 
argument proceeds only from being (onto=being).  Philosophers agree that Anselm 
makes at least two different arguments in chapters II and III, though some 
philosophers find three and even four separate arguments. Many logicians have 
wrestled with it, and some logicians see it as a "modal" argument.

The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy gives a very brief and readable 
description of Anselm's ontological argument: Be sure  to read sections 1, 2a, 
3, and 4.

http://www.iep.utm.edu/ont-arg/

I hope that you will agree, after reading the brief account in the link above 
that Anselm is quite relevant to placing Peirce's "neglected" argument into 
context. The connection is that both Anselm and Peirce seek to prove God's 
existence purely from a thought process.

Now, if you want to read a different take on Anselm's understanding of what is 
meant by "existence," I invite you to read my article entitled "Anselm on 
Nothing," in the International Philosophical Quarterly, Volume 48, Issue 3, 
September 2008, pages 305-320, which you may read on line here:

https://www.academia.edu/13891780/Anselm_on_Nothing

For this second link, it must be borne in mind that Anselm wrote two tracts 
relating to God's existence (or being), and the first link deals with his 
second work, the Proslogion, where his famous ontological argument is found 
(appended below), while the second link (my article) deals mostly with Anselm's 
arguments in his first work, the Monologion. (Understand, too, that my views 
though increasingly cited are nevertheless minority.)

Understand too that Peirce's works were constantly on my mind throughout 
writing "Anselm on Nothing," and that I planned to write a second article on 
Peirce and Anselm, but was largely discouraged from doing so by the realization 
that Peirceans would disagree with just about everything a simple person like 
me would say about Peirce's thought---which is why I was so excited when Jon 
posted his questions that began this chain.For example, I thought the example I 
gave of simple firstness, secondness, and thirdness was safe, but I received a 
private email from an observer of this list that such is not the case:

Echoing others, the Firstness-Secondness-Thirdness ordering in your example is 
too linear. It should be Firstness-Thirdness-Secondness. That is, some shock 
meets your habitual conditioning which determines the reaction. How else could 
we have different reactions?

So, I need a lot of enlightenment, which is why I appreciate this forum so much.

In any event, appended below are Chapters II, III, and IV of the Proslogion, 
which contains Anselm's famous ontological argument;


Ben
Chapter II

Therefore, O Lord, who grantest to faith understanding, grant unto me that, so 
far as Thou knowest it to be expedient for me, I may understand that Thou art, 
as we believe; and also that Thou art what we believe Thee to be. And of a 
truth we believe that Thou art somewhat than which no greater can be conceived. 
Is there then nothing real that can be thus described? for the fool hath said 
in his heart, There is no God. Yet surely even that fool himself when he hears 
me speak of somewhat than which nothing greater can be conceived under stands 
what he hears, and what he understands is in his understanding, even if he do 
not under stand that it really exists. It is one thing for a thing to be in the 
understanding, and another to understand that the thing really exists. For when 
a painter considers the work which he is to make, he has it indeed in his 
understanding; but he doth not yet understand that really to exist which as yet 
he has not made. But when he has painted his picture, then he both has the 
picture in his understanding, and also under stands it really to exist. Thus 
even the fool is certain that something exists, at least in his understanding, 
than which nothing greater can be conceived; because, when he hears this 
mentioned, he understands it, and whatsoever is understood, exists in the 
understanding. And surely that than which no greater can be conceived cannot 
exist only in the understanding. For if it exist indeed in the understanding 
only, it can be thought to exist also in reality; and real existence is more 
than existence in the under standing only. If then that than which no greater 
can be conceived exists in the understanding only, then that than which no 
greater can be conceived is something a greater than which can be conceived: 
but this is impossible. There fore it is certain that something than which no 
greater can be conceived exists both in the under standing and also in reality.

Chapter II

Not only does this something than which no greater can be conceived exist, but 
it exists in so true a sense that it cannot even be conceived not to exist. For 
it is possible to form the conception of an object whose non-existence shall be 
inconceivable; and such an object is of necessity greater than any object whose 
existence is conceivable: wherefore if that than which no greater can be 
conceived can be conceived not to exist; it follows that that than which no 
greater can be conceived is not that than which no greater can be conceived 
[for there can be thought a greater than it, namely, an object whose 
non-existence shall be inconceivable]; and this brings us to a contradiction. 
And thus it is proved that that thing than which no greater can be conceived 
exists in so true a sense, that it cannot even be conceived not to exist: and 
this thing art Thou, O Lord our God! And so Thou, O Lord my God, existest in so 
true a sense that Thou canst not even be conceived not to exist. And this is as 
is fitting. For if any mind could conceive aught better than Thee, then the 
creature would be ascending above the Creator, and judging the Creator; which 
is a supposition very absurd. Thou therefore dost exist in a truer sense than 
all else beside Thee, and art more real than all else beside Thee; because 
whatsoever else existeth, existeth in a less true sense than Thou, and 
therefore is less real than Thou. Why then said the fool in his heart, There is 
no God, when it is so plain to a rational mind that Thou art more real than any 
thing else? Why, except that he is a fool indeed?

Chapter IV

But how came the fool to say in his heart that which he could not conceive? or 
how came he to be able not to conceive that which yet he said in his heart? For 
it may be thought that to conceive and to say in one’s heart are one and the 
same thing. If it is true—nay, because it is true, that he conceived it, 
because he said it in his heart; and also true that he did not say it in his 
heart because he could not conceive it; it follows that there are two senses in 
which something may be understood to be conceived or said in the heart. For in 
one sense we are said to have a conception of something, when we have a 
conception of the word that signifies it; and in another sense, when we 
understand what the thing really is. In the former sense then we may say that 
God is conceived not to exist: but in the latter, He cannot by any means be 
conceived not to exist. For no man that understandeth what fire and water mean, 
can conceive that fire is really water; though he may have this conception, as 
far as the words go. Thus in like manner no man that understandeth what God is 
can conceive that God does not exist; although he may say these words [that God 
does not exist] either with no meaning at all, or with some other meaning than 
that which they properly bear. For God is that than which no greater can be 
conceived. He who well under standeth what this is, certainly understandeth it 
to be such as cannot even be conceived not to exist. Whosoever therefore 
understandeth in this way that God exists, cannot conceive that he does not 
exist. Thanks be to Thee, O good Lord, thanks be to Thee! because that which 
heretofore I believed by Thy grace, I now by Thine illumination thus 
understand, so that, even though I should not wish to believe in Thine 
existence, I cannot but understand that Thou dost exist.







Ben Novak<http://bennovak.net>
5129 Taylor Drive, Ave Maria, FL 34142
Telephone: (814) 808-5702

"All art is mortal, not merely the individual artifacts, but the arts 
themselves. One day the last portrait of Rembrandt and the last bar of Mozart 
will have ceased to be—though possibly a colored canvas and a sheet of notes 
may remain—because the last eye and the last ear accessible to their message 
will have gone." Oswald Spengler

On Tue, Sep 13, 2016 at 5:11 PM, Jerry Rhee 
<jerryr...@gmail.com<mailto:jerryr...@gmail.com>> wrote:
Ben,

What is Anselm's ontological argument, for it is my opinion that someone from 
Missouri is expected to know it.

If I, being from Missouri, is not expected to know about Anselm's ontological 
argument, then why are you imposing the question on us, which includes me?

Best,
Jerry R

On Tue, Sep 13, 2016 at 3:05 PM, Ben Novak 
<trevriz...@gmail.com<mailto:trevriz...@gmail.com>> wrote:
Dear Jon Alan Schmidt:

I would like to go back to the point that this chain of emails began. Jon Alan 
Schmidt asked about something he found Peirce had said in the Neglected 
Argument, which had been omitted in the version published in the Essential 
Peirce:


CSP:  Among the many pertinent considerations which have been crowded out of 
this article, I may just mention that it could have been shown that the 
hypothesis of God's Reality is logically not so isolated a conclusion as it may 
seem.  On the contrary, it is connected so with a theory of the nature of 
thinking that if this be proved so is that.  Now there is no such difficulty in 
tracing experiential consequences of this theory of thinking as there are in 
attempting directly to trace out other consequences of God's reality.

Jon said that raised "a few interesting questions," namely:

  1.  To what specifically was Peirce referring here as "a theory of the nature 
of thinking"--the three stages of a "complete inquiry" and their "logical 
validity," as laid out in sections III and IV of the paper, or something else?
  2.  How exactly is "this theory of thinking" logically connected with "the 
hypothesis of God's reality"?
  3.  What would be some "experiential consequences of this theory of thinking" 
that we could, with comparatively little difficulty, deductively trace and 
inductively test?
  4.  What exactly would it mean to "prove" Peirce's "theory of the nature of 
thinking," such that "the hypothesis of God's reality" would thereby also be 
"proved"?

I have some tentative thoughts about these matters, including a couple of ideas 
that I found in the secondary literature, but would appreciate seeing what 
others have to say initially.

So, let me respond.

I thought I understood firstness, secondness, and thirdness when  our 
discussion began. This is the example I had in mind.  I am a student sitting in 
a class listening to an interesting lecture, when suddenly an explosion occurs. 
It could be a firecracker under behind the professor's desk, or a truck wreck 
on the street right outside the classroom windows. The sound of true explosion, 
whatever it is, is  sudden, unexpected, and immediate.  The sound or other 
shock waves hitting my body constitute firstness--I feel them. Secondness is 
what my body does in reaction, which is to  immediately and involuntarily, 
raise my head, flinch, and commence other bodily reactions to the explosion 
waves reaching me. Thirdness occurs next, when my mind begins to wonder what 
just happened. All this  can happen in far less than the blink of an eye.  
Peirce's analysis of it by breaking it down in this way was thought to be a 
fertile way of beginning to understand thinking, or to begin a theory of 
thinking.

Please correct me again, Jon, if that is not an elementary example of 
firstness, etc.

However, I soon got lost in the subsequent discussion of these, where thirdness 
became intertwined with secondness and firstness, and so on, in the subsequent 
emails.  I do  not doubt that all of you are correct that Peirce did take this 
rudimentary example to far heights of thinking which I may just be 
constitutionally unable to rise to. But my reading of Peirce suggests that he 
was a very pragmatic person who appreciated someone from Missouri showing up 
and saying "show me." In any event, so much of the subsequent discussion 
involved concepts going back and forth with no examples that allowed them to be 
brought to earth for examination. At least, that is what it seemed to me.

So, is it possible to get back to the original question. Remember that Peirce 
thought that all this became clear to him his daily walks through the woods, 
and he wrote this essay suggesting that its thinking would be available to 
anyone of ordinary intelligence who pondered the three universes suggested on 
their own daily walks through the woods.

So, let's go back to Jon's 2nd, 3rd, and 4th questions, because I think he  is 
on to something:

  1.  How exactly is "this theory of thinking" logically connected with "the 
hypothesis of God's reality"?
  2.  What would be some "experiential consequences of this theory of thinking" 
that we could, with comparatively little difficulty, deductively trace and 
inductively test?
  3.  What exactly would it mean to "prove" Peirce's "theory of the nature of 
thinking," such that "the hypothesis of God's reality" would thereby also be 
"proved"?

In response, some raised the ontological argument of St. Anselm. But the 
raising of it was not followed through. Here is my question (which I hope 
"nests" all three of Jon's questions):

What would Anselm's ontological argument look like if it were restated in 
Peirce's terms? In other words, could Anselm have discovered the same argument 
as Peirce? Would this give us any insight into the theory of thinking? Peirce 
says that we could, with comparatively little difficulty, deductively and 
inductively test such a theory of thinking. Someone from Missouri might say, 
"Show me."

Ben Novak




Ben Novak<http://bennovak.net>
5129 Taylor Drive, Ave Maria, FL 34142
Telephone: (814) 808-5702<tel:%28814%29%20808-5702>

"All art is mortal, not merely the individual artifacts, but the arts 
themselves. One day the last portrait of Rembrandt and the last bar of Mozart 
will have ceased to be—though possibly a colored canvas and a sheet of notes 
may remain—because the last eye and the last ear accessible to their message 
will have gone." Oswald Spengler

On Tue, Sep 13, 2016 at 12:34 PM, Clark Goble 
<cl...@lextek.com<mailto:cl...@lextek.com>> wrote:

On 9/13/2016 3:29 AM, John Collier wrote:
I used Peirce’s ideas fairly prominently in my philosophy of science courses in 
the 1980s and 90s. I also used his work to cast light on Kuhnian issues both in 
my classes and in my doctoral dissertation. Although the last was accepted 
enthusiastically, I continually got grumblings about how  was not teaching the 
Standard View properly.

Maybe things have improved, with more naturalistic approaches becoming more 
prevalent, but the culture wars really made a mess of trying to bring in 
Peircean ideas because the view that science was a mere social construct seemed 
to be supported by naïve interpretations of Peirce. So I found myself 
apparently fighting myself at some times.

Yes, the culture wars (which are still with us) are rather annoying. Not just 
because of how they try to make science into something we can control and 
thereby reject but because of how often they just read philosophers so badly. 
Lots of figures who make more careful subtle distinctions about science’s 
social aspects are appropriated for tasks they’d be aghast at. (Kuhn is the 
classic example although it’s not hard to find others)


-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to 
peirce-L@list.iupui.edu<mailto:peirce-L@list.iupui.edu> . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send 
a message not to PEIRCE-L but to 
l...@list.iupui.edu<mailto:l...@list.iupui.edu> with the line "UNSubscribe 
PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .








-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to 
peirce-L@list.iupui.edu<mailto:peirce-L@list.iupui.edu> . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send 
a message not to PEIRCE-L but to 
l...@list.iupui.edu<mailto:l...@list.iupui.edu> with the line "UNSubscribe 
PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .








-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to 
peirce-L@list.iupui.edu<mailto:peirce-L@list.iupui.edu> . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send 
a message not to PEIRCE-L but to 
l...@list.iupui.edu<mailto:l...@list.iupui.edu> with the line "UNSubscribe 
PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to