> "The capitalist, as representative of capital engaged in its valorisation
process - productive capital - performs a productive function, which
consists precisely in directing and exploiting productive labour.

Marx distinguishes in the manuscripts of Das Kapital between what he calls
the "functioning capitalist" or entrepreneur and coupon clippers, and he
regards the technical organisation and coordination of production as a
productive force.

Thus, for Marx, the management function was always a two-edged issue; a
technical division of work between "thinkers" and "doers" or between
"co-ordinating" and "executive" functions was often technically necessary
for productive efficiency (we cannot all do everything, and must co-operate
to maximise results), but this technical division of work (specialisation)
was interlaced with a social division of work, which had nothing to do with
any technical requirements, but rather with power-relations and the private
appropriation of net profits.

In the personality structure of the individual, these two sides are combined
in the concept of "responsibility", which denotes both technical skill and a
personal moral development enabling leadership in organising people to do
things, i.e. a degree of self-management or self-determination, which
enables the management of others. However, the concept of responsibility in
civil society is not "neutral", but has an inevitable moral-political
dimension, because of structural class conflict and competition in
capitalist society among employers, between employers and employees, and
between employees.

Since, however, under capitalism the economising of work is subordinated to
the imperative of realising and privately appropriating the maximum possible
surplus-values through market sales, as net income, it frequently becomes
difficult to distinguish clearly between "technically indispensable"
specialisations, and modes of organising production which owe their
characteristics mainly to the imperative of the private appropriation of
wealth, or to power relations deriving from the ownership and control of
private or publicly owned assets.

That is to say, "market competition" can be as much a constraint on the
development of the productive powers of creative human work as an incentive
or stimulus to develop them further, and this creates new categories in the
division of work, exclusively concerned with the defence and realisation of
surplus-values, as net income entitlements. I am using the term "creative
human work" in the broad cultural sense - i.e. human culture includes
everything humans have made, in contrast to that provided by nature. A
bricklayer "creates" just as much as an artist does, he creates pavements
instead of sculptures maybe, but it is creative work anyhow.

I also use the expression "private appropriation of net profits"
deliberately, since this appropriation is as much a question of relations of
production (ownership entitlements) as of relations of distribution (access
entitlements to functions and occupations which permit this appropriation,
and functions concerned with the realisation of surplus-values in trading).
"Professionalisation" processes in capitalist society can show similarities
to the medieval guild system, i.e. rules of inclusion and exclusion are
enforced which (1) protect incomes, (2) prevent certain social classes from
entry into occupations, and thus from certain types of income entitlements.
"Free markets" such as envisaged in Marx's model of a purified capitalism
are hypothetical, basically a bourgeois myth, the question is really more
how exactly markets are regulated (i.e. what legal and enforcement rules
apply).

Simply put, the thought of Aristotle and Plato was based on slave-labour,
without which they would not have had the time to philosophise.
Nevertheless, part of the thought of Aristotle and Plato proved of enduring
value, so much so, that we still refer to their ideas today. The fact that
we do so, does not constitute a justification of slave labour. But it does
affirm that such a mental-manual division of labour could produce
constructive results, whatever the oppression, which could not be have been
achieved if everybody had to do everything it takes to survive for himself.
Naturally, the rich and the tyrants will always argue slaves are necessary,
and they will justify that e.g. by saying that some people are just stupid
or defective, they haven't got what it takes, or they just want to be
slaves. But socialists think that stupidity or intelligence is something
that humans produce or reduce, rather than something which is just natural.
It's a result of civilisation and emancipation processes.

The more pertinent conclusion to draw, is that the achievement of human
progress depends crucially on teamwork, on cooperation. When bourgeois
ideologues extol the virtues of competition, they don't know what they are
talking about. Because to engage in private competition at all, already
presupposes an enormous amount of co-operation between people, a lot of it
unpaid (for example, female "labour of love", and spying by the rich, to
obtain knowledge without paying for it; as I have said previously,
capitalism and class society is always based on getting something for
nothing, and hence people must be forced into a specific understanding and
validation of human love).

What Marx regarded as ultimately the progressive characteristic of
marketisation, was the objective socialisation of production, even if this
is not yet institutionally acknowledged as socialism. In other words, the
internationalisation of trading relations creates a complex network and
infrastructure of human interdependencies and connections, that forms the
basis of the next step in human evolution, unless the infrastructure for it
is destroyed through wars.

The interpretation of management just mentioned reflected Marx's concept of
the "social surplus product" as being both (1) technically, the social
accumulation fund or investment fund necessary in any type of society as the
source of expanded reproduction (economic growth) and (2) socially, a
surplus appropriated by the ruling classes as gross income by virtue of
ownership entitlements (under capitalism, an appropriation of private
profit). I.e., it involves both a technical relationship and a class
relationship, such that the magnitude of the surplus product depends not
just on the productivity of work, given tools & technology, but also on a
class relationship and ownership relations, enforcing a specific division of
the new incomes generated from production and trade between social classes
(this concept is discussed at length in E. Mandel, Marxist Economic Theory).

Marx (and subsequently N. Bukharin, R. Luxemburg and P. Baran) then judged
the relative historical "progressiveness" of the elites in terms of what
they actually did with the surplus, i.e. what part was re-invested to
develop the productive or destructive forces, and what part was consumed,
and how it was consumed or squandered. This is a theme in Marx's discussion
of the "reconversion of surplus-values into capital" upon realisation, which
is not simply a question of relative profitability, but also of the
political-cultural predilections and circumstances of the owning classes,
who have their own culture, human concerns and political stance.

Implicitly, Marx suggests that by enabling a clear distinction between
production of output as such, and the accumulation of private capital, the
capitalist mode of production for the first time in history clarifies very
precisely the economic principles of the economising of work involved,
principles which in previous modes of production could not be so clearly
specified, among other things because "the economy" did not exist as a
distinct and separate sphere of civil society or in social ideology. It does
so (1) by objectifying economic relations as market relations, expressed in
money-prices, and (2) through a process of specialisation, which
increasingly separates out production functions and transactional functions,
clearly defining them as the exclusive function of different people.

Indeed, part of the "alienation of work" consists in the fact that a job as
a narrow specialisation cannot express all that one is, it is frequently
impossible to express or realise one's individual nature in work, and work
defines or shapes personal identity less and less, regardless of the issue
of whether that's good or bad. This is, for Marx, a result of the imbalanced
development of humankind, which the rather anarchic, competitive,
capitalistically regulated world market promotes: higher human needs are
cultivated which go beyond the social framework in which they can be
satisfactorily met, while more basic needs are not met at all,  i.e.
superdevelopment here, combines with underdevelopment there, to the point
where humans in different areas of the world can scarcely recognise each
other as "human" anymore, because their levels of personal development are
so far apart.

The movement towards communism is essentially a process of the
transformation of the division of work inherited from the past, according to
new allocative principles, emphasising balanced human development,
satisfaction of the basic structure of human needs, egalitarianism and an
open society, stewardship of the biosphere which is the basis of life, and
the maximisation of human freedom (not just freedom from constraints, but
freedom expressed such that it frees others, as well as oneself). The
process starts at the personal level, with the will to break with narrow
capitalistic depictions of economic rationality, and culminates at the
organised social-political level, with a better stewardship of resources
according to goals of human development, rather than narrow self-enrichment
at the expense of others. This requires increasing the responsibility level
of the proletariat and the peasantry in the defined way.

Let's just have a brief look at the structure of the total population of US
capitalist society in 2002, in approximate figures showing different broad
occupational categories, ranked according to the number of people in them
(this does not pretend to be a completely scientifically exact analysis, I'm
not paid to do that). Then you can better understand and question for
yourself, which and how much of those categories are really technically
necessary or inevitable, to economise optimal human development, and which
categories are more just a product of the existence of social classes,
private accumulation of capital, and the market allocation of resources.
First of all, let us derive the basic employment categories in approximate
figures:

American total resident population 288 million
population (16+) 224 million
economically active population 218 million
total civilian non-institutional population (16+) 215 million

population 16-65 years 188 million

civilian labour force in 2002 = 145 million

employed civilian labour force 137 million

Unpaid family workers 0.03 million

employers 10 million (4.9 million distinct firms, 7 million establishments)

self-employed (farm) 1 million

selfemployed (non-farm) 9 million

wage & salary earners 136 million

employees 127 million

government employees 20 million

private sector workforce 105 million

Parttime workers non-farm 27 million

Parttime workers farm 0.5 million

private sector waged employees 95 million

unionised wage earners   18 million


Now let's look at the proportions of what this total American population
actually does, in approximate figures, basic categories (somebody can do the
figures more exactly than I can):

Children (under 16, not working for pay) 64 million
Retired (over 65, not in the labour force) 28 million
Fulltime housewives, house-husbands and idle not working for pay 22 million
Industrial production workers 26.2 million
Managers and executives 15.8 million
Clerical and administrative workers 15.3 million
Sales workers 15 million
Reserve army of unemployed 13 million
Engineers, architects, technicians, programmers and scientists 10.5 million
Employers of workers, all kinds 9.8 million
Supervisors of workers, all kinds 9.1 million
Teachers, professional childcare workers and paid childcare assistants 8
million
Transport workers 5 million
Unskilled labourers, handlers and helpers  4.8 million
Aides, ushers, guides, orderlies, and attendants 4.8 million
Personal care, health and medical workers 4.3 million
Cleaners, janitors, private cooks, maids & housekeepers 3.7 million
Accountants, auditors, underwriters, and financial officers 2.6 million
Adults in institutional care n.e.c. 2.5 million
Specialists & consultants in human resources, PR and labour relations  2.1
million
Prison & jail inmates 2 million
Artists, entertainers & designers, photographers, professional athletes,
recreational services 1.6 million
Nursing home residents 1.6 million
Fulltime criminals and lumpenised, not in corrective institutions 1.5
million
Lawyers, judges and legal assistants 1.3 million
Therapists, counselors, social workers and welfare service aides 1.2 million
Police, detective, and law enforcement officers 1.2 million
Medical doctors, dentists, vetinarians, optometrists, and podiatrists 1.1
million
Military personnel, domestic 1.1 million
Groundskeepers, gardeners, animal caretakers (non-farm) 1.1 million
Security guards   1 million
Farmers 1 million
Prostitutes 1 million
Working children (under 16) 1 million
Inspectors (construction, production and compliance) 0.9 million
Editors, writers, reporters, proofreaders, librarians, archivists, and
curators 0.6 million
Adult hospital patients 0.5 million
Religious clergy, and employees of religious institutions 0.4 million
Corrective institution & prison officers 0.3 million
Firefighting, fire prevention and pest control workers 0.3 million
Water, sewage and electricity workers 0.2 million
Hospice inpatients 0.1 million
Adult psychiatric patients 0.2 million



(for a sociological discussion of the theoretical need to develop concepts
in order to move towards making an analysis of the division of labour in the
future, see http://itsa.ucsf.edu/~eliotf/Conceiving_of_Divisions_of.html ).


In Marx's lifetime, the "joint-stock company" wasn't as widespread as it is
today, i.e. the division between the actual direction of production and the
ownership of the private assets that give entitlement to profit income,
creating a long "chain" of claimants to profit income, from those who
control the productive assets, to those who are far removed from the
process, just wasn't so extensive. I have previously posted on PEN-L an
example of the nickel industry, where it's clear, that there is a division
in the owning classes participating in that industry, between "functioning
capitalists", money-managers and coupon-clippers far removed from the scene.

As regards the discussion about the law of value in China, the Chinese are
primarily interested in transcending material poverty in their country, and
who can blame them. So they look at economics, primarily from the point of
view of the efficiency and effectiveness of production of new wealth, and
the maximisation of output that can satisfy consumer needs.

To the extent that they have opted for capitalist methods, this has a lot to
do with (1) their dependence on superior production technologies developed
outside China, (2) pressures from the world market and the capitalist class,
(3) the cultural development of the Chinese masses, and (4) with
bureaucratic excesses, due to a monopolisation of power by the CCP. In the
1980s, this led to the abandonment of the "iron rice bowl" and the
introduction of the "responsibility system", rather than far-reaching
socialist democratisation of civil society. In other words, a narrow view of
material and moral incentives was adopted. The "cultural revolution" had
attempted to abolish the division of labour by sending intellectuals and
artists into the countryside, but that obviously didn't work, even if some
people benefited from getting their hands dirty with some manual work.

Responsibility can of course be encouraged in various ways - through the
incentive of private income entitlement resulting from privately-held
assets, through systems of efficient majority rule, through culture wars
which develop the independent, self-acting powers of human beings, and so
on. It's very much a political question, and not just a cultural or economic
question - morality spans all these spheres.  I already referred to the
ambiguity of the concept of responsibility: it combines both technical
ability to manage and moral-political ability to manage, in other words,
self-management and management of others are things which must develop
together, and then the question is, what the best ways of encouraging that
are, and what the obstacles to that are. It is easy to bury that discussion
in a pile of ideological nonsense.

Bureaucratic excesses (red tape, repression, arbitrariness) create
demoralisation, and a lack of incentive or motivation for creative work that
improves human wellbeing, a lack of individual initiative and
entrepreneurial capacity, and then people think capitalist methods are the
only alternative, which of course isn't true, that is really more a question
of power relations and politics. Capitalism is just as good at stifling
individual initiative, because initiative is only allowed if it is
compatible with capital accumulation, and doesn't detract too much from it.
Women's voluntary labour usually isn't counted as "initiative".

Bureaucracies are basically constituted either on the basis of a monopolised
asset ownership, or a legally or a religiously constituted monopoly of
legislative and executive power, and usually this involves control over
communication and information. In some cases, capitalists methods may be the
only alternative, even simply just to break through bureaucratic jungles and
restore a rationally allocated responsibility in individuals, but, the
advantage of the Chinese system, in which the state regulates the economy,
is that at least it permits experimentation with different allocative
methods, to see what works best (cf. Makoto Itoh, Political Economy of
Socialism).

The question in China is really whether the issues of alternative allocative
methods can be intelligently discussed, or whether this discussion is
brutally repressed, and for this, some kind of democracy or free expression
is obviously necessary. If you cannot even discuss a problem, then you are
unlikely to be able solve it either, in most cases, precisely because you
have to co-operate to do it, and you cannot do that very well, if people
make you dumb and deaf. However, Westerners often operate with a fake
concept of Chinese democracy as well, their democracy is different from
ours, and our own democracy is in some respects less meaningful than theirs.
Democratic rhetoric from businessmen is usually a call for freedom for
self-enrichment at the expense of others. Thus, democracy is good if it
enriches one-self, anything that doesn't, is "undemocratic".

The problematic of bureaucratisation was extensively discussed by European
socialists and Marxists (see Catherine Samary's useful summary, Plan, Market
& Democracy, an IIRE Notebook, not cited by Makoto Itoh). Economic
rationality resulting from bureaucratisation can be far worse, than economic
irrationality resulting from market economy, but this discussion cannot be
separated from the politics of social classes and their interests, and if it
is, then no clear conclusions can be drawn, because the
biophysical-technical-scientific problems of economising resources, and the
social-political problems involving conflicts of class and sectional
interests are confused with each other.

Alec Nove correctly pointed out that "workers democracy" is not the perfect
vaccination against bureaucracy that Marxists often think it is. To operate
democracy again requires administration and a technology. The real problem
is different: it concerns the invention of modes of mass participation,
which really work well, and are efficient. This requires a combination of
different sciences - decisions must always be made at an appropriate level,
i.e. you don't normally require a parliament to design a bus timetable, that
decision has to be made by bus workers. It's a question of efficiently
allocating the making of decisions concerning the management of society's
resources. Decisionmaking processes in capitalist society which work well
should be kept, those that are inefficient and ineffective should be
replaced.

What is often ignored in public discussion is that in capitalist society,
bureaucracy is a far bigger problem in private enterprise than in
government, and we can illustrate this, by noting that out of a total number
of about 15.3 million clerical and administrative workers in the USA, only
about 1.3 million are government workers, the rest are in the private
sector. Since the bulk of these private sector workers are employed by
corporations, you can easily see that corporate bureaucracy is far bigger
than government bureaucracy, even although government bureaucracy is the
largest single employer. The Cato Institute may rail against "government red
tape" but corporate bureaucracy is a far bigger issue. If you have 18.3
thousand central corporate, subsidiary, & regional managing office
establishments (2000 figures) employing 2.6 million people, this by no means
exhausts the specifically administrative (financial and non-financial) work
that corporations actually do. And that work employs another 10 million
clerical and administrative employees.

Here's some employment data on the government officialdom in the USA in
2002:

Total government employees 18.2 million (grand total 19.8 million fulltime +
parttime + casual + contractors)
Total local govt employees    11.4 million (fulltime equivalents)
Total state govt employees   5 million
Total federal employees      1.8 (domestic & overseas)

Composition of federal officialdom (broad occupational categories):

Professional            433.5 thousand
Administrative        596.6 thousand
Technical                395.2 thousand
Clerical                    150.2 thousand
Other White Collar    56.4 thousand
Blue Collar             210.8 thousand
(Unspecified                 870 employees)

Composition of state government officialdom:

Financial Administration        173.5 thousand
Central Administration           61.5 thousand
Judicial & Legal                   164.2 thousand
Police Total                            106.5 thousand
Other public services                       4.6 million

Composition of local government officialdom:

financial administration            213.5 thousand
central administration             216 thousand
judiciary and legal staff            244.7 thousand
police apparatus                     782.6 thousand
Other public services                       9.9 million

I recall that actor-president Ronald Reagan once compared Soviet agriculture
with American agriculture, in terms of the amount of workers it took to
produce an output, and he felt that this was absolute proof of the
superiority of capitalist agriculture, because even although the Russians
needed much more workers, they were importing grain. There is indeed some
truth in this. For example, Kruschev's agricultural policy of cultivating
"virgin lands" was in great part an ecological disaster - in some areas, the
burning of vegetation to create arable land, meant that the top soil just
blew away in the wind, so that nothing could be planted and cultivated
anymore. Sensible ecological thinking and rural sensitivity was not part of
official Marxist-Leninist dogma. In places like Kazakhstan, this caused
environmental devastation on a scale so great, that the cost involved in
repairing it probably cannot be met for many generations. It had nothing to
do with Marx either, as various Marxian scholars have proved with chapter
and verse.

But the problem is much more complex than Reagan, as an apologist for the
American elite, can admit. We have to consider not just (1) Stalin's
inhuman, anti-socialist, forced collectivisation of the peasantry, which
murdered masses of people unnecessarily and without provocation, and (2) the
faulty policy of over-emphasising heavy industry at the expense of workers'
consumption, so that the elite might shop in special shops, but also (3)
problems of technological dependence, (4) climatic conditions, (5) soil
fertility and infrastructure, (6) imperialist blockades and aggression, (7)
the cultural level of the agricultural population, (8) the human and
economic starting level from which an attempt at socialist modernisation
began, (9) the initial land ownership system that needed to be transformed,
and (10) the political repression of peasant parties. For example, to get
capitalist agriculture going in the USA, a genocide of the Indians was
necessary. In the Russian Empire, you couldn't do that, because the majority
of the population were peasants.

Jurriaan (in memoriam J. Tinbergen)

Reply via email to