Thanks for all the helpful responses on this.  I've published a post on the
underinclusiveness question here:

http://balkin.blogspot.com/2014/01/hobby-lobby-part-iv-myth-of.html


On Sat, Jan 11, 2014 at 7:54 AM, Marty Lederman <lederman.ma...@gmail.com>wrote:

> Just a quick point to quibble with the factual premises of the
> "selectivity" argument.  Plans offered by small business *do *have to
> include the relevant preventive services, including -- but hardly limited
> to -- contraception services.  (The services also include cholesterol
> screening; colorectal cancer screening; diabetes screening for those with
> high blood pressure; certain immunizations; “evidence-informed preventive
> care and screenings” for infants, children, and adolescents; specified
> annual well-woman visits; gestational diabetes screening; HPV DNA testing;
> testing for sexually transmitted diseases and HIV screening and counseling;
> breastfeeding support, supplies and counseling; and domestic violence
> screening and counseling.)
>
> Likewise, the so-called grandfathering "exception" is merely an ordinary
> "phasing in," or timing, provision, which allows a transition period for
> compliance with several of the Act's requirements until the plans otherwise
> make one of several specified changes.  The employees of such plans will
> eventually receive the preventive care coverages (not only contraception --
> all those listed above).
>
> The only real "carve-out" -- the only one that would result in employees
> not receiving contraceptive coverage -- is HHS's own exemption for churches
> and their auxiliaries.  And if *that religious accommodation* is what
> triggers *Lukumi*, well . . .
>
>
> On Fri, Jan 10, 2014 at 9:37 PM, James Oleske <jole...@lclark.edu> wrote:
>
>> The opening brief for Conestoga Wood Specialties Corp. has been filed,
>> and I believe this may be the first time the Supreme Court has been
>> presented with an argument in a party's merits brief as to the scope of the
>> so-called "Sherbert-exception to Smith" -- the idea expressed in both Smith 
>> and
>> Lukumi that although the Free Exercise Clause does not require religious
>> exemptions to be made from uniform legal obligations, religious exemptions
>> may be required when other exemptions to a law are available.
>>
>> In an article last year, I suggested that there remain at least five
>> major unresolved questions about the selective-exemption rule:
>>
>> 1.  What is the purpose of the rule: is it designed to guard against the
>> danger of intentional discrimination or to address the adverse impact on
>> religious minorities of unintentional neglect or indifference?
>>
>>
>> 2.  Does the rule only apply when a law allows for ad hoc,
>> individualized exemptions to an obligation (e.g., discretionary excuses
>> under a "good cause" or "necessary" standard), or does it also apply when
>> the government makes select categorical exemptions to a law?
>>
>>
>> 3.  If the rule applies when categorical exemptions are made, how should
>> courts determine whether an existing categorical exemption to a law is
>> sufficiently analogous to the requested religious exemption to be deemed a
>> relevant comparator?
>>
>>
>> 4.  How many comparable categorical exemptions must exist before the
>> selective-exemption rule is triggered by the denial of a religious
>> exemption?
>>
>>
>> 5. What is the appropriate level of judicial scrutiny to be applied once
>> the selective-exemption rule is triggered?
>>
>> Conestoga's positions on questions #2 and #5 are what you would expect.
>> On #2, it argues that the selective-exemption rule extends to situations
>> involving categorical exemptions (in this case, the ACA's exemptions for
>> small businesses and grandfathered plans). On #5, it argues for strict
>> scrutiny (which is what the Court indicated in both Smith and Lukumi
>> applies to individualized-exemption situations).
>>
>> Conestoga's brief does not contain much argument relevant to questions #3
>> and #4.
>>
>> As for #1, I found the most relevant passage in Conestoga's brief to be
>> quite surprising. Usually, advocates of a broad reading of the
>> selective-exemption rule make a point of contending that the rule is not
>> limited to situations involving the danger of discriminatory intent. Yet,
>> Conestoga's brief quotes a portion of the Third Circuit's decision in
>> Fraternal Order of Police Newark Lodge v. Newark that speaks directly to
>> discriminatory intent and is not usually quoted by advocates of a broad
>> reading of the rule:
>>
>> "Providing secular exemptions 'while refusing religious exemptions is
>> sufficiently suggestive of discriminatory intent as to trigger heightened
>> scrutiny under Smith and Lukumi.'" Br. at 46 (quoting Newark Lodge at
>> 365).
>>
>> As it turns out, this is the very same passage from Newark Lodge that I
>> suggested in my article may narrow the universe of categorical-exemption
>> situations that trigger the selective-exemption rule:
>>
>>  "[T]the court’s application of the selective-exemption rule in Newark
>> Lodge also included the key phrase, 'while refusing.' That phrase is a
>> reminder of an important but underappreciated fact in the case: the
>> categorical medical exemption was *not* part of the original no-beard
>> policy and was only adopted *after* the request for the religious
>> exemptions was made. Under those circumstances, granting the categorical
>> medical exemption while denying the religious exemptions would, as the
>> court notes, seem to raise the same risk of devaluing religion as a
>> situation in which individualized exemptions are available and religious
>> exemptions are denied. It is important to note, however, that the very
>> reason there was a risk of devaluing religion in Newark Lodge—that the
>> denied religious exemption was considered alongside other granted
>> exemptions—is a dynamic likely to be absent in many categorical exemption
>> cases, where exemptions are written into a law or policy separate from any
>> consideration of a request for a religious exemption. In those more typical
>> categorical exemption cases, there would seem to be considerably less
>> reason to draw an inference of discriminatory intent from the adoption of a
>> categorical exemption." - Lukumi at Twenty, 19 Animal Law 295, 308 (2013).
>>
>> With respect to the ACA cases, the denied religious exemptions for
>> commercial business owners were not considered alongside the granted
>> secular exemptions. Rather, "the granted secular exemptions (for small
>> businesses with fewer than fifty employees and for grandfathered plans)
>> were adopted by Congress in the ACA *prior *to HHS's regulatory
>> consideration of religious exemptions for commercial businesses." Id. at
>> 328 n.193. So if my reading of the selective-exemption rule is correct, the
>> rule would not necessarily be implicated in the ACA cases (at least by the
>> small business and grandfather exemptions; I'll leave to others the merits
>> of Conestoga's argument that HHS's granting of exemptions to some religious
>> entities requires exemptions to be granted to all entities with a religious
>> objection).
>>
>> Of course, many commentators take a much broader view of the
>> selective-exemption rule than do I, as reflected in the brief filed by 24
>> constitutional law professors in Stormans v. Selecky, which is now being
>> held by the Ninth Circuit pending Conestoga.
>>
>> That law-scholars amicus brief is available here:
>>  http://www.becketfund.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/02/Constitutional-Law
>> -Scholars-Brief.pdf.
>>
>> My article on the selective-exemption rule is available here:
>> http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2216207
>>
>> Conestoga's opening brief is available here:
>> http://www.adfmedia.org/files/ConestogaMeritsBrief.pdf
>>
>> - Jim
>>
>>
>>
>> _______________________________________________
>> To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
>> To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see
>> http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw
>>
>> Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as
>> private.  Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are
>> posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or
>> wrongly) forward the messages to others.
>>
>
>
_______________________________________________
To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu
To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see 
http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw

Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private.  
Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can 
read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the 
messages to others.

Reply via email to