On 5/29/2012 2:22 PM, Jesse Mazer wrote:


On Sun, May 27, 2012 at 2:51 PM, Aleksandr Lokshin <aaloks...@gmail.com <mailto:aaloks...@gmail.com>> wrote:


    To make the general idea more clear , suppose we are proving the well-
    known formula  S = ah/2 for the area of a triangle. Our proof will
    necessarily begin as follows:
    “Let us consider AN ARBITRARY triangle…” Here we obviously apply the
    operator of the free will choice which cannot be replaced by the
    random choice. In fact, let us imagine that our proof begins in such a
    way : “Let us consider A RANDOMLY SELECTED triangle…”  Surely, such a
    beginning will not lead us to the desired proof. The formula obtained
    for a randomly selected triangle is not necessarily valid for all
    triangles!


The notion of "choosing" isn't actually important--if a proof says something like "pick an arbitrary member of the set X, and you will find it obeys Y", this is equivalent to the statement "every member of the set X obeys Y". In formal logic this would be expressed in terms of the upside-down A symbol that represents "universal quantification" in a given "universe of discourse" such as the set of all triangles ( http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Universal_quantification ). In fact, in proofs like this one typically *doesn't* imagine choosing any specific triangle, one just thinks about properties that would apply to every member of the set and thus every "arbitrary member", like the property of having three sides or or the property of having its angles add up to 180 degrees in the case of a triangle obeying Euclidean axioms. And note that any mathematical proof can be expressed in a formal symbolic way using logical symbols/rules as well as some symbols/rules specific to the domain of mathematics under consideration (see http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Formal_proof ), and in this form the proof will often contain the universal quantification symbol, but there is no separate symbol corresponding to the notion of "pick an arbitrary member of the set".

    On the other hand when proving the formula S=ab/2, obviously, it is
impossible to consider all the triangles simultaneously.

Why not? One can consider the properties that all these triangles are defined to share, and then show that these properties, along with the axioms of geometry, can be used to derive some other properties they will all share.

    Thus the
    operator of the free will choice must be used inevitably.
    More widely, let us consider a variable x which is running about a
    sphere of radius 1. Let us pose a question: what does x  denote?
    Clearly,
    a) x does not denote an object,
    b) x does not denote a multitude,
    c) x does not denote a physical process.
    In my opinion, x denotes the free will choice which the reader of the
    mathematical text must do. So, the notion of a variable inevitably is
    based on the notion of the free will.


If it really depended on free choice, then you would have no way of being sure that just because *your* choice obeyed a certain rule, every other possible choice of examples from the same set would do so as well.

Jesse
--

Hi Jesse,

Would it be correct to think of "arbitrary" as used here as meaning " some y subset Y identified by some function i or mapping j that is not a subset (or faithfully represented) in X, yet x => y : x /subset X"? The "choice" of a basis of a linear space comes to mind. The idea is that one it is not necessary to specify the method of identification ab initio <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ab_initio>.

--
Onward!

Stephen

"Nature, to be commanded, must be obeyed."
~ Francis Bacon

--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
"Everything List" group.
To post to this group, send email to everything-list@googlegroups.com.
To unsubscribe from this group, send email to 
everything-list+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
For more options, visit this group at 
http://groups.google.com/group/everything-list?hl=en.

Reply via email to