My understanding is that many conservatives are rather fond of
geoengineering as it allows the continuing BAU pathway (at least
superficially).

Further, as David  Keith has pointed out, a degree of moral hazard is
entirely rational. However, what's surprising is that a degree of negative
or perverse moral hazard has been found in a couple of studies. IE that
some people become more worried about AGW when CE is explained. This can
potentially be rationalised by the shift in perception caused by realising
CE is considered a serious option. I guess they'd prefer blue skies to
SUVs, and facing that choice makes it more pressing.

My own serious games work supported negative moral hazard, but had to be
ditched due to methodology flaws.

A
 On 4 Mar 2014 19:22, "John Nissen" <johnnissen2...@gmail.com> wrote:

> Hi Greg,
>
> The theory is that people tend to be polarised into two camps.  One camp
> is against the idea that climate change can have anything to do with our
> greenhouse gas emissions; and therefore (subconsciously) this camp is
> against geoengineering because it would admit of a massive problem to be
> solved.  The other camp is against geoengineering (subconsciously) because
> of the moral hazard - the idea that it's a "get out of jail free" for the
> people responsible for causing climate change in the first place.  They
> will talk of geoengineering as a climate "fix", that it is "playing with
> God", etc.
>
> Kahan refers repeatedly to a 2012 study where it was shown that the "moral
> hazard" argument against geoengineering was scientifically invalid.  But
> subconsciously the second camp may still have this deep-seated fear of
> geoengineering.
>
> Therefore I deduce, using his argument, that neither camp will accept
> geoengineering, whatever evidence of the need for geoengineering is
> presented to them.
>
> I think this is the crux of the matter: nobody, identified with either of
> the common "camps", will accept geoengineering.  Only when this impasse is
> properly acknowledged, will it be possible for people to accept the
> scientific evidence that geoengineering is needed, not only to suck CO2 out
> of the atmosphere, but also to cool the Arctic.
>
> Cheers,
>
> John
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
> On Tue, Mar 4, 2014 at 4:22 AM, Rau, Greg <r...@llnl.gov> wrote:
>
>>  This observation may bear repeating:
>> "To be effective, science communication must successfully negotiate both
>> channels. That is, in addition to furnishing individuals with valid and
>> pertinent information about how the world works, it must avail itself of
>> the cues necessary to assure individuals that assenting to that information
>> will not estrange them from their communities."
>>
>>  Isn't this what good advertising does, and couldn't our community
>> benefit from some cogent advice from Madison Ave, if we could afford it?
>> Science and scientific reasoning alone apparently isn't enough, especially
>> when there are (well funded) individuals who would cast such reasoning as a
>> threat to their communities.
>> Greg
>>  ------------------------------
>> *From:* geoengineering@googlegroups.com [geoengineering@googlegroups.com]
>> on behalf of David Morrow [dmorr...@gmail.com]
>> *Sent:* Monday, March 03, 2014 6:27 PM
>> *To:* geoengineering@googlegroups.com
>> *Subject:* [geo] Re: Geoengineering and Climate Change Polarization:
>> Testing a Two-channel Model of Science Communication, Ann. Am. Acad. Pol. &
>> Soc. Sci.
>>
>>   FYI, the lead author of that paper, Dan Kahan, posted two additional
>> blog posts on culture, values, and geoengineering:
>>
>>
>> http://www.culturalcognition.net/blog/2014/2/24/geoengineering-the-cultural-plasticity-of-climate-change-ris.html
>>
>>
>> http://www.culturalcognition.net/blog/2014/2/26/geoengineering-the-science-communication-environment-the-cul.html
>>
>>
>>
>> On Thursday, February 27, 2014 2:04:00 AM UTC-6, andrewjlockley wrote:
>>>
>>> Poster's note : This is just brilliant. At last an explanation of why
>>> believing nonsense is rational. Useful to reflect on how this paper replies
>>> to the origin and persistence of other belief systems, as well as climate
>>> change. Leaves me wondering what nonsense I believe.
>>>
>>> http://www.culturalcognition.net/blog/2014/2/23/three-
>>> models-of-risk-perception-their-significance-for-self.html
>>>
>>> Three models of risk perception & their significance for self-government
>>>
>>> Dan Kahan Posted on Sunday, February 23, 2014 at 7:52AM
>>>
>>> From Geoengineering and Climate Change Polarization: Testing a
>>> Two-channel Model of Science Communication, Ann. Am. Acad. Pol. & Soc.
>>> Sci. (in press).
>>>
>>> Theoretical background
>>>
>>> Three models of risk perception
>>>
>>> The scholarly literature on risk perception and communication is
>>> dominated by two models. The first is the rational-weigher model, which
>>> posits that members of the public, in aggregate and over time, can be
>>> expected to process information about risk in a manner that promotes their
>>> expected utility (Starr 1969). The second is the irrational-weigher model,
>>> which asserts that ordinary members of the pubic lack the ability to
>>> reliably advance their expected utility because their assessment of risk
>>> information is constrained by cognitive biases and other manifestations of
>>> bounded rationality (Kahneman 2003; Sunstein 2005; Marx et al. 2007; Weber
>>> 2006).Neither of these models cogently explains public conflict over
>>> climate change--or a host of other putative societal risks, such as nuclear
>>> power, the vaccination of teenage girls for HPV, and the removal of
>>> restrictions on carrying concealed handguns in public. Such disputes
>>> conspicuously feature partisan divisions over facts that admit of
>>> scientific investigation. Nothing in the rational-weigher model predicts
>>> that people with different values or opposing political commitments will
>>> draw radically different inferences from common information. Likewise,
>>> nothing in the irrational-weigher model suggests that people who subscribe
>>> to one set of values are any more or less bounded in their rationality than
>>> those who subscribe to any other, or that cognitive biases will produce
>>> systematic divisions of opinion of among such groups.
>>>
>>> One explanation for such conflict is the cultural cognition
>>> thesis (CCT). CCT says that cultural values are cognitively prior to facts
>>> in public risk conflicts: as a result of a complex of interrelated
>>> psychological mechanisms, groups of individuals will credit and dismiss
>>> evidence of risk in patterns that reflect and reinforce their distinctive
>>> understandings of how society should be organized (Kahan, Braman, Cohen,
>>> Gastil & Slovic 2010; Jenkins-Smith & Herron 2009). Thus, persons
>>> with individualistic values can be expected to be relatively dismissive of
>>> environmental and technological risks, which if widely accepted would
>>> justify restricting commerce and industry, activities that people with such
>>> values hold in high regard. The same goes for individuals
>>> withhierarchical values, who see assertions of environmental risk as
>>> indictments of social elites. Individuals with egalitarian and communitarian
>>> values, in contrast, see commerce and industry as sources of unjust
>>> disparity and symbols of noxious self-seeking, and thus readily credit
>>> assertions that these activities are hazardous and therefore worthy of
>>> regulation (Douglass & Wildavsky 1982). Observational and experimental
>>> studies have linked these and comparable sets of outlooks to myriad risk
>>> controversies, including the one over climate change (Kahan
>>> 2012).Individuals, on the CCT account, behave not as expected-utility
>>> weighers--rational or irrational--but rather as cultural evaluators of risk
>>> information (Kahan, Slovic, Braman & Gastil 2006). The beliefs any
>>> individual forms on societal risks like climate change--whether right or
>>> wrong--do not meaningfully affect his or her personal exposure to those
>>> risks. However, precisely because positions on those issues are commonly
>>> understood to cohere with allegiance to one or another cultural style,
>>> taking a position at odds with the dominant view in his or her cultural
>>> group is likely to compromise that individual's relationship with others on
>>> whom that individual depends for emotional and material support.
>>> As individuals, citizens are thus likely to do better in their daily lives
>>> when they adopt toward putative hazards the stances that express their
>>> commitment to values that they share with others, irrespective of the fit
>>> between those beliefs and the actuarial magnitudes and probabilities of
>>> those risks.The cultural evaluator model takes issue with the
>>> irrational-weigher assumption that popular conflict over risk stems from
>>> overreliance on heuristic forms of information processing (Lodge & Taber
>>> 2013; Sunstein 2006). Empirical evidence suggests that culturally diverse
>>> citizens are indeed reliably guided toward opposing stances by unconscious
>>> processing of cues, such as the emotional resonances of arguments and the
>>> apparent values of risk communicators (Kahan, Jenkins-Smith & Braman 2011;
>>> Jenkins-Smith & Herron 2009; Jenkins-Smith 2001).But contrary to the
>>> picture painted by the irrational-weigher model, ordinary citizens who are
>>> equipped and disposed to appraise information in a reflective, analytic
>>> manner are not more likely to form beliefs consistent with the best
>>> available evidence on risk. Instead they often become even more culturally
>>> polarized because of the special capacity they have to search out and
>>> interpret evidence in patterns that sustain the convergence between their
>>> risk perceptions and their group identities (Kahan, Peters, Wittlin,
>>> Slovic, Ouellette, Braman & Mandel 2012; Kahan 2013; Kahan, Peters, Dawson
>>> & Slovic 2013).Two channels of science communication
>>>
>>> The rational- and irrational-weigher models of risk perception generate
>>> competing prescriptions for science communication. The former posits that
>>> individuals can be expected, eventually, to form empirically sound
>>> positions so long as they are furnished with sufficient and sufficiently
>>> accurate information (e.g., Viscusi 1983; Philipson & Posner 1993). The
>>> latter asserts that the attempts to educate the public about risk are at
>>> best futile, since the public lacks the knowledge and capacity to
>>> comprehend; at worst such efforts are self-defeating, since ordinary
>>> individuals are prone to overreact on the basis of fear and other affective
>>> influences on judgment. The better strategy is to steer risk policymaking
>>> away from democratically accountable actors to politically insulated
>>> experts and to "change the subject" when risk issues arise in public debate
>>> (Sunstein 2005, p. 125; see also Breyer 1993).
>>>
>>> The cultural-evaluator model associated with CCT offers a more nuanced
>>> account. It recognizes that when empirical claims about societal risk
>>> become suffused with antagonistic cultural meanings, intensified efforts to
>>> disseminate sound information are unlikely to generate consensus and can
>>> even stimulate conflict.
>>>
>>> But those instances are exceptional--indeed, pathological. There are
>>> vastly more risk issues--from the hazards of power lines to the side-effects
>>> of antibiotics to the tumor-stimulating consequences of cell phones--that
>>> avoid becoming broadly entangled with antagonistic cultural meanings. Using
>>> the same ability that they reliably employ to seek and follow expert
>>> medical treatment when they are ill or expert auto-mechanic service when
>>> their car breaks down, the vast majority of ordinary citizens can be
>>> counted on in these "normal," non-pathological cases to discern and conform
>>> their beliefs to the best available scientific evidence (Keil 2010).
>>>
>>> The cultural-evaluator model therefore counsels a two-channel strategy
>>> of science communication. Channel 1 is focused on information content and
>>> is informed by the best available understandings of how to convey
>>> empirically sound evidence, the basis and significance of which are readily
>>> accessible to ordinary citizens (e.g., Gigerenzer 2000; Spiegelhalter,
>>> Pearson & Short 2011). Channel 2 focuses on cultural meanings: the myriad
>>> cues--from group affinities and antipathies to positive and negative
>>> affective resonances to congenial or hostile narrative structures--that
>>> individuals unconsciously rely on to determine whether a particular stance
>>> toward a putative risk is consistent with their defining commitments. To be
>>> effective, science communication must successfully negotiate both channels.
>>> That is, in addition to furnishing individuals with valid and pertinent
>>> information about how the world works, it must avail itself of the cues
>>> necessary to assure individuals that assenting to that information will not
>>> estrange them from their communities (Kahan, Slovic, Braman & Gastil 2006;
>>> Nisbet 2009).
>>>
>>   --
>> You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
>> "geoengineering" group.
>> To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an
>> email to geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
>> To post to this group, send email to geoengineering@googlegroups.com.
>> Visit this group at http://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering.
>> For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/groups/opt_out.
>>
>> --
>> You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
>> "geoengineering" group.
>> To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an
>> email to geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
>> To post to this group, send email to geoengineering@googlegroups.com.
>> Visit this group at http://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering.
>> For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/groups/opt_out.
>>
>
>  --
> You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
> "geoengineering" group.
> To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an
> email to geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
> To post to this group, send email to geoengineering@googlegroups.com.
> Visit this group at http://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering.
> For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/groups/opt_out.
>

-- 
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups 
"geoengineering" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email 
to geoengineering+unsubscr...@googlegroups.com.
To post to this group, send email to geoengineering@googlegroups.com.
Visit this group at http://groups.google.com/group/geoengineering.
For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/groups/opt_out.

Reply via email to