Clark - thanks for your long outline. I don't, at the moment, have to time to 
go through it. I understand you appreciate Derrida - while I, to be honest, 
totally dislike him. I've read and re-read the three texts I have by him...but 
I don't see him as understanding the Peircean semiosis, with its modal 
categories and its triadic semiosis. And - you also seem to support Plato's 
outlines - again, I can see them fitting in with Derrida but not with Peirce.

I also prefer: object-representamen-interpretant, as I consider that it's 
confusing to call the representamen a 'sign'.

Edwina

  ----- Original Message ----- 
  From: Clark Goble 
  To: Peirce-L 
  Sent: Wednesday, October 28, 2015 3:03 PM
  Subject: [PEIRCE-L] Derrida (was: Seeing things)


  I just wanted to get to this since I’d forgotten Halloween is this weekend so 
I may not have as much free time as I’d thought. I wanted to address some 
points I’d raised with Edwina. I started this last week and it’s gotten a 
little longer than I expected. My apologies but it seemed necessary for the 
topic at hand. I’ll probably have to go silent until next week. So my apologies 
if I don’t answer your comments or corrections.


    On Oct 23, 2015, at 2:12 PM, Edwina Taborsky <tabor...@primus.ca> wrote:


    The way I read Derrida (and I admit, some time ago) in his 'Linguistics and 
Grammatology' and 'The End of the Book and the Beginning of Writing', they were 
filled with Saussurian terms (signifer and signified;  distinction between 
language and speech) which he didn't seem to question. And his focus on Peirce 
was only a few pages - he never examines the triadic semiosic action. He seems 
more to focus on the symbol - but this is not the semiosic action. That is, for 
Derrida, the focus is on rhetoric - which is all about 'signs' - but not the 
triadic semiosic action. Derrida even calls the 'thing itself' (which i take to 
be the Dynamic Object) as a 'representamen'!! (Of Grammatology, p 49).


  Saussure is the ideal foil for Derrida due to the place his lectures came to 
have in structuralism. Structuralism of course dominated a lot of philosophy 
and analysis, especially in Europe, during the first half of the 20th century. 
More importantly though Saussure’s theory of sign is a dualism of 
object:interpretant rather than a trichotomy of object:sign:interpretant. (At 
least in the form as used. I’ve had some people tell me this isn’t how Saussure 
himself necessarily conceived of it.) This conception of sign in turn applies 
for Derrida not just to Saussure and structuralism but also to Husserl and the 
problem of the inside and out within that conception phenomenology. As such an 
analysis of Saussure is the perfect for an understanding of an underlying 
problem Derrida sees in philosophy. Not just Saussure or Husserl but also 
Descartes and the logical positivists and more broadly.


  This is often cast by Derrida as logocentrism which I’d define as a logic 
that denies vagueness or a move towards determinism (semiosis). 


    I have identified logocentrism and the metaphysics of presence as the 
exigent, powerful, systematic, and irrepressible desire for such as signified 
(On Grammatology, 49)


  That is there is a desire and logic for a complete and present sign we always 
have access to. For Derrida the ideal example of this error is a certain way of 
reading Plato such that the forms are always absolute and already complete 
forms. A kind of stasis ala Parmenides rather than the flux of Heraclitus. 
European structuralism and Saussure in particular are a manifestation of this 
stasis in how they conceive of the sign.


  Derrida’s using Saussurean terms not because he agrees with Saussure but 
because he wants to show how they undermine themselves. Effectively the 
critique is of Saussure from a more Peircean perspective but in terms of 
Saussurean terminology. This can be confusing if one doesn’t keep straight what 
is going on. (At least it can be for me as I tend to think in Peircean 
terminology) While the explicit Peircean section is just a few pages the 
analysis fundamentally runs through the entire first section of the book. (And 
in some ways through the Rousseau section as well, although I’ll confess I 
don’t like that part nearly as much)


  One should keep in mind that in the 50’s Derrida came to Harvard with one of 
his major projects studying Peirce for a full year. So we should be very 
careful in dismissing Derrida’s use of Peirce. While Peircean scholarship in 
the 50’s was clearly nothing like it is today, Derrida would have read all the 
main papers of Peirce along with quite a few not widely dispersed in that era. 
Whether we agree with Derrida or not, I don’t think we can say Derrida was 
being casual with Peirce.


  As for semiotic action and the symbol, there clearly are parts Derrida’s not 
focusing on. However I think in particular “New Elements” is very important to 
understand Derrida’s project. Again we can criticize how Derrida reads Peirce. 
I recognize most dismiss Derrida’s reading. But I think we have to be careful 
in our criticisms. 


  The thing itself should be considered in terms of Husserl's and Heidegger's 
phenomenology where they saw the project as a return to the things themselves. 
As such their phenomenology projects can in certain ways be seen as a kind of 
return to direct realism whether of the scholastic form or even of the Scottish 
renaissance. Of course there are key differences from say the direct realism of 
Reid and company. For both Peirce and Derrida the direct realism is mediated 
whereas the classic medieval direct realism is unmediated as I recall. (I think 
there were variants though) As for why Derrida uses representamen for thing 
itself I think “New Elements” gets at this issue.


  However beyond that in On Grammatology Derrida is concerned with the relation 
of the thing itself and the sign.


    The sign is usually said to be put in the place of the thing itself, the 
present thing, “thing” here standing equally for meaning or referent. The sign 
represents the present in its absence. It takes the place of the present. When 
we cannot grasp or show the thing, state the present, the being-present, when 
the present cannot be presented we signify, we go through the detour of the 
sign. We signal. The sign, in this sense, is deferred presence….And this 
structure presupposes that the sign which defers presence is conceivable only 
on the basis of the presence that it defers and moving towards the deferred 
presence that it aims to appropriate. (“Différance", 9)


  Within the analysis of Saussure we’ll thus have Peirce’s final interpretant 
(which is the completeness of the sign through a temporal process it is moving 
towards as a limit) put up against Saussure’s transcendental signified (which 
is the perfection of the sign as already present). The thing is both the object 
as source of semiosis as well as the interpretant towards which semiosis leads. 
Again this is made quite clear in a Peircean frameworks in “New Elements."



  Allow me first to clarify one of my comments to you.




    Quickly off the top of my head (so beware errors on my part) what Derrida 
means by rhetoric is what Peirce calls speculative grammar. (I’ll see if I 
can’t write more on this later)


  I didn’t put that very well. I don’t mean Derrida reduces speculative grammar 
to speculative rhetoric or vice versa. Quite the opposite. He’s after how they 
are irreducible and produce a certain tension.


  I’m not sure when Peirce first introduces these terms but I know the 
distinction plays a key place in “Of Reasoning in General” (EP 2:20) The idea 
is that the study of semiotics is split into speculative grammar, logic, and 
speculative rhetoric. Speculative grammar arises out of some medieval texts 
falsely attributed to Duns Scotus.


  The typical argument against Derrida’s use of Peirce is that Peirce’s 
semiotics is concerned with logic whereas Derrida rejects such logic. I think 
this just gets Derrida wrong but I recognize it’s a common way of reading the 
use of Peirce in On Grammatology. It’s true Derrida’s aim is to deconstruct the 
sign. However we always have to keep in mind that the sign Derrida deconstructs 
is Saussure’s sign which is a dualism not a trichotomy as in Peirce. By 
extension this will also apply to phenomenology involved in dualisms (which is 
how Derrida reads Husserl, although there are ways of reading him different 
ways)


  What Derrida does is replace the term “sign” with the term “gramme” and 
semiotics" with “grammatology.” The criticism is that Derrida wants to avoid 
all categories and that with this move he’s rejecting Peirce’s sign and 
semiotics. I’m not quite sure this is accurate. Instead what I think he wants 
to do is note how all categories are themselves based upon signs and are 
symbols. (That is categories as signs - which can get confusing because we can 
talk of the categories of signs) Thus the very notion of category itself 
depends upon the play of signs. (Or if you don’t like the word play replace it 
with process or semiosis) A sign is interpreted by making an other sign. This 
means that stable categories (pure secondness) and undermined if they are in 
fact thirdness. Derrida is then concerned with how this applies to signs 
themselves. Further the shift in terminology is to break with Saussure, not 
Peirce. The later terminology he adopts is that of trace as the Peircean sign 
which he gets out of the Timaeus. In the Timaeus there’s a section dealing with 
the creation of elements. The elements are made by the form and the receptical 
(khora) producing the elements. Interestingly Peirce’s cosmology in various 
places makes a similar move with potential becoming actualness via signs. I’m 
convinced Peirce is also influenced by the Timaeus although that’s getting us a 
bit afield.


  Now Derrida’s move here poses no problem for Peirce since of course his 
notions of mediation and continuity require this. Any sign can itself be broken 
down into sub signs ad infinitum. Derrida then applies this in a more 
Heideggarian realm. Being is within philosophy treated as a thing, as being 
subject to the category. If it is a manifestation of this logic of thirdness 
though (process) then how philosophy conceives of Being is just wrong. (See 
below when I discuss Peirce’s “New Elements”) The problem is that Being as 
Being (or thirdness as thirdness for that matter) can’t be understood only as 
representation the way say analytic philosophy does. Analytic philosophy misses 
the iconic and indexical parts. More importantly it misses signs as this 
essential thirdness. Philosophers seem always to want to make signs a matter 
just of object and interpretant and avoid what makes that relationship possible.


  Those making the criticism of Derrida in terms of Peirce typically (although 
not universally) make the mistake of treating thirdness as just this sort of 
representation (especially representations as conceived of in analytic 
philosophy from Descartes to the present) Again “New Elements” is crucial here.


  Going back to Peirce’s categories in “Of Reasoning in General” we have the 
following.


  logic: reference of signs to objects
  speculative grammar: general conditions of signification
  speculative rhetoric: relation of signs to interpretants


  By speculative grammar Peirce is concerned with how signs must function in 
order to have a sense. The idea from the medieval era is that meaning is 
independent of truth but is tied to signs. But note how Peirce’s speculative 
grammar entails that notions of truth simply can’t function as they do 
especially in the analytic tradition. (But also the earlier continental 
tradition with Kant through Hegel up to Husserl) Peirce can deal with this 
because of the way the final interpretant functions. But again, the final 
interpretant as such is always absent. It is never something present as we have 
with Descartes or the most popular interpretations of Plato. We may have a true 
statement but it is true because it is the same kind of sign as the sign of the 
final interpretant. But we don’t have an absolute certain way of having truth. 
And this disruption between truth and sign is possible because signs are 
thirdness and not secondness. 


  Going back to Derrida this aspect of Peirce means that speculative grammar 
and speculate rhetoric can’t be collapsed into one an other. We then have the 
connection between rhetoric or signs to interpretants and grammar or signs in 
themselves. The issue is that because of grammar we have an indefinite form of 
reference. (Signs signify their object with a guess; interpretants rise out of 
this logic of guessing) It is this gap between sign and object that lets us 
know we’re even dealing with signs. Yet with speculative rhetoric we have this 
notion of interpretants and the very idea of a final interpretant.


  This is why Derrida emphasizes that “the thing itself is a sign.” This gets 
at categories and in particular the Saussurean sign where we only have the 
object and interpretant in a dualism. This play of the sign is absent. Things 
are never static. This also is the issue of inside/outside for Husserlian 
phenomenology where we have this dualism rather than a thirdness. (Although 
again there are some key places to read Husserl in a different way) It’s 
precisely this issue of a problem in Husserl that is why Derrida turns to the 
problem in Saussure and by extension all structuralism in the first half of the 
20th century.


  Now we get to the key place in On Grammatology for rhetoric. When Derrida 
speaks of rhetoric he’s talking of the third category just as in “On Reasoning 
in General.” He says it “has the task to ascertain the laws by which every 
scientific intelligence one sign gives birth to another.” That is 
interpretants. But note the subtle shift. The interpretant is itself an other 
sign. So there’s this essential connection between speculative rhetoric 
(interpretants) and speculative grammar (signs). To have a final interpretant 
in the traditional (non-Pericean) sense is to have an absolute stop. But 
Peirce’s final interpretant is not a final stop. It is a place of stability in 
semiosis. It’s not a stop so much as a completeness. The final interpretant are 
the interpretants semiosis arrives at given sufficient time. But it doesn’t 
mean semiosis has stopped. (This is why in other places Derrida appeals to 
Nietzsche’s use of the Eternal Round which is just the playing out in infinity 
of all signs such that we can conceive of completeness)


  There are some big places to critique Derrida here. However they simply 
aren’t the places he usually gets critiqued. The big question I’d put up for 
Derrida would be how to deal with Peirce’s conception of substance. However 
even here, at least in the early Peirce, things get tricky. Early on as Peirce 
is revising Kant he has five categories: Being, Quality, Relation, 
Representation, Substance. (W 2:49-59) However he drops Being and Substance 
because they are unthinkable limits and thus have no meaning in terms of how we 
think. Kelly Parker does some great work on this — although we should be 
careful to distinguish the early Peirce from the mature Peirce. The mature 
Peirce in “New Elements” is a bit more cautious. Allow me an extended 
quotation. (Sorry, quoting from my Kindle so I don’t have page numbers - 
emphasis is mine.)


    Every sign that is sufficiently complete refers to sundry real objects. All 
these objects, even if we are talking of Hamlet’s madness, are parts of one and 
the same Universe of being, the “Truth.” But so far as the “Truth” is merely 
the object of a sign, it is merely the Aristotelian Matter of it that is so. In 
addition however to denoting objects, every sign sufficiently complete 
signifies characters, or qualities. We have a direct knowledge of real objects 
in every experiential reaction, whether of Perception or of Exertion (the one 
theoretical, the other practical). These are directly hie et nunc. But we 
extend the category, and speak of numberless real objects with which we are not 
in direct reaction. We have also direct knowledge of qualities in feeling, 
peripheral and visceral. But we extend this category to numberless characters 
of which we have no immediate consciousness. All these characters are elements 
of the “Truth.” Every sign signifies the “Truth.” But it is only the 
Aristotelian Form of the universe that it signifies. The logician is not 
concerned with any metaphysical theory; still less, if possible, is the 
mathematician. But it is highly convenient to express ourselves in terms of a 
metaphysical theory; and we no more bind ourselves to an acceptance of it than 
we do when we use substantives such as “humanity,” “variety,” etc., and speak 
of them as if they were substances, in the metaphysical sense. But, in the 
third place, every sign is intended to determine a sign of the same object with 
the same signification or meaning. Any sign, B, which a sign, A, is fitted so 
to determine, without violation of its, A’s, purpose, that is, in accordance 
with the “Truth,” even though it, B, denotes but a part of the objects of the 
sign, A, and signifies but a part of its, A’s, characters, I call an 
interpretant of A. What we call a “fact” is something having the structure of a 
proposition, but supposed to be an element of the very universe itself. The 
purpose of every sign is to express “fact,” and by being joined with other 
signs, to approach as nearly as possible to determining an interpretant which 
would be the perfect Truth, the absolute Truth, and as such (at least, we may 
use this language) would be the very Universe. Aristotle gropes for a 
conception of perfection, or entelechy, which he never succeeds in making 
clear. We may adopt the word to mean the very fact, that is, the ideal sign 
which should be quite perfect, and so identical,— in such identity as a sign 
may have,— with the very matter denoted united with the very form signified by 
it. The entelechy of the Universe of being, then, the Universe qua fact, will 
be that Universe in its aspect as a sign, the “Truth” of being. The “Truth,” 
the fact that is not abstracted but complete, is the ultimate interpretant of 
every sign.


  There’s a lot in this paragraph. Peirce has shifted from his earlier phase. 
He’s willing to use metaphysical language. Particularly Aristotle conceive of 
in a more neoplatonic way. However he doesn’t feel committed to it. The key 
though is conceive the universe in its aspect as a sign. Second there’s a type 
of direct realism which I think is what Heidegger’s externalism commits him to 
and that by extension the realist interpretation of Derrida commits him to. 
(Remember though for Derrida the things themselves that Heidegger is committed 
to are signs because we can only think in signs) So what Derrida says rhetoric 
gets us to is this universe in its aspect as a sign. Speculative rhetoric can’t 
fully be separated from speculative grammar. The final interpretant is not 
something abstracted and present but is the completeness of semiosis. This is 
that unthinkable limit that Peirce refers to early on. (It’s just that now 
Peirce is willing to use metaphysical language while being explicit he’s not 
committed to it)


  I should add that “New Elements” has some analysis of Being that is just 
amazingly profound and I don’t think gets commented on enough. In particular 
how he discusses the copula. He makes an interesting note about Greek permits 
the copula to be admitted and it’s not until Abelard when logic is done in 
Latin that the copula is seen as constituent of logic. He then notes how 
logicians have treated the copula. Yet he notes that logically the mark of the 
junction, where the copula goes, is an index. Then he notes, "the only way in 
which any index can ever signify anything; by involving an icon. The sign 
itself is a connection.” Heidegger and Derrida’s work placing being under 
erasure (often the copula in various forms with a big X through it always 
reminds me of this part of “New Elements."


  Peirce next condemns the German practice of tying all this to judgment in 
place of propositions (which are these signs with the index by icon). Finally 
he makes a masterful analysis in terms of feelings of how iconicity of symbols 
functions and enables indices. He then makes a comment that could have been an 
aporia written by Derrida. (And it appears this underlies a lot of the analysis 
Derrida does in On Grammatology)


    It is quite certain therefore that in this feeling we have a definite 
instance of a symbol which, in a certain sense, necessarily signifies what it 
does. We have already seen that it can only be by an accident, and not by 
inherent necessity, that a symbol signifies what it does. The two results are 
reconciled by the consideration that the accident in this case is that we are 
so constituted that that feeling shall be so interpreted by us.


  The nature of the constitution is revealed in the climax of “New Elements” 
found in its final paragraph. It’s the idea of the human as symbol and thus 
part of semiosis. That is our judgments aren’t judgments in the German sense 
Peirce condemns (and that we find in America as the Vienna Circle comes to 
dominate analytic philosophy for a time) Rather they (and we) are merely the 
selection of greater powers in this process of semiosis. A remarkably radical 
claim constitutive of his semiotic realism. 


  Peirce then next return to a cosmology fairly similar to his early thought.


    Now it is of the essential nature of a symbol that it determines an 
interpretant, which is itself a symbol. A symbol, therefore, produces an 
endless series of interpretants. Does anybody suspect all this of being sheer 
nonsense? Distinguo. There can, it is true, be no positive information about 
what antedated the entire Universe of being; because, to begin with, there was 
nothing to have information about. But the universe is intelligible; and 
therefore it is possible to give a general account of it and its origin. This 
general account is a symbol; and from the nature of a symbol, it must begin 
with the formal assertion that there was an indeterminate nothing of the nature 
of a symbol. This would be false if it conveyed any information. But it is the 
correct and logical manner of beginning an account of the universe. As a symbol 
it produced its infinite series of interpretants, which in the beginning were 
absolutely vague like itself. But the direct interpretant of any symbol must in 
the first stage of it be merely the tabula rasa for an interpretant. Hence the 
immediate interpretant of this vague Nothing was not even determinately vague, 
but only vaguely hovering between determinacy and vagueness; and its immediate 
interpretant was vaguely hovering between vaguely hovering between vagueness 
and determinacy and determinate vagueness or determinacy, and so on, ad 
infinitum. But every endless series must logically have a limit.


    Leaving that line of thought unfinished for the present owing to the 
feeling of insecurity it provokes, let us note, first, that it is of the nature 
of a symbol to create a tabula rasa and therefore an endless series of tabulae 
rasae, since such creation is merely representation, the tabulae rasae being 
entirely indeterminate except to be representative. 


    [...]


    In so far as the interpretant is the symbol, as it is in some measure, the 
determination agrees with that of the symbol. But in so far as it fails to be 
its better self, it is liable to depart from the meaning of the symbol. Its 
purpose, however, is to represent the symbol in its representation of its 
object; and therefore, the determination is followed by a further development, 
in which it becomes corrected. It is of the nature of a sign to be an 
individual replica and to be in that replica a living general. By virtue of 
this, the interpretant is animated by the original replica, or by the sign it 
contains, with the power of representing the true character of the object. That 
the object has at all a character can only consist in a representation that it 
has so,— a representation having power to live down all opposition. In these 
two steps, of determination and of correction, the interpretant aims at the 
object more than at the original replica and may be truer and fuller than the 
latter. The very entelechy of being lies in being representable. A sign cannot 
even be false without being a sign and so far as it is a sign it must be true. 
A symbol is an embryonic reality endowed with power of growth into the very 
truth, the very entelechy of reality. This appears mystical and mysterious 
simply because we insist on remaining blind to what is plain, that there can be 
no reality which has not the life of a symbol.


    [...]


    A chaos of reactions utterly without any approach to law is absolutely 
nothing; and therefore pure nothing was such a chaos. Then pure indeterminacy 
having developed determinate possibilities, creation consisted in mediating 
between the lawless reactions and the general possibilities by the influx of a 
symbol. This symbol was the purpose of creation. Its object was the entelechy 
of being which is the ultimate representation.


  The importance of “New Elements” when considering Derrida just can’t be 
underestimated. It’s here that we understand the relationship of icon and index 
in feeling so as to enable symbols to function the way they do. The other place 
of attack on Derrida relative Perice is usually that Derrida neglects the icon 
and especially index. I think reading “New Elements” carefully shows why 
Derrida’s use of symbol doesn’t fall prey to this attack.


  The final interpretant really should be thought of in terms of mathematical 
limits such as we find in calculus.



  Finally quite from denying logic Derrida’s whole point is to show how logic, 
rhetoric and grammar are irreducible. It’s only by examining them carefully 
that we realize this and thereby see how logic has to proceed. Peirce is pretty 
clear on this, especially in key papers like “New Elements.” Those who take 
Derrida as rejecting or undermining logic just miss that what he is taking 
seriously is the relationship of logic (or how signs relate to objects) with 
signs in themselves and how signs relate to interpretants. The problem is that 
philosophers want to deny in various ways this irreducible nature. Or, as 
Peirce typically puts it, they are committed to nominalism: the idea of 
object:name rather than object:sign:interpretant. 




------------------------------------------------------------------------------



  -----------------------------
  PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON 
PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . 
To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with 
the line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to