Gary F, Jeff, Mike,

Thanks for the reference, Jeff.

I thought that the question of consequentiae might be more complicated than
being able to relate it to the terms of formal symbolic logic, but I wanted
to see what your thoughts were on it, and so I do. The confirmation is much
appreciated.

-- Franklin

On Oct 25, 2017 8:05 PM, "Mike Bergman" <m...@mkbergman.com> wrote:

> Hi Jeff,
>
>
> Thank you. The Bellucci reference is excellent and timely. I found a PDF
> online at http://www.academia.edu/download/41369857/Bellucci_
> CSP_consequences.pdf; some of the Abelard quotes are translated at
> http://johnmacfarlane.net/abelard.pdf.
>
>
> Best, Mike
>
> On 10/25/2017 6:18 PM, Jeffrey Brian Downard wrote:
>
> Franklin, Gary F, List,
>
>
> In *Reading Peirce Reading*, Richard Smyth suggests that many logicians,
> such as Quine, make the error of   making assignments to the truth table
> for the conditional in a rather arbitrary fashion. Peirce, on the other
> hand, is developing a logical theory that seeks to explain why some
> inferences that we take to be good or bad really are valid or invalid. As
> such, he is setting up a semantic assignment of values to the truth table
> that is not arbitrary.
>
>
> Here, in the second lecture, he trying to show us how to set up
> mathematical system of logic that will enable us to analyze examples of
> reasoning more carefully and exactly. As such, he is trying to avoid the
> temptation of developing a logical system that prejudges the questions
> we're trying to answer in the normative theory of logic.
>
>
> For background on the relation between these different accounts of the
> conditional, it might be worth looking atFrancesco Bellucci
> <http://www.tandfonline.com/author/Bellucci%2C+Francesco>'s "Charles S.
> Peirce and the Medieval Doctrine of *consequentiae".*
> See: http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/01445340.
> 2015.1118338?scroll=top&needAccess=true&
>
>
> In this article, he provides a historical reconstruction of what Peirce
> was drawing from in the medieval doctrine, and how this account of the
> conditional shape his understanding of the relation of implication.
>
>
> --Jeff
>
>
> Jeffrey Downard
> Associate Professor
> Department of Philosophy
> Northern Arizona University
> (o) 928 523-8354 <(928)%20523-8354>
> ------------------------------
> *From:* Franklin Ransom <pragmaticist.lo...@gmail.com>
> <pragmaticist.lo...@gmail.com>
> *Sent:* Wednesday, October 25, 2017 1:51:13 PM
> *To:* peirce-l@list.iupui.edu 1
> *Subject:* RE: [PEIRCE-L] Lowell Lecture 2.4
>
> Gary F,
>
> If I try to picture the Philonian and Diodoran interpretations in terms of
> truth value tables, they essentially correspond to material and strict
> implication, respectively. But I'm not sure how the distinction between
> ordinary consequence and simplex de inesse fits in. Would that have more to
> do with modal logic (possible vs...actual?), which the gamma graphs aim to
> treat of, and which you are suggesting is where the Philonian or material
> approach becomes problematic?
>
> -- Franklin
>
>
> On Oct 25, 2017 4:22 PM, <g...@gnusystems.ca> wrote:
>
> Franklin, list,
>
>
>
> The distinction between the conditional “simplex de inesse” and other
> if-then propositions is that the “simplex” is indeed simpler, and
> absolutely exact from a logical point of view, which removes all possible
> ambiguity from the interpretation of it. It asserts no connection at all
> between the truth of the antecedent and the truth of the consequent
> *except* that when the former is true, the latter is true, “never mind
> the why or wherefore.” This means that there is no way to falsify the
> conditional proposition as a whole *except* to observe that the
> antecedent is true *and* the consequent is false. The proposition as a
> whole — contrary to the “ordinary language” usage and the Diodoran point of
> view — remains perfectly true if *both* antecedent and consequent are in
> themselves false.
>
>
>
> The *significance* of this distinction should become more clear as Peirce
> proceeds to define the “scroll” as the diagram representing the conditional 
> *de
> inesse*. The reading of the scroll follows from the stipulation “that in
> logic we are to understand the form “If A, then B” to mean “Either A is
> impossible or in every possible case in which it is true, B is true
> likewise,” or in other words it means “In each possible case, either A is
> false or B is true.”
>
> From this Peirce will derive the meaning of the cut as *negation of what
> is inside the cut*. It seems to me, in hindsight, that right here on the
> ground level of the whole EG system lies a design feature that will later
> become problematic for the gamma part of EGs, i.e. for modal logic. That’s
> why I’m trying to understand why Peirce felt compelled to design them in
> the way he did.
>
>
>
> The significance of the distinction becomes amplified, I think, as soon as
> we take a step beyond exact logic into metaphysics. But we’re not ready to
> talk about that yet. Or at least I’m not, I’m still trying to clarify
> exactly how EGs are supposed to work, so that their meanings become more
> directly visible to me.
>
>
>
> Gary f.
>
>
>
> *From:* Franklin Ransom [mailto:pragmaticist.lo...@gmail.com]
> *Sent:* 25-Oct-17 14:32
> *Cc:* peirce-l@list.iupui.edu 1 <PEIRCE-L@list.iupui.edu>
> *Subject:* Re: [PEIRCE-L] Lowell Lecture 2.4
>
>
>
> Gary F,
>
>
>
> Do you understand the significance of the distinction between regular
> consequentia and consequentia simplex de inesse to the conditional debate?
> That is not clear to me in what was stated in the excerpt from RLT, given
> what Peirce says in the excerpt from the second Lowell lecture.
>
>
>
> -- Franklin
>
>
>
> Here’s the 1898 excerpt that explains the importance of the “conditional *de
> inesse*” *(R441, RLT 125-6, NEM4 169-70):*
>
>  Cicero informs us that in his time there was a famous controversy
> between two logicians, Philo and Diodorus, as to the signification of
> conditional propositions. Philo held that the proposition “if it is
> lightening it will thunder” was true if it is not lightening or if it will
> thunder and was only false if it is lightening but will not thunder.
> Diodorus objected to this. Either the ancient reporters or he himself
> failed to make out precisely what was in his mind, and though there have
> been many virtual Diodorans since, none of them have been able to state
> their position clearly without making it too foolish. Most of the strong
> logicians have been Philonians, and most of the weak ones have been
> Diodorans. For my part, I am a Philonian; but I do not think that justice
> has ever been done to the Diodoran side of the question. The Diodoran
> vaguely feels that there is something wrong about the statement that the
> proposition “If it is lightening it will thunder” can be made true merely
> by its not lightening.
>
> Duns Scotus, who was a Philonian , as a matter of course, threw
> considerable light upon the matter by distinguishing between an ordinary
> *consequentia*, or conditional proposition, and a *consequentia simplex
> de inesse*. A *consequentia simplex de inesse* relates to no range of
> possibilities at all, but merely to what happens, or is true, *hic et
> nunc*. But the ordinary conditional proposition asserts not merely that
> here and now either the antecedent is false or the consequent is true, but
> that in each possible state of things throughout a certain well-understood
> range of possibility either the antecedent is false or the consequent true.
> So understood the proposition “If it lightens it will thunder” means that
> on each occasion which could arise consistently with the regular course of
> nature, either it would not lighten or thunder would shortly follow.
>
> Now this much may be conceded to the Diodoran, in order that we may fit
> him out with a better defence than he has ever been able to construct for
> himself, namely, that in our ordinary use of language we always understand
> the range of possibility in such a sense that in some possible case the
> antecedent shall be true. Consider, for example, the following conditional
> proposition: If I were to take up that lampstand by its shaft and go
> brandishing the lamp about in the faces of my auditors it would not
> occasion the slightest surprise to anybody. Everybody will say that is
> false; and were I to reply that it was true because under no possible
> circumstances should I behave in that outrageous manner, you would feel
> that I was violating the usages of speech.
>
> I would respectfully and kindly suggest to the Diodoran that this way of
> defending his position is better than his ordinary stammerings. Still,
> should he accept my suggestion I shall with pain be obliged to add that the
> argument is the merest *ignoratio elenchi* which ought not to deceive a
> tyro in logic. For it is quite beside the question what ordinary language
> means. The very idea of formal logic is, that certain *canonical forms*
> of expression shall be provided, the meanings of which forms are governed
> by inflexible rules; and if the forms of speech are borrowed to be used as 
> *canonical
> forms of logic* it is merely for the mnemonic aid they afford, and they
> are always to be understood in logic in strict technical senses. These
> forms of expression are to be defined, just as zoologists and botanists
> define the terms which they invent, that is to say, without the slightest
> regard for usage but so as to correspond to natural classifications. That
> is why I entitled one of the first papers I published, “On the Natural
> Classification of Arguments.” And by a *natural* classification, we mean
> the most pregnant classification, pregnant that is to say with implications
> concerning what is important from a strictly logical point of view.
>
> Now I have worked out in MS. the whole of syllogistic in a perfectly
> thoroughgoing manner both from the Philonian and from the Diodoran point of
> view. But although my exposition is far more favorable to the Diodoran
> system even than that of DeMorgan in his *Syllabus of Logic*, which is
> much the best presentation of the Diodoran case ever made by an adherent of
> it, yet I find that the Philonian system is far the simpler,— almost
> incomparably so. You would not wish me to take you through all those
> details. This general statement is all that is appropriate for this brief
> course of lectures.
>
> Be it understood, then, that in logic we are to understand the form “If A,
> then B” to mean “Either A is impossible or in every possible case in which
> it is true, B is true likewise,” or in other words it means “In each
> possible case, either A is false or B is true.”
>
> Continuing from Lowell 2.3,
>
> https://www.fromthepage.com/jeffdown1/c-s-peirce-manuscripts
> /ms-455-456-1903-lowell-lecture-ii/display/13602:
>
> The most immediately useful information is that which is conveyed in
> conditional propositions, “*If* you find that this is true, *then* you
> may know that that is true.” Now in ordinary language the conditional form
> is employed to express a variety of relations between one possibility and
> another. Very frequently when we say “If A is true, then B is true,” we
> have in mind a whole range of possibilities, and we assert that among all
> possible cases, every one of those in which A is true will turn out to be a
> case in which B is true also. But in order to obtain a way of expressing
> that sort of conditional proposition, we must begin by getting a way of
> expressing a simpler kind, which does not often occur in ordinary speech
> but which has great importance in logic. The sort of conditional
> proposition I mean is one in which no range of possibilities is
> contemplated, which speaks only of the actual state of things. “If A is
> true then B is true,” in this sense is called a conditional proposition *de
> inesse*. In case A is not true, it makes no assertion at all and
> therefore involves no falsity. And since every proposition is either true
> or false, if the antecedent, A, is not true, the conditional *de inesse*
> is true, no matter how it may be with B. In case the consequent, B, is
> true, all that the conditional *de inesse* asserts is true, and therefore
> it is true, no matter how it may be with A. If however the antecedent, A,
> is true, while the consequent, B, is false, then, and then only is the
> conditional proposition *de inesse* false. This sort of conditional says
> nothing at all about any real connection between antecedent and consequent;
> but limits itself to saying “If you should find that A is true, then you
> may know that B is true,” never mind the why or wherefore.
>
> *http://gnusystems.ca/Lowell2.htm <http://gnusystems.ca/Lowell2.htm>* }{
> Peirce’s Lowell Lectures of 1903
>
> https://fromthepage.com/jeffdown1/c-s-peirce-manuscripts/ms-
> 455-456-1903-lowell-lecture-ii
>
>
>
>
>
> -----------------------------
> PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON
> PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to
> peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L
> but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the
> BODY of the message. More at http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm
> .
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
> -----------------------------
> PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON
> PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to
> peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L
> but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the
> BODY of the message. More at http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm
> .
>
>
>
>
>
>
-----------------------------
PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON PEIRCE-L 
to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . To 
UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message not to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu with the 
line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of the message. More at 
http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .




Reply via email to