John, List, All:

JFS: The bottom line (which I added) is a translation of the algebraic
notation to EGs.  It shows the EG for a single negation defined by an EG
with three negations.


That "translation" is blatantly question-begging since it *presupposes *the
cut for negation rather than properly *deriving *it from the scroll for
implication with a blackened inner close for falsity/absurdity, expressed
positively as "every proposition is true."  Pietarinen recently wrote
another excellent paper with Bellucci, Shafiei, and two other co-authors
specifically about the latter (
https://www.researchgate.net/publication/343688226_The_Blot).

JFS: It seems strange (dubious? unreasonable? unjustified?) to claim that a
triple negation is more fundamental than a single negation.


It is strange, dubious, unreasonable, and unjustified to attribute
something to Peirce that he never stated, implied, or even so much as
suggested.

JFS: But his English explanation of Figures 23 to 26 is vague and
rambling.  He was struggling to make a bad choice seem plausible.


On the contrary, the passage is quite lucid and straightforward, as well as
perfectly consistent with multiple others in Peirce's writings on the same
subject. Here it is in its entirety so that those reading along can judge
for themselves.

CSP: The Cut came to be thought of because of the immense frequency of
occasions on which it was necessary to express the assertion "If X be true,
then every assertion is true." It was forced upon the logician’s attention
that a certain development of reasoning was possible before, or as if
before, the concept of *falsity *had ever been framed, or any recognition
of such a thing as a false assertion had ever taken place. Probably every
human being passes through such a grade of intellectual life, which may be
called the state of paradisaical logic, when reasoning takes place but when
the idea of falsity, whether in assertion or in inference, has never been
recognized. But it will soon be recognized that not every assertion is
true; and that once recognized, as soon as one notices that if a certain
thing were true, every assertion would be true, one at once rejects the
antecedent that lead to that absurd consequence. Now that conditional
proposition "If A is true, every proposition is true," is represented, in
the model of Fig. 23, "If A is true, C is true" by blackening the entire
inner close, as if there were no room, in reason, for any additional
consequence. This gives Fig. 24: "If A be true whatever can be asserted is
true," which is as much as to say that A is not true and the inner close
being cut very small, we get, first Fig. 25 and finally Fig. 26, in which
the idea of flat falsity is first matured. (R 669:18-20[16-18], LF 1:582,
1911 May 31)


As Pietarinen emphasizes repeatedly, both in various papers over the years
and in the introductory material in *Logic of the Future*, the scroll for
implication is a logical primitive for Peirce--just like its algebraic
predecessors, the copula of inclusion and the sign of consequence--because
it corresponds directly to *inference*, which does not require any prior
notion of falsity. By contrast, the cut for negation must be
explicitly *defined
*as a scroll with an infinitesimally small blackened inner close because
otherwise it is a scroll *without *an inner close, thus signifying "if A"
with no consequent or "if A, then something is true" where we interpret the
inner close as containing the blank, which has been deiterated (CP 4.564n,
c. 1906).

JFS: And by the way, nothing in the article by Ma and Pietarinen depends on
which logical operators are assumed as primitives.  With derived rules of
inference, the choice of primitives is irrelevant.


Peirce has a different opinion, and I agree with him. Bellucci and
Pietarinen summarize it as follows.

FB & AVP: As an abbreviation, we can interpret the oval as negation and
then express the conditional in terms of negation and conjunction (as in
EGs) or in terms of negation and disjunction (as in Entitative Graphs). In
this way, it is possible to negate *a* without resorting to the more
complex conditional form with the blot as in Fig. 4. But Peirce is clear
that this is just a derived interpretation, an interpretational corollary
(MS 450, 1903). Taking the idea of negation as primary is philosophically
inaccurate:

All my own writings upon formal logic have been based on the belief that
the concept of Sequence, alike in reasonings and in judgments, whether the
latter be conditional or categorical, could in no wise be replaced by any
composition of ideas [...] Indeed, so far is the concept of Sequence from
being a composite of two Negations, that, on the contrary, the concept of
the Negation of any state of things, X, is, precisely, a composite of which
one element is the concept of Sequence. Namely, it is the concept of a
sequence from X of the essence of falsity. (MS 300, pp. 46-48, 1908)

Negation is not a primitive idea; rather, it is a conception derived from
that of implication. Therefore, the sign of negation ought to be considered
as a complication or determination of a more primitive sign, the scroll.
The analysis of negation in terms of the conditional is according to Peirce
one of the few satisfactory proofs of the indecomposability or
uncompoundness of a logical concept that can be obtained. He took that in
logical analysis, it is “tolerably easy to demonstrate compoundness, but
next to impossible to make sure of elementality, or elementarity” (MS 300,
p. 49, 1908). Once all other logical constants of the propositional
calculus are defined in terms of the conditional relation, we have carried
analysis to its extreme (truth-functional) limit: the conditional is
logically unanalyzable, while other logical relations are analyzable
through it. (
https://www.cambridge.org/core/services/aop-cambridge-core/content/view/9C4689940BDC5B17F739C34A87C2B77F/S1755020315000362a.pdf/div-class-title-existential-graphs-as-an-instrument-of-logical-analysis-part-i-alpha-div.pdf,
pp. 220-221)


As Peirce explains at the ellipsis in the quotation, from a strictly
theoretical standpoint, implication *must *be a logical primitive and
*cannot *be analyzed as a composite of two negations because the latter is
missing the "real movement of thought in the mind" from antecedent to
consequent.

Regards,

Jon Alan Schmidt - Olathe, Kansas, USA
Structural Engineer, Synechist Philosopher, Lutheran Christian
www.LinkedIn.com/in/JonAlanSchmidt - twitter.com/JonAlanSchmidt

On Sat, Feb 27, 2021 at 11:58 PM John F. Sowa <s...@bestweb.net> wrote:

> Jon AS, List,
>
> To understand Peirce's views prior to 1911, I recommend the detailed
> analysis in "Peirce's calculi for classical propositional logic", by
> Minghui Ma and Ahti Pietarinen:
> https://www.researchgate.net/publication/327235076
>
> For a definition of negation in terms of material implication, see
> MM_AVP.png (attached below).  The top two lines are copied from p. 6 of
> that article.  The bottom line (which I added) is a translation of the
> algebraic notation to EGs.  It shows the EG for a single negation defined
> by an EG with three negations.  It seems strange (dubious? unreasonable?
> unjustified?) to claim that a triple negation is more fundamental than a
> single negation.
>
> To state an equivalent definition in R669, Peirce started with a scroll
> for (A implies C) and took three steps to derive not-A.  (See the attached
> R669figs.png.)  But his English explanation of Figures 23 to 26 is vague
> and rambling.  He was struggling to make a bad choice seem plausible.
>
> After Peirce wrote R669, he could not have been satisfied with those four
> EGs and his vague English prose.  He probably went to the blackboard to
> draw other variations.  If he drew the EG at the bottom of MM_AVP.png (or
> anything similar), the conclusion would be obvious; negation must be
> primitive.
>
> JAS> Peirce's actual claim was that his primary purpose when developing
> both algebraic and graphical systems of logic was "not at all the
> construction of a calculus to aid the drawing of inferences," but rather
> "that the system devised for the investigation of logic should be as
> analytical as possible, breaking up inferences into the greatest possible
> number of steps, and exhibiting them under the most general categories
> possible" (CP 4.373, 1902).
>
> Yes, both Peirce and Frege made the sane mistake.  As pioneers in logic,
> neither of them had any experience with derived rules of inference.  To see
> how the derived rules enable the same choice of primitives to be used for
> both theory and practice, please reread
> http://jfsowa.com/peirce/EGcalculus.pdf .
>
> And by the way, nothing in the article by Ma and Pietarinen depends on
> which logical operators are assumed as primitives.  With derived rules of
> inference, the choice of primitives is irrelevant.  The authors could
> strengthen their argument by showing that the formal derivations are
> independent of the choice of logical primitives.
>
> JAS> Indeed, treating negation as if it were the third logical primitive
> results in a more efficient calculus for classical logic, as well as a
> simpler introduction of EG for the previously uninitiated....
>
> Yes!  And the beauty of the 1911 EGs is that the best foundation for
> teaching novices is also the best for professionals in every branch of the
> empirical sciences:  phaneroscopy, semeiotic, metaphysics, normative
> science, logic as semeiotic, physical sciences, and psychical sciences.
> For an explanation of that point, see "Natural logic is diagrammatic
> reasoning about mental models": http://jfsowa.com/pubs/natlog.pdf .
>
> Since calculation is the theme of this thread, it's important to note
> Peirce's mistake at the end of R669:  "the application of the two illative
> permissions... can only be made by a living intelligence." In fact,
> computer systems today can apply Peirce's permissions and the rules derived
> from them much faster and more accurately than any human.
>
> Today, the enormous volume of data on the www, especially documents
> written in natural languages, poses a challenge to the fastest
> supercomputers available.  In June 2020, I presented a lecture "Language,
> ontology, and the Semantic Web" at the European Semantic Web Conference:
> http://jfsowa.com/talks/eswc.pdf
>
> In section 3 (slides 13 to 20 of eswc.pdf), I introduced EGs, and in later
> sections I discussed the importance of Peirce's logic and semeiotic for
> supporting innovative methods for addressing that challenge.  The
> generality of the 1911 EGs is essential.
>
> In summary, the three documents EGcalculus.pdf, natlog.pdf, and eswc.pdf,
> which are based on the 1911 EGs, show the importance of Peirce's insight on
> or about 3 June 1911.  No one has shown any evidence in favor of older
> versions of EGs.  If anyone has any doubts on that point, I would be happy
> to answer them.
>
> John
>
_ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _
► PEIRCE-L subscribers: Click on "Reply List" or "Reply All" to REPLY ON 
PEIRCE-L to this message. PEIRCE-L posts should go to peirce-L@list.iupui.edu . 
► To UNSUBSCRIBE, send a message NOT to PEIRCE-L but to l...@list.iupui.edu 
with no subject, and with the sole line "UNSubscribe PEIRCE-L" in the BODY of 
the message. More at http://www.cspeirce.com/peirce-l/peirce-l.htm .
► PEIRCE-L is owned by THE PEIRCE GROUP;  moderated by Gary Richmond;  and 
co-managed by him and Ben Udell.

Reply via email to