Steven, thanks for getting our next slow read started – i have a couple of 
questions and a comment on your first post.

In your comments on JR's opening, you say that “Semeiotic Theory is, for me, 
the first activity of scientific thinking.” I take “Semeiotic Theory” to be 
your shorthand for “development of Semeiotic Theory” (since “Theory” is not in 
itself an “activity”). Given the usual Peircean concept of “philosophy” as “an 
experiential, or positive science, but a science which rests on no special 
observations, made by special observational means, but on phenomena which lie 
open to the observation of every man, every day and hour” (CP 7.526), the 
proposition that “the development of Semeiotic Theory is the first activity of 
scientific thinking” would seem to imply that it *is* the activity of 
philosophers (as well as thinkers in more specialized sciences). Yet you say 
that you “do not think this.” Should we infer then that the term “philosopher” 
for you denotes something other than a practitioner of “philosophy” as Peirce 
defined it? Or did you mean to say that Semeiotic theorizing is the first 
activity *not only* of philosophers but of all scientific thinkers?

One comment on your paraphrase of JR's opening:
[[ Semeiotic Theory, he says, must avoid the distinction between the empirical 
and the nonempirical, between experimental and the nonexperimental. ]] Yet JR 
does make this distinction explicitly, in paragraphs 9 and 10, in order that it 
may be “possible for us to regard *all* applied semiotics as empirical 
semiotics” [8 -- emphasis JR's]. This latter claim would be meaningless if 
there were no difference between empirical and non-empirical. JR's point, then, 
is not that Semeiotic Theory must avoid the distinction altogether, but that we 
must “disentangle the conceptions of the experiential, the experimental and the 
empirical from certain other complexes of ideas with which they have become 
associated” [1]. And that is what JR proceeds to do – after several paragraphs 
of beating about the bush of entanglements from which he wishes to free those 
conceptions.

One more question, regarding “Semeiotic Theory”: would you characterize your 
“technical excursion” on JR's paragraph [2] as an instance or an application of 
it? Or is it an excursion *from* “Semeiotic Theory”? For me at least, your 
answer might help to clarify your intention to “to lay a more rigorous 
foundation for the discussion of the rest of the paper,” as i'm finding it 
difficult to see the point of your “excursion.” 

Gary F.

} How do you know you are on the path? Reality checks you at every turn. [gnox] 
{

www.gnusystems.ca/Peirce.htm }{ gnoxic studies: Peirce



-----Original Message-----
Sent: November-06-11 1:08 AM

Dear List,

Herein begins the slow read of:

        On the Paradigm of Experience Appropriate for Semiotic by Joseph 
Ransdell
        http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/aboutcsp/ransdell/paradigm.htm

This paper was originally presented in 1980 and last modified as the above 
version in 1998.

I have delayed starting in order to review the notes that I have made in 
preparing for this reading. I want to ensure that my comments take into account 
the full context of the paper and in the past few days I have spent some more 
time with the paper in order to achieve this. 

I have also taken the opportunity to review comments that relate to this 
subject that Joe made in conversations with myself and others over the past 
decade on Peirce-l. Readers of this paper should also reference the following 
paper that was the subject of a slow read in July.

        Is Peirce a Phenomenologist?
        http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/aboutcsp/ransdell/phenom.htm

This paper provides an informal discussion of "categories of apprehension" and 
advocates, explores and clarifies the unified view of science and the nature of 
verification as advocated by Peirce and numerous thinkers that came after 
Peirce, notably Rudolf Carnap. 

Ransdell's approach is provocative. He begins:

"[1] The thesis of my paper is that it is doubtful that any distinction should 
be drawn between empirical and nonempirical semiotics or even between 
experimental and nonexperimental semiotics. Doing so tends to reproduce within 
the semiotics movement the present academic distinction between the sciences 
and the humanities which semiotics should aim at discouraging, rather than 
reinforcing. But to overcome this undesirable dichotomy, it is necessary to 
disentangle the conceptions of the experiential, the experimental and the 
empirical from certain other complexes of ideas with which they have become 
associated by accident rather than necessity."

I confess that on first reading the phrase "it is doubtful that" caused me some 
problems. I think it dilutes the impact of the paper and reveals a caution that 
I think is unnecessary. This is, I believe, because Ransdell is addressing a 
community of American philosophers, a European thinker would have been more 
confidently assertive. 

Ransdell here sees the development of Semeiotic Theory as the activity of 
"philosophers" and they are clearly his audience, so I should make it clear 
from the start - in order to contextualize my comments - that I do not think 
this. Semeiotic Theory is, for me, the first activity of scientific thinking. I 
further believe that it should be the first activity in mathematical thinking, 
though today it is not.

This is no criticism of Ransdell, I'm quite sure he would agree, but it is 
important to the reading of the paper and to understanding my comments.

In any case, what Ransdell says here is, on the face of it, radical. Semeiotic 
Theory, he says, must avoid the distinction between the empirical and the 
nonempirical, between experimental and the nonexperimental. Indeed, as the 
paper progresses Ransdell argues that these distinctions are simply ways of 
speaking - derived from convention - and unnecessary.

In my following comments concerning paragraph [2] I am going to take a 
technical excursion dealing with apprehension and then leave it at that for 
today. I do this in order to lay a more rigorous foundation for the discussion 
of the rest of the paper.

Continuing then:

"[2]  Things which are or become present to us, such that we can recall them 
sufficiently well to be able to refer to and describe them in some manner -- 
let us call these things "phenomena" -- are usually classified or classifiable 
by us as things sense-perceived, remembered, foreseen, dreamed, daydreamed, 
imagined, hallucinated, inferred, supposed, conceived, envisioned, and so 
forth. That is, they are classified in relation to what I will call, for want 
of a better phrase, "categories of apprehension." This, or a roughly similar 
classification scheme, is shared by the peoples of the contemporary Western 
world, and, of course, by a great many others who have become "Westernized," 
but it is not a "human universal"; for it is a classification of phenomena 
considered in relation to what we think of as our faculties of awareness, and 
although it may be debatable whether the idea that there are such things as 
faculties of this sort is a humanly universal idea, it is certain, in any case, 
that this particular set of ways of conceiving them is far from being 
universal. It is not even necessary to turn to anthropological evidence or to 
histories of non-Western civilizations in this connection, for even the ideas 
of remembering and foreseeing -- which are, on the face of it, the most likely 
candidates for universality in this set -- are implicitly qualified by their 
relations to conceptions of time and history which have developed well within 
the recorded history of Western culture, and most if not all of the rest could 
probably be shown to be just as clearly qualified in their meaning through 
their relation to specifically Western ways of regarding things."

Ransdell claims that our concept of “phenomena” as commonly differentiated into 
these “categories of apprehension” are, at least to some degree, qualified by 
cultural influences that are necessarily the product of social history. And 
what is more, our conception of history and time itself influence these 
conceptions and are themselves the product of cultural convention.

It seems necessary at this point to identify the universal properties of 
apprehension in order for us to make progress with this argument.

When considering which of the categories of apprehension have a universal 
nature Ransdell suggests that the basis of the conceptions “remembering” and 
“foreseeing” are the most likely candidates. I agree.

Let us attempt a more rigorous analysis of these ideas here. “Human universal” 
refers here to a conception that occurs in common form independent of cultural 
influence and despite any such influence.

We can argue that the notions of “order” and “specialized function,” for 
example, are encountered by the child in familial relationships. If a child is 
raised by parents in a social order in which the father is the provider and the 
mother is the caregiver there will naturally arise the notion of 
specialization. Whereas a child born to parents that share equally these tasks 
will anticipate less specialization of themselves and others.

Further, if a society values the effort of the provider over the effort of the 
caregiver (by awarding privilege to the one and not the other) then a sense or 
“order” will arise, the placement of one before another. And clearly there are 
numerous social relationships that may strengthen these senses of order and 
specialized function.

We may argue then that this is the power of “analogy.” We will view analogy 
here as the combined function of remembering and foreseeing, or more exactly 
the “recollection of similarity” as Carnap would have it.

What distinguishes memory and prediction (as I will prefer to call them) is 
that they do not arise by analogy but arise simply by human function or, more 
generally, by biophysical function.

Some conceptions derived by analogy, such as “order” and “specialized 
function,” may also be considered “universal.”

Let me note here, as a further example, the idea put forward by Kant that the 
notion of “space”  is a priori. I mention this here only to observe that the 
conceptions of analogy need not be socially influenced and that there are 
conceptions that naturally derive by analogy from the environment. The base 
notion of “location” or “relative placement” is one such conception.

I put aside, for the moment, existential questions except to say that neither 
“space” nor “time” have existential status in my model beyond their 
apprehension. So despite the universal nature of the relative spacial 
conceptions mentioned above I will argue that our notions of space and time are 
the product of cultural influence, our the universal conceptions derived from 
our experience of the world are shaped by the force of convention. And no one 
today should be surprised by this view since it is consistent with Mach and 
Einstein.

Similarly, We may also argue that both “order” and “specialized function” are 
conceptions that derive from our direct experience of the world. We see order 
in the world, there are environmental processes in which one event consistently 
occurs before another, and there is a repeatability of specialized function in 
the world.

I choose these examples because they have an additional feature, they are 
conceptions that arise by analogy from our direct experience of the 
environment. If we are denied this experience then they will not arise. They 
can then only arise by social convention. But under normal circumstances 
conceptions that arise from direct experience and social convention reinforce 
each other in the action of consensus building.

And so we are left with three base categories of apprehension that enable us to 
classify those mentioned by Ransdell, those which derive from basic human 
function, by the unified operation of these functions (analogy), and by direct 
experience of the world.

Since the basic biophysical function of our species is impossible to 
differentiate from other species then we must assume that these conceptions are 
present in all biophysics.

Where then do the influences of culture and convention fit in? These too are 
apprehended by direct experience of the world. What distinguishes them from our 
other experiences? Nothing at all, not even that practice we call “language.”

=====

With respect,
Steven

---------------------------------------------------------------------------------
You are receiving this message because you are subscribed to the PEIRCE-L 
listserv.  To remove yourself from this list, send a message to 
lists...@listserv.iupui.edu with the line "SIGNOFF PEIRCE-L" in the body of the 
message.  To post a message to the list, send it to PEIRCE-L@LISTSERV.IUPUI.EDU

Reply via email to