RE: psychoanalysisMy cousin is a philosopher and psychoanalyst. He is
associated with a hospital in Toronto as well as the U of  Toronto unless he
is retired by now. Here is a piece on truth in psychoanalysis. I always
thought that there were other theories of truth than just the correspondence
and coherence theory but I suppose the pragmatic theory could be just
considered a bunch of confusions  using a classic comics version of
coherence theory ie. it coheres equals it works in some sense.but the
semantic theory is at the least a very special type of correspondence theory
and then there is the redundancy theory that really doesnt seem to hold up
but is certainly distinct. This is long.

Cheers, Ken Hanly

http://www.psychomedia.it/rapaport-klein/hanly91.htm




The Concept of Truth in Psychoanalysis
Charles Hanly
[Paper presented on June 15, 1991, at the Annual Meeting of the
Rapaport-Klein Study Group]

Psychoanalysis is passing through a difficult period in its history
(Wallerstein, 1988). It is still unclear whether there will emerge further
splintering, further dilution, or a gradual re-unification and
re-integration (Rangell, 1988). This paper seeks to explore a core issue in
our current differences: the concept of truth in psychoanalysis.
Philosophers have advocated two different theories of truth: correspondence
and coherence. The correspondence theory states that truth consists of the
degree of correspondence between an object and its description. It assumes
that under normal conditions the human mind is able to gain knowledge of
objects by means of observation and its experimental refinement. This
observational knowledge can then be used to test beliefs and theories. The
correspondence theory is implied with oblique eloquence in Galileo's 'eppur
si muove' (see Drake, 1978, pp. 356-7). Neither his official recantation of
his astronomical discoveries, nor the majestic coherence of Ptolemaic
astronomy, nor its obvious agreement with experience, nor the consensus of
generations of scholars, could alter the fact that Galileo's observations of
the moon, planets, and sun had enabled him to describe much more accurately
what was actually happening in nature. This same view of truth and of
science has been held by the great seminal scientists: Harvey, Newton,
Darwin, Einstein, and Freud, and by scientists generally. The school of
thought in philosophy with which the correspondence concept of truth is
associated is realism: critics of correspondence would say naive realism;
advocates would say critical realism.
The coherence theory of truth adopts the view that of the question: 'What
objects does the world consist of? only makes sense within a theory or
description. Truth. is some sort of (idealized) rational acceptability -
some sort of ideal coherence of beliefs with each other and with our
experiences as those experiences are themselves represented in our belief
system - and not correspondence with mind-independent or
discourse-independent "states of affairs"' (Putnam, 1981, pp. 47-9). Thus
there may be more than one true description of the world. The correspondence
theory allows for only one. In effect the coherence theory abandons objects
as they actually are as the ground of truth for objects as they are
constructed or constituted by the belief and theory investments that govern
their observation and the way in which they are experienced by observers.
The mind must, as a matter of psychological and epistemological
inevitability, subject the objects which it seeks to know to the conditions
under which it is able to know them. The original form of this idea is
traceable to Kant (1781) although Kant was a scientific realist. Among its
modern adherents have been Bradley (1897), Merleau-Ponty (1945), Sartre
(1943), Ricoeur (1970), Habermas (1971), and the philosophers of science
Kuhn (1970), Feyerabend (1965), and Putnam (1981). The school of thought, in
philosophy, to which the coherence theory belongs is idealism.
Two further ideas tend to accompany the correspondence idea of truth: one
epistemological, the other ontological. The epistemological premise is that
objects are able to cause our senses to form more or less correct
observations of them as they actually are. These observations can be, or can
be made to be, sufficiently independent of theories held by observers
concerning their objects that theories can be objectively tested. The
ontological premise is that anyone's thoughts, and actions of any kind, are
caused. Minds are part of nature.
Similarly, two further ideas tend to be associated with the coherence idea
of truth. Epistemologically, it is assumed that our ways of thinking and
perceiving unavoidably condition what we observe. Objects are unable to
exert an independent influence upon our senses such as would enable us and
oblige us to correct our theory-laden ideas of them. Facts are theory-bound,
never theory-independent. Objects are amorphous and unintelligible in
themselves. They have no means by which to define themselves. They must wait
upon the definitions inherent in the theories we invent to try to understand
them. The ontological idea is that human beings are unique in nature on
account of a consciousness which supports the capacity for voluntary actions
of a special kind - actions which are motivated by reasons rather than by
causes. Minds constitute nature.
The idea of truth as coherence, of the intrinsic indefiniteness of persons
as objects of knowledge and of voluntarism, are logically interconnected in
the following way: if a person's actions are motivated by reasons which are
neither causes nor caused, if a person freely chooses his motives, then his
actions become at once immunized against the influence of his past and
unpredictable. Voluntarism is a source of an intrinsic indefiniteness of the
human mind which allows it always to slip away from any description that
would seek to correspond with some fixed and determinate nature. The link
between voluntarism and the indeterminacy of psychic life has been nicely
stated as follows:
It has often been said that one's past determines one's present and future.
Let it be underlined that one's present and future - how he commits himself
to existence at the moment - also determines his past (May, 1958, p. 88).
Present choice determines the meaning of the past and the motives of
actions. Psychic life ceases to be sufficiently determinate to be a suitable
object for descriptions whose truth resides in their correspondence with an
objective state of affairs.
Bound to this view is the hermeneutic, phenomenological, existential, and
idealist idea that self-consciousness involves the capacity for
self-transcendence. Self-transcendence allows for the abrogation of
causality, the transformation of motives as causes into sui generis reasons
at the disposal of consciousness. Thus Habermas (1971) claims that, when a
neurotic conflict is resolved, self-reflection has actually 'dissolved' or
'overcome' the causal connexion between the symptom or inhibition and the
repressed drive demands. Where psychic determinism was, the uncaused choice
shall be.
This constellation of ideas has found its way into contemporary
psychoanalytic theorizing, where it has been pressed into service in a
number of ways.
Sometimes there is an appeal to the coherence theory of truth as a means of
defending a theory against criticism. Goldberg (1976), (1988) has used the
coherence theory to defend self-psychology against its critics. The
philosophical idea that observations are theory-bound is used to explain
differences in clinical observation: when two individuals with roughly
similar neurophysiological equipment view the same thing or event and each
see it differently, it is not necessarily true that one is incompetent or
even wrong; rather it may be that they each observe with a different theory
(Goldberg, 1976, p. 67).
This idea also agrees with Putnam (1981) that there may be more than one
true theory about the same thing because the observations that confirm
theories are contaminated by the very theoretical concepts they confirm. As
Putnam states it, 'the very (experiential) inputs upon which our knowledge
is based are conceptually contaminated.' (p. 54). However three difficulties
arise when the coherence theory is used in this way. One: it is a
double-edged sword. The observations of classical analysts cannot falsify
self-psychology, but neither can the observations of self-psychology falsify
classical - or any other - theory (Hanly, 1983). Two: one and the same
patient can have a neurosis caused by a failure to resolve oedipal conflicts
when he is treated by a classical analyst, and a failure to find a suitable
object for idealization when he is treated by a self-psychologist (Kohut,
1971). The Oedipus complex is both a cause and not a cause - only a symptom.
This consequence defies an elementary principle of logic, the principle of
identity: nothing can be both p and not-p. Three: a scientific theory must
be falsifiable in principle. Goldberg's use of coherence implies that
neither self-psychology nor classical theory are scientific, since neither
has a domain of observations that could ever falsify it. This use of the
coherence theory results in theoretical solipsism and truth by conversion.
Goldberg (1988) has implicitly addressed these difficulties by considering
the conditions for theory testing in psychoanalysis. Goldberg suggests a
pragmatic test although, unlike scientific pragmatic testing, this form of
testing requires 'commitment' over time to the theory being tested (p. 27).
This requirement opens the door to the claim by adherents of a theory that
falsifying observations are the result of a lack of such 'commitment'. It is
of interest for our argument, however, that in the end Goldberg indirectly
appeals to correspondence. If, for example, we are to be able to carry out
the injunction to 'remain alert to the effects of our observations' (p. 110)
we must be able to make observations of objects that are not subject to
these effects. This crucial issue will be further considered below.
Spence (1982a), (1982b), despite some ambiguity, comes down in favour of
coherence as the criterion of truth in psychoanalysis when he claims that
'the analyst functions more as a pattern-maker than a pattern-finder.' and
goes on to refer to analyses as 'artistic masterpieces'. This account agrees
with the notion that a present intention or perception interprets the past -
that there is no discrete, specific, particular past which continues to be
what it was; there are only the diverse perspectives on the past brought
about by the intentions inherent in current projects, moods, affects,
attitudes, and theories. The idea that the meaning of a person's past, as
well as its influence upon his current life, is determined by present
choices is very different from the idea that contemporary affective
experiences activate chains of associated memories leading back to infantile
precursors. The latter idea assumes that memories thus reactivated have
inherent meaning that remains the same even if its conscious recall does
not; the former idea assumes that memories are a kind of opaque mass than
can be redesigned and informed with meaning by present intentions and
investments: that is, by volitions conceived as uncaused causes.
These ideas belong with those of Habermas (1971) and Ricoeur (1974), (1981).
Habermas (1971) advanced the view that psychoanalytic 'self-reflection' is
able to suspend or transcend psychic causality.
Although some self-psychologists may not agree with his position, Kohut
(1959) rested his theorizing on the coherence theory premise of
indeterminacy:
What we experience as freedom of choice, as decision, and the like, is an
expression of the fact that the I-experience and a core of activities
emanating from it cannot at present be divided into further components. They
are, therefore, beyond the law of motivation, i.e., beyond the law of
psychic determinism (p. 232).
Psychic causation becomes a product of self-disintegration along with the
Oedipus complex. The cohesive self rises above the bounds of causality.
Kohut (1977), in explicit agreement with Habermas (1971), introduced the
idea of the mutuality of observer and observed in order to claim on behalf
of self-psychology a more fundamental knowledge of human nature than that of
psychoanalysis. Kohut's concept of empathy disallows the degree of epistemic
independence of subject and object required by correspondence. Goldberg
(1988) has extensively elaborated the epistemological implications of the
self-psychological version of empathy. Ricoeur (1974) asserted, in line with
Habermas, that 'there are no "facts" nor any observation of "facts" in
psychoanalysis but rather the interpretation of a narrated history' (p.
186). And although Ricoeur (1981) intended to abandon his earlier (1970)
view that reasons and motives are sui generis, he failed to do so in so far
as he continued to conceive of the relation between unconscious wishes and
dreams, neurotic symptoms, or parapraxes as one of referring, denoting,
signifying: that is, as an a-causal, semantic relation. Ricoeur (1981)
appealed to coherence in a particularly naive and unsatisfactory form: 'a
good psychoanalytic explanation must be coherent with the theory or, if one
prefers, it must conform to Freud's psychoanalytic system' (p. 271). Such a
dictum makes nonsense of the clinical testing of his ideas which Freud
advocated.
The relationship of the concept of causality to the problem of truth in
psychoanalysis is also raised by Schafer (1976), (1978) and Klein (1976).
Schafter (1978) asserts that 'thinking historically, we do not say an agent
is causally motivated to perform some action . we say that this agent did
that and perhaps gave or could have given these reasons for doing so.' (p.
56). Like Klein, Schafer wants to deny that reasons, intentions, purposes,
wishes, motives in general, are causes. Schafer and Klein erroneously
identify causality with fatalism as did Sartre (1943). Schafer and Klein are
also committed to a coherence theory of truth.
There are more ways than one to understand reality (Schafter, 1976). Reality
is not, as Freud usually assumed, a definite thing to be arrived at or a
fixed and known criterion of objectivity (Schafter, 1978, p. 66).
Once motives become reasons rather than causes they acquire a wonderfully
amorphous, open-textured nature which allows them to be 'correctly'
construed in a variety of ways. Interpretation is an expansion and
complication of the context of an action. Different theories expand and
complicate the context differently. Narrative coherence becomes the
operative criterion of truth. There are as many true understandings as there
are coherent, comprehensive, unified narratives about the motivating
reasons.
Schafer (1978) states the ontological basis for this relativism: 'the
concept of action requires us to regard each action as inherently
spontaneous, as starting from itself' (pp. 48-9). This astonishing assertion
certainly provides the basis for a 'free' construal of the reasons for an
action. But if actions are not the outcome of past and present events but
really are free creations, as Kant (1785) believed of morally willed
actions - actions which have consequences but no antecedents - then they do
not have a history at all. Schafer's position is the same as the
existentialist view of Sartre (1943) despite Schafer's (1976) disavowal, and
it is fundamentally at odds with the view of Ryle (1949), upon whose ideas
Schafter otherwise has relied for his attack on Freud's metapsychology.
Schafer's concept of action provides no justification for widening the
context of an action to earlier events and actions (conscious or
unconscious); it provides a justification for a life history that is no more
than a phenomenological chronology. Anything more, if, indeed, every action,
as Schafer claims, spontaneously starts from itself, would be sheer
invention: an invention for which the only possible criterion of truth would
be coherence. This idea provides unlimited opportunity for Spence's
pattern-making.
A number of considerations lend credence to the coherence criterion of truth
for psychoanalysis. Freud appears to have espoused coherence. Freud often
(1895, pp. 194-5), (and 1909, pp. 165-9, for example) testified to his
awareness of the complex, seemingly arbitrary, fragmentary, subtle, evasive
mass of material produced by associations. Is not this material typically so
ambiguous, so rife with uncertainties, that the best we can achieve is a
coherent account with the possibility of other no less coherent accounts
being constructed? In apparent support of Goldberg, Freud (1915) pointed out
that even at the earliest stages of description a new science already
applies concepts that are not drawn altogether from the field of observation
to which the descriptions apply (p. 117). Freud (1927) remarked that 'a
number of very remarkable, disconnected facts are brought together . into a
consistent whole' (p. 23) by his 'Totem and taboo' hypothesis. Given the
multiple variables at work in the clinical situation, which in this regard
only reflects the human situation; given the complex, shifting nature of
transference; given the difficulty of sorting out what the patient has
innocently suffered at the hands of others, what he has provoked, what he
has only fantasized, and with what he has been complicit . is it not
heuristically judicious to adopt a concept of truth that refuses to lay
claim to an objectivity that is not attainable?
Moreover, does not an analysis bring about changes in the meaning that
events in the patients' pasts have for them in the present and future? - for
example, a woman who was unable adequately to enter into, let alone resolve,
the conflicts of the oedipal stage but who manages to do so in the
transference comes, in the course of this experience, to remember her father
as a sexually exciting object when, during childhood, she had experienced
him only as an indifferent, zombie-like figure who was silent and remote. Is
not this routine clinical experience evidence for Spence's 'pattern-making',
for Ricoeur's 'narrated history', for Habermas' 'self-reflection', for the
determination of the past by investments in the present and the concept of
truth in psychoanalysis as coherent narration?
Moreover, the current state of psychoanalytic theory lends plausibility to
the idea of coherence. There is no unified theory. There are only divergent,
often mutually inconsistent theories supported by clinical observations.
Does not this state of affairs cohere rather well with the coherence theory?
Perhaps there are as many true life histories as there are theories that can
give a consistent account of them?
Attractive as these possibilities are in certain respects, to these
questions I believe the answer is No. The description above of the
uncertainty of associations is tendentious and incomplete. Even when a
patient is filling the hour with reports of manifest dream contents to the
exclusion of associations, the details of the material are clear and
determinate. There is nothing indefinite or illusive about it. Of course, it
is unintelligible and uninterpretable in the absence of associations; but
this fact has itself an obvious interpretation. The patient is anxiously
clinging to the manifest dream content. This interpretation, properly timed
and expressed and linked to the transference, will begin a process of change
that will enable the patient to begin associating to his dreams. These
associations will then also be determinate and discrete. If they are
incomplete - as they are likely to be - it will be because further
resistances are at work. If they become vague and uncertain it is for the
same reason. Vagueness and uncertainty are themselves determinate states of
affairs that have an explanation. They are not characteristic qualities of
mental contents and states as such. The same is true of fantasies, memories,
character traits, etc. Pattern-making by the analyst is not required so long
as resistances and defences are interpreted in such a way as to allow the
intrinsic forces at work in the psychic life of the patient to make
themselves known. These forces will determine the pattern as they will
determine the transference. The forces in question are the drives, their
vicissitudes and their derivatives. The ideas of pattern-making, of
theory-bound observation, and the like are rationalizations for
countertransferential resistance to the threats posed by the drives, that
is, by the instinctual unconscious. It is for this reason that
psychoanalytic adherents of coherence have to find some way to banish them
conceptually. Psychoanalytic theories that repudiate the drives are also
likely to employ coherence as a concept of truth. Freud (1900), (1923) was
certainly aware of the complexity of dreams and the extent to which they are
representative of all mental phenomena; however Freud (Dora, 1905) also
believed that the obscurities of a dream can be cleared up, that each
manifest element can be traced along the paths of displacement and
condensation from whence it came and that the meaning of the dream is to be
found in the unconscious wishes of the dreamer. We are not always able to
find the meaning, but it is there to be found, independently of any
pattern-making activity on the part of the analyst. The task of
interpretation as Freud conceived it is to make the interpretation
correspond with the operative unconscious wishes of the dreamer - wishes
that have a definite nature of their own. (For an opposing view see
Viderman, 1970, 1972).
It is also true that Freud appreciated the extent to which any inquiry has
to be guided by preliminary ideas. In this respect Freud's grasp of
epistemology was more realistic and empirical than that of Bacon (1620), the
great founder of modern empiricism. But Freud also thought that these
preliminary ideas can and must be continually criticized and made to reflect
the facts of observation more accurately. From the need to have a theory
that will enable us to make predictions about what we will observe in order
to make systematic observations, it does not follow that these predictions
must govern what we will find. The preliminary ideas Harvey had concerning
the circulation of the blood did not add or subtract anything from his
crucial measurement of the amount of blood ejected by the heart in a single
pulse. Hawking's (1988) mathematical derivation which proves, on current
thermodynamic and quantum assumptions, that black holes emit particles does
not affect the observations that will now have to be made on cosmic
radiation to test the empirical truth of this derivation. Freud's prediction
of the incidence of infantile seduction required by his seduction theory did
not in some subtle way influence the number of such occurrences or Freud's
ability to estimate them. Adequately formulated scientific theories or
common-sense beliefs yield predictions and give rise to expectations that
can be tested by observing what actually happens. These observations have
meaning in their own right, independently of the theories or beliefs we have
about their objects.
Freud (1927) defended science against those philosophers who assert that all
knowledge claims, whether religious or scientific, are ultimately equal
because they are equally subjective. Our observations, it was argued then as
now, are inevitably conditioned by what we believe and how we observe. As we
have shown above, various psychoanalysts are now advocates of variants of
this idea of truth. Freud offered three arguments (biological,
methodological, and epistemological) on behalf of scientific realism. Mental
activities have developed in order to explore the world; it is likely that
they have acquired a structure that facilitates that exploration (the
biological argument). These mental activities are a part of the world; they
can, themselves, be investigated in order to discover their degree of
facility, its causes, and methods of improvement (the methodological
argument). Scientific knowledge, because of its methods, is determined not
only by our mental activities and their structures but, primarily, by the
objects observed (the epistemological argument). I have elsewhere (Hanly,
1983), (1988) set out supporting evidence from cultural history for Freud's
biological argument. His methodological and epistemological arguments are
supported by evidence from the history of science. Science has been able to
identify and to take into account the influence of our sensory apparatus
upon our experience of nature. Copernicus and Galileo discovered the
influence of the earth's daily rotation upon our observation of stars and
planets and, by correcting for it, they were able to construct a genuinely
objective description of the solar system. Einstein's invention of
relativity theory enabled the human mind to realize that the self-evident
rectilinearity of space is only a consequence of the organization of our
sensory apparatus. Psychoanalysis has made its own contribution to this
process of observational 'correction' for the field of human phenomena.
These examples indicate that the expediency of the adaptation of the human
sensory apparatus and thought activity to reality brought about by
environmental pressure has been sufficient to allow it to proceed beyond the
requirements of survival.
Freud employed a coherence criterion within the framework of his realist
epistemology. Nowhere is the use of coherence more evident than in his
effort to prove the objective reality of the Wolf Man's primal scene (1918).
But even though his interpretation makes coherent sense of the details of
the Wolf Man's infantile history and its connexion with both his infantile
and adult neuroses, Freud does not claim that he had succeeded in proving
that the primal scene was an occurrence rather than a fantasy. A crucial
fact concerning the Gruska scene (the boy's urination) could only be
established inferentially. Similarly, Freud only claimed that his hypothesis
in 'Totem and taboo' was more plausible than existing theories and that it
probably contained some measure of truth. He did not claim either that its
coherence made it true or that such coherence constituted a limit beyond
which knowledge could not reach. Freud used coherence as a necessary but not
a sufficient criterion of truth. He took correspondence to be necessary and
sufficient. Freud used coherence as a formal, logical criterion and
correspondence as a material, epistemological criterion. Correspondence is
built into the foundations of psychoanalysis. It is part of the meaning of
the reality principle.
Yet Freud may have been in error. And, in any case, it would be to argue
fallaciously from authority to treat as evidence what Freud believed rather
than to weight the force of the arguments on which his view was based. Here
are two additional arguments, one drawn from mathematics and physical
science and one drawn from psychoanalysis.
Euclidean geometry is a mathematical system which is complete and completely
coherent. For this reason it escapes Gödel's theorem. Yet it turns out that
it does not describe the space of the universe. Physics has been able to
identify facts which show this to be the case. The axioms of Euclidean
geometry were believed to be self-evidently true. Plato, Descartes, and
Leibniz considered them to be innate to the mind. Kant considered them to be
a priori conditions of experience. Yet despite this self-evidence and
coherence, and despite the fact that we actually do observe the world in a
Euclidean fashion, these axioms have been shown by relativity physics to be
approximations suitable only to regions of space smaller than the solar
system.
Psychoanalysis is familiar, in the psychoses, with systems of belief,
observation, and behavior that are remarkable both for their coherence and
for their detachment from reality. The following bit of case history is
representative. A psychotic student in a university seminar experienced
growing agitation when certain topics were under discussion while the sounds
of shuffling feet were accompanied by the sounds of a streetcar passing
under the windows. This agitation cohered perfectly with his belief that
such conjunctions of sounds signalled the approach of evil forces at work in
his Manichean cosmos. Coherent as well with his beliefs were the ritual
precautions he undertook to oppose the advance of those forces. Nowhere are
the shortcomings of coherence as a sufficient criterion of truth more
forcefully demonstrated than in our own field. Just as an argument may be
valid and yet have a false conclusion, so a system of beliefs or a narrative
may be coherent but false. The concept of coherence is not sufficient to
bridge the gap between ideas and objects.
Moreover, psychoanalytic findings offer a defence against one of the
philosophical criticisms of the correspondence theory. Putnam (1981) has
argued that realism requires, in addition to the observer and the observed,
a third party to whom reference can be made in order to compare the
observer's perception with the object independently of the observer. How
else could we form a judgment about its correspondence? Since the human
observer is not in a position to form this judgement, realism is flawed with
the hidden theological assumption of a God whose perception of objects is
the ideal against which human perceptions can be measured.
But psychoanalysis has shown that this third-party observer is none other
than the human observer himself. During the period of the pre-oedipal
anaclitic bond, children, while having their own perceptions of things, use
their idealized parents to carry out the very function assigned to God by
Putnam's argument. Parental perceptions are taken to be authoritative - the
standard against which children are able to measure their own experience.
Certain ego regressed patients continue to have to establish a relation with
an idealized figure because they cannot trust the evidence of their own eyes
unless vouched for and authenticated by an authority. Even Harvey had to
attribute his discovery of the truth about the circulatory system to Galen,
in whose works no such idea is to be found. Psychoanalysis (Freud, 1923) ;
(Waelder, 1934) ; (Hanly, 1979) has shown that the identifications involved
in the resolution of the Oedipus complex normally bring into play a capacity
for critical self-awareness that includes the perception of objects. An
individual acquires the ability sufficiently to objectify his own
perceptions and beliefs to enable him to consider to what extent they
correspond with and are adequate to the object and to what extent they are
not. This capacity forms the psychological ground for critical common sense
and for scientific realism. The reality principle requires neither the
alleged olympianism of correspondence nor the demiurge of coherence.
In psychoanalysis, through sympathetic identification clarified by
countertransference awareness, this same self-critical capacity can
facilitate our search after an understanding of our patients in their terms
rather than our own. The complement of this self-critical receptive
observation on the part of the analyst is the struggle for self-honesty in
the analysand. The view that an analysis consists of a mutual construction
by analyst and analysand of the analysand's life fails to do justice to this
struggle. There are analysands who have been able to use the analytic
process to discover more about themselves, to recover more of their past and
find ways to reconcile themselves with it, than their analysts could
comprehend. Fortunately for our profession and for our patients the process
that the analyst facilitates can yield for the analysand a degree of
resolving self-knowledge and improved functioning that exceeds those of his
analyst. There is a common human nature, although to be sure not in the form
of an Aristotelian essence, that exists in nature, that awaits our better
understanding. It is embodied in the lives lived by individuals. These
individual lives are part of nature. They are there to be known, however
difficult that may be. The self-honesty of an analysand in his realization
that he feared his father because he wanted to murder him, or of an
analysand in her realization that her frigidity and the pleasure she took in
rape fantasies was caused by her wish to use intercourse to castrate the
man, implies that these realizations correspond with real wishes that
continue to influence the individual's life. Neither the pain of those
realizations nor their beneficial effects can be accounted for by any other
assumption. In the end, each person has only his own life to live, however
shared with others. At the core of the being of each person there is a
solitude in which he is related to himself. Truth resides in this solitude
to the extent that one can remember one's own past as it actually was. The
ground of genuine analytic work in the analyst is his attitude of respect
for this solitude.
SUMMARY
A philosophical controversy concerning the nature of truth has begun to play
an important part in psychoanalytic theorizing. The two major philosophical
notions, the coherence and the correspondence theories and their use in
psychoanalytic theory making, are examined. It is argued that although
coherence is part of the criteria of truth, correspondence is the more
essential and fundamental criterion. It was in this way that Freud used
these concepts in creating psychoanalysis. Psychoanalytic discoveries
concerning the psychogenesis of objectivity in perception and thought
support the correspondence theory of truth and provide, in addition, an
answer to the third party critique of correspondence. The correspondence
theory as a basic attitude of mind is a necessary element in the respect for
the patient upon which psychoanalytic therapy depends.
REFERENCES
BACON, F. (1620) Novum organum. In Philosophers from Bacon to Mill ed. E. A.
Burtt. New York: The Modern Library, 1939
BRADLEY, F. H. (1897) Appearance and Reality London: Swan & Sonnenschein.
DRAKE, S. (1978) Galileo at Work: His Scientific Biography Chicago: Univ.
Chicago Press.
FEYERABEND, P. (1965) Problems of empiricism. In Beyond the Edge of
Certainty: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy ed. R. G. Colodny.
FREUD, S. (1895) Studies in hysteria S.E. 2
FREUD, S. (1900) The interpretation of dreams S.E. 4 & 5
FREUD, S. (1905) Fragment of an analysis of a case of hysteria S.E. 7
FREUD, S. (1909) Notes upon a case of obsessional neurosis S.E. 10
FREUD, S. (1912-13) Totem and taboo S.E. 13
FREUD, S. (1915) Instincts and their vicissitudes S.E. 14
FREUD, S. (1918) From the history of an infantile neurosis S.E. 17
FREUD, S. (1923) Remarks on the theory and practice of dream-interpretation
S.E. 19
FREUD, S. (1927) The future of an illusion S.E. 21
GOLDBERG, A. (1976) A discussion of the paper by C. Hanly and J. Masson, 'A
critical examination of the new narcissism' Int. J. Psychoanal. 57 67-70
GOLDBERG, A. (1988) A Fresh Look at Psychoanalysis: The View from
Self-Psychology Hillsdale: The Analytic Press.
HABERMAS, J. (1971) Knowledge and Human Interests trans. J. J. Shapiro.
Boston: Beacon Press.
HANLY, C. (1979) Existentialism and Psychoanalysis New York: Int. Univ.
Press.
HANLY, C. (1983) A problem of theory testing Int. Rev. Psychoanal. 10
393-405
HANLY, C. (1985) Logical and conceptual problems of existential psychiatry
J. Nervous & Mental Disease 173 263-81
HANLY, C. (1986) Review of The Assault on Truth: Freud's Suppression of the
Seduction Theory and In the Freud Archives. Int. J. Psychoanal. 67 517-19
HANLY, C. (1988) From animism to rationalism In Philosophy, History and
Social Action: Essays in Honour of Lewis Feuer ed. S. Hook, W. L. O'Neill &
R. O'Toole. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Pub., pp. 221-34
HAWKING, S. (1988) A Brief History of Time New York: Bantam Books.
KANT, I. (1781) Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason trans. N. K. Smith.
London: Macmillan, 1950
KANT, I. (1785) Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals trans. H. J. Paton.
London: Hutchinson, 1947
KLEIN, G.S. (1976) Psychoanalytic Theory New York: Int. Univ. Press.
KOHUT, H. (1959) Introspection, empathy, and psychoanalysis: An examination
of the relationship between mode of observation and theory In The Search for
the Self Volume 1 ed. P. H. Ornstein. New York: Int. Univ. Press, 1978 pp.
205-32
KOHUT, H. (1971) The Analysis of the Self New York: Int. Univ. Press.
KOHUT, H. (1977) The Restoration of the Self New York: Int. Univ. Press.
KUHN, T. S. (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Second edition,
enlarged. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press.
MAY, R. (1958) Contributions of existential psychotherapy In Existence: A
New Dimension in Psychiatry and Psychology ed. R. May. New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1967 pp. 37-91
MERLEAU-PONTY, M. (1945) Phenomenology of Perception trans. C. Smith.
London: Routledge & Kegan Pual, 1962
PUTNAM, H. (1981) Reason, Truth and History Cambridge: Cambridge Univ.
Press.
RANGELL, L. (1988) The future of psychoanalysis: The scientific crossroads
Psychoanal. Q. 57 313-40
RICOEUR, P. (1970) Freud and Philosophy New Haven: Yale Univ. Press.
RICOEUR, P. (1974) The Conflict of Interpretations ed. D. Ihde. Evanston:
Northwestern Univ. Press.
RICOEUR, P. (1981) Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences trans. J. B.
Thompson. New York: Cambridge Univ. Press.
RYLE, G. (1949) The Concept of Mind London: Hutchinson's Univ. Library.
SARTRE, J.-P. (1943) Being and Nothingness trans. H. E. Barnes. New York:
Philosophical Library, 1956
SCHAFER, R. (1976) A New Language for Psychoanalysis New York: Yale Univ.
Press.
SCHAFER, R. (1978) Language and Insight New Haven: Yale Univ. Press.
SPENCE, D. (1982a) Narrative Truth and Historical Truth: Meaning and
Interpretation in Psychoanalysis New York: W. W. Norton.
SPENCE, D. (1982b) Narrative truth and theoretical truth Psychoanal. Q. 51
43-69
VIDERMAN, S. (1970) La construction de l'espace analytique Paris: Denoel.
VIDERMAN, S. (1972) Comme un miroir, obscurément. Nouv. Rev. Psychoanal. 5
131-152
WAELDER, R. (1934) The problem of freedom in psychoanalysis and the problem
of reality testing In Psychoanalysis: Observation, Theory, Application New
York: Int. Univ. Press, 1976 pp. 101-20
WALLERSTEIN, R. S. (1988) One psychoanalysis or many? Int. J. Psychoanal. 69
5-21
[Note: A version of this paper was presented at the 36th International
Psychoanalytic Congress, Rome, July 1989, and appeared in The International
Journal of Psychoanalysis, 1990, 71: 375-383. It appeared also as the first
chapter of Charles Hanly's book The Problem of Truth in Applied
Psychoanalysis, New York: Guilford Press, 1991. We thank the The
International Journal of Psychoanalysis for the permission. Copyright ©
Institute of Psychoanalysis.]



Web Editor: Paolo Migone. For suggestions or corrections, please e-mail to:
[EMAIL PROTECTED]
PSYCHOMEDIA --> HOME PAGE RAPAPORT-KLEIN STUDY GROUP --> HOME PAGE


----- Original Message -----
From: Devine, James
To: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Sent: Thursday, June 12, 2003 4:42 PM
Subject: Re: psychoanalysis


[was:  Skewering stilted language and theory: F. Crews]
Carrol writes: > Actually, psychoanalysis has virtually disappeared from
psychiatry and serious neuro-science. It survives only in literary criticism
and among those marxists Timpanaro described as believing the "Freud never
made a mistake." ...<
Not knowing what we were doing, we sent my son (who has Asperger's syndrome
and ADD) to a psychoanalyst for awhile (luckily paid for by the state of
California). The shrink believed in Bruno Bettelheim's discredited theory
that autism (of which Asperger's is a variant) is a result of the
"refrigerator Mom" (not enough attention to the kid). Not only that, but he
seem to have encouraged my son's tendency toward psychosis (which has
luckily been since counteracted by other professionals). Further, he wanted
to start seeing my son 4 times a week!
I used to think that Freudian psychoanalysis played the progressive role of
redistributing income from the neurotic rich with lots of time to those with
advanced academic degrees, but this role has been totally eclipsed for me.
------------------------
Jim Devine [EMAIL PROTECTED] &  http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/~jdevine

Reply via email to