My question is a bit different than the one Hillel posed. Suppose the religious exemption permitting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation in places of public accommodation/employment is broader than exemptions provided to religious objectors who believe they are required to discriminate on the basis of race, gender, or religion. Does that exemption discriminate on the basis of faith or denomination in that it provides greater protection to religious objectors whose beliefs prohibit them from serving or hiring gays and lesbians than it provides to religious objectors whose beliefs prohibit them from serving or hiring women, or African-Americans, or Jews? What standard of review should be applied to this challenge?
There are lots of cases in which members of religions that require the use of marijuana argued that the government discriminated on the basis of religion when it granted an exemption for the ritual use of peyote but refused to grant an exemption for the ritual use of marijuana. They almost always lost. The courts adjudicating these cases weren't always clear what standard of review they were applying or even whether they were applying a standard of review at all. But they seemed to think it was necessary to explain why an exemption for marijuana use was different and less justified than an exemption for peyote use. And these discussions typically involved an argument that an exemption for marijuana use was more dangerous and created more problems for law enforcement than an exemption for peyote use. Should a similar analysis apply here? And if so, what arguments should a court accept to justify providing greater protection to religious objectors to civil rights laws protecting gays and lesbians than are provided to religious objectors to civil rights laws protecting women , racial minorities, or religious minorities? There is, of course, an argument that civil rights laws protecting African-Americans have a unique value and purpose in light of American history. But what about laws prohibiting gender and religious discrimination? Alan ________________________________ From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu <religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu> on behalf of Doug Laycock <dlayc...@virginia.edu> Sent: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 7:01 AM To: 'Law & Religion issues for Law Academics' Subject: RE: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny Strict scrutiny would not be triggered under Smith/Lukumi, principally because the legislated exemptions are for religious objectors, do not discriminate on the basis of faith or denomination, and are a reasonable legislative effort to exempt the cases where the claim to religious exemption is strongest. Therefore, they do not imply a value judgment that secular reasons for exemption are more important than religious reasons for exemption. They imply only a judgment that religious reasons for exemption are stronger in very small businesses that generally are personally run by the owner than in larger and generally more impersonal businesses. Of course that generalization is not perfect, and the precise line drawn between large and small is inevitably arbitrary. But there is no discrimination between religious and secular. Douglas Laycock Robert E. Scott Distinguished Professor of Law University of Virginia Law School 580 Massie Road Charlottesville, VA 22903 434-243-8546 From: religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu [mailto:religionlaw-boun...@lists.ucla.edu] On Behalf Of Hillel Y. Levin Sent: Wednesday, February 25, 2015 5:53 AM To: Law & Religion issues for Law Academics Subject: Anti-discrimination, legislative compromise, and strict scrutiny Friends: As you are likely aware, the LDS church recently announced support for legislation prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation in Utah, so long as such legislation included religious accommodations. LDS leaders were not explicit about the precise contours of the accommodations they seek, but I have the distinct sense that they would insist on broader accommodations than have been written into law elsewhere. Suppose that supporters of anti-discrimination legislation were able to accept a compromise with LDS leaders that included accommodations for some for-profit service providers/employers/landlords so long as gays and lesbians could find alternative providers without much difficulty. (Similar to pharmacist conscience clauses with respect to dispensation of contraception in some states.) Alternatively, suppose that categorical exceptions were carved out for small businesses and small-time landlords. Hypothetically, what if businesses with fewer than 20 employees were excluded from coverage, as were landlords with fewer than 5 properties. Now suppose that a religious objector who did not meet the criteria for the religious accommodation or categorical exception sued under the FEC. Given the exceptions built into the compromise legislation, would strict scrutiny automatically apply, under the theory that with the compromise legislation, the law is not generally applicable? And if so, how would the case come out, given that the compromise legislation necessarily drew somewhat arbitrary lines? I am aware that the question of what triggers strict scrutiny is subject to considerable debate in the literature, and that those who require a showing of animus to trigger Lukumi's strict scrutiny would not find any here. But for those who do not believe that animus is required, how would this come out? My sense is that this difficulty might stand in the way of any legislative compromise. -- Hillel Y. Levin Associate Professor University of Georgia School of Law 120 Herty Dr. Athens, GA 30602 (678) 641-7452 hle...@uga.edu<mailto:hle...@uga.edu> hillelle...@gmail.com<mailto:hillelle...@gmail.com> SSRN Author Page: http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_dev/AbsByAuth.cfm?per_id=466645
_______________________________________________ To post, send message to Religionlaw@lists.ucla.edu To subscribe, unsubscribe, change options, or get password, see http://lists.ucla.edu/cgi-bin/mailman/listinfo/religionlaw Please note that messages sent to this large list cannot be viewed as private. Anyone can subscribe to the list and read messages that are posted; people can read the Web archives; and list members can (rightly or wrongly) forward the messages to others.