Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-19 Thread James J. Roper
Warren,

If you want succinct, then I believe Endler does the job:

If you have:

1. Phenotypic vaiability that
2. comes from genotypic variability, and that gives
3. Differential reproductive success (due to that phenotypic 
variability).  We call this fitness.

Then you will have natural selection, which is just a different genotype 
frequency in subsequent generation.  If that continues in the same way 
for generations, then we are likely to have Evolution by Natural 
Selection.  These are all necessary and sufficient conditions for 
natural selection.  We can also see that fitness differences CAN come 
from competition, but they do not HAVE to.

And, we must remember that while Darwin coined the term, he knew nothing 
of genetics, which  has come a long way since then.  And, there was the 
New Synthesis that put Darwin's ideas into a more modern framework, with 
Fischer, White, Mayr.  And, then, we have Dawkins and Gould, who might 
have argued between themselves, but who, by reading, WE can all come to 
understand evolution better.

Cheers,

Jim

Warren W. Aney wrote:
 I've been trying to follow this discussion with little profit until I read
 this last posting from Wirt Atmar.  This is the most intelligent, succinct,
 evocative and accesible (and inspiring) explanation I've ever read on the
 topic of basic evolution.  Maybe it's old-hat to evolutionary biologists,
 but it's going to be part of this wildlife ecologist's permanent lexicon.

 Thanks, Wirt, for persisting on this topic.

 Warren Aney
 Senior Wildlife Ecologist
 Tigard, OR

 -Original Message-
 From: Ecological Society of America: grants, jobs, news
 [mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] Behalf Of Wirt Atmar
 Sent: Tuesday, 18 July, 2006 14:20
 To: ECOLOG-L@LISTSERV.UMD.EDU
 Subject: Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection


 Dan writes:

   
 I am not an expert on evolution (far from it) but I have a
 hunch that relates to Hutchinson's quote and analogy about
 the evolutionary play in the ecological theater.
 

 Let me say that you can do no wrong by reading and memorizing G. Evelyn
 Hutchinson, and especially his student, Robert MacArthur.

 The metaphor I tend to use however invokes a different art form, that of a
 movie. The study of ecology, which entails investigations into the totality
 of
 the biotic interactions we find on earth, is like the last, current frame of
 a
 movie that has been running at 24 frames per second for the last several
 hundred years.

 When we do ecology, we're looking only at the last frame of the movie.
 Ecology is evolution in now time, captured in the current frame, but no
 matter how
 intricately we tease apart the ecological physics of those interactions in
 this last frame, the interactions will never make complete sense unless they
 are
 examined over the course of the entire movie.

 The ghosts of competitions past, where pronghorn antelope run at high
 speed
 from a cheetah that's no longer present on the North American plains, is as
 good an example as we have of the necessity of imposing time into our
 studies,
 making Hutchinson's the evolutionary play in the ecological theater phrase
 all the more relevant.

 Why are developing these metaphors important? On one hand, saying all of
 this
 is obvious. On the other, these discussions have almost no practical value
 when you're in the field, taking detailed measurements. But science
 doesn't
 mean data. The mathematician Henri Poincare wrote, Science is built of
 facts
 the way a house is built of bricks, but an accumulation of facts is no more
 science than a pile of bricks is a house.

 Science literally means understanding, and without developing these
 perspectives, we really don't understand much of anything. Evolving truly
 accurate
 mental metaphors and models is fundamental to doing science, of any stripe.

 Saying this, what then of the idea of the evolutionary algorithm? In that
 regard, you write:

   
  My hunch combined with your analogy below of evolution as
  algorithm might be considered ecology as operating system.
  This focuses on ecology at the ecosystem and biosphere level.
  Your description of the algorithm seems to explain and
  characterize selection well, but it does not seem to account
  for 1) generation of novelty, other than via random or
  error-related mutation, 2) feedbacks that result when the
  organisms and communities/ecosystems alter the environment
  and then have to adapt to their own alterations (as studied
  in niche construction and ecosystem engineers) and
  3) the infrastructure and maintenance of elements, energy,
  materials that make the instantiation or materialization of
  new forms (actors) possible, participates in juxtaposing
  them in new plays and cleans up the mess after the play
  (i.e. decomposition and recycling) so that the theater is
  not cluttered from past performances. I could convert these
  to algorithm or application/program vs operating system
  examples relation

Re: Evolution Environment Adaptation Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-19 Thread James J. Roper
Joerg,

I like your analogy, and many studies have compared fitness landscapes 
to your topography that you describe here.

Note, those are fitness landscapes, not Natural Selection 
landscapes.  So, if you are in a wide flat plane, you might compare that 
to Gould's equilibrium in his context of punctuated equilibrium.  
That is, no natural selection is taking place.  You may go extinct 
because you run out of space, a disease comes along and so forth, but, 
no natural selection needs to be taking place.
 An analogy from maths (where I come from): in global optimization, if 
 you are on a wide flat plane and you have no clue in which direction to go 
 to find the valley, you are stuck with the solution you have at hand. It 
 might be a rather bad one (extinction) but anywhere you turn it doesn't get 
 (much) better.
 That doesn't mean that in many cases optimization algorithms won't work
 they do even in quite bad conditions if you have a lot of time to search. 
 So I think it just comes down to the degree of maladaptation versus the 
 likely rate of change.
And, we must understand that while adaptation is the process whereby 
natural selection over time (evolution) forms features that permit 
organisms to do well, we cannot think that maladaptations are formed 
by the same process.  Accidents (meteors, floods, continental drift, 
climate change) may make something that was once useful into something 
that is no longer useful, but the maladaptation was not made for that 
new scenario through natural selection.

So, care must be used in thinking about the process.

Cheers,

Jim

-- 
-
James J. Roper, Ph.D.
Universidade Federal do Paraná
Depto. de Zoologia
Caixa Postal 19020
81531-990 Curitiba, Paraná, Brasil
=
E-mail: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Phone/Fone/Teléfono:   55 41 33611764
celular:   55 41 99870543
e-fax:1-206-202-0173 (in the USA)
=
Zoologia na UFPR
http://zoo.bio.ufpr.br/zoologia/
Ecologia e Conservação na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/ecologia/
-
http://jjroper.sites.uol.com.br


EVOLUTION Higher concept Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-19 Thread Wayne Tyson
At 02:19 PM 7/18/2006, Wirt Atmar wrote:
In Darwin's alternate universe of death and famine, we unfortunately have a
simple, easy-to-understand mechanism, one that does eventually builds the
most exalted objects which we are capable of conceiving, the 
production of the
HIGHER [capitals mine, since italics and bold are rejected by the 
program--WT] animals.


Honorable Forum:

Many years ago my wife was being interviewed by a radio host.  He 
asked her about how we were BETTER than the other species.  We're 
not better, we're just different, she said.  That was one of my 
proudest moments, in many proud moments, of her long career of simply 
doing, not bragging (that, obviously, is what I am doing here, 
entirely without her permission and knowledge, but it's germane to 
the issue).

I can't help but wonder if the evolution of culture was not the 
ultimate maladaptation, and that the consequences of all population 
booms is a downslope trend, if not the last frame of the movie 
called, with ironic arrogance, Homo sapiens sapiens.  Doubly wise, indeed!

FIN

wt


Evolution Environment Adaptation Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-18 Thread Wayne Tyson
Kim:

Excuse my ignorance, but what's the contradiction?

WT

At 09:36 PM 7/8/2006, Kim van der Linde wrote:
Hi all,

I am having an interesing discussion at the moment about Natural
selection. The context is a single population of individuals that, due
to changes in the environment, are now maladapted and the population is
reducing in size. Based on the often used definition of differential
reproduction, when there is not much to differentiate with, there is no
longer differential selection, and as such, no natural selection.
However, they are maladapted, so unfit to survive. Any opinions about
this nice contradiction?

Cheers,

Kim

--
http://www.kimvdlinde.com


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-18 Thread Wirt Atmar
Dan writes:

 I am not an expert on evolution (far from it) but I have a
 hunch that relates to Hutchinson's quote and analogy about
 the evolutionary play in the ecological theater. 

Let me say that you can do no wrong by reading and memorizing G. Evelyn 
Hutchinson, and especially his student, Robert MacArthur.

The metaphor I tend to use however invokes a different art form, that of a 
movie. The study of ecology, which entails investigations into the totality of 
the biotic interactions we find on earth, is like the last, current frame of a 
movie that has been running at 24 frames per second for the last several 
hundred years. 

When we do ecology, we're looking only at the last frame of the movie. 
Ecology is evolution in now time, captured in the current frame, but no 
matter how 
intricately we tease apart the ecological physics of those interactions in 
this last frame, the interactions will never make complete sense unless they 
are 
examined over the course of the entire movie.

The ghosts of competitions past, where pronghorn antelope run at high speed 
from a cheetah that's no longer present on the North American plains, is as 
good an example as we have of the necessity of imposing time into our studies, 
making Hutchinson's the evolutionary play in the ecological theater phrase 
all the more relevant.

Why are developing these metaphors important? On one hand, saying all of this 
is obvious. On the other, these discussions have almost no practical value 
when you're in the field, taking detailed measurements. But science doesn't 
mean data. The mathematician Henri Poincare wrote, Science is built of facts 
the way a house is built of bricks, but an accumulation of facts is no more 
science than a pile of bricks is a house. 

Science literally means understanding, and without developing these 
perspectives, we really don't understand much of anything. Evolving truly 
accurate 
mental metaphors and models is fundamental to doing science, of any stripe.

Saying this, what then of the idea of the evolutionary algorithm? In that 
regard, you write:

  My hunch combined with your analogy below of evolution as
  algorithm might be considered ecology as operating system.
  This focuses on ecology at the ecosystem and biosphere level.
  Your description of the algorithm seems to explain and
  characterize selection well, but it does not seem to account
  for 1) generation of novelty, other than via random or
  error-related mutation, 2) feedbacks that result when the
  organisms and communities/ecosystems alter the environment
  and then have to adapt to their own alterations (as studied
  in niche construction and ecosystem engineers) and
  3) the infrastructure and maintenance of elements, energy,
  materials that make the instantiation or materialization of
  new forms (actors) possible, participates in juxtaposing
  them in new plays and cleans up the mess after the play
  (i.e. decomposition and recycling) so that the theater is
  not cluttered from past performances. I could convert these
  to algorithm or application/program vs operating system
  examples relation to hardware realizations, memory and/or
  disk space/clutter.
  
  Algorithms are great, but for them to work one needs an
 operating system that can continue to run and allow many
 programs to run and that is robust and does not itself
 crash. There is also work by folks following up on Robert
 Rosen that suggests that much of the essence of life process
 is non-computable, not algorithmic and non-mechanistic. Some
 of the work here focuses on ambiguity and circularity, both
 of which algorithms do not handle well but life seems
 accustomed to.

I previously wrote the evolutionary algorithm as:

Given self-reproduction, Darwinian evolution is composed of only these five 
components:

 o  a bounded arena 
 o  a replicating population which must eventually expand beyond the 
bounds of the arena
 o  thermodynamically inescapable replicative error, guaranteeing 
variation within the reproducing population
 o  competition for space in that arena among the inevitable variants
 o  the consequential competitive exclusion of the lesser fit

But it's important to note that Darwin probably would have said the same 
thing, if the word algorithm had been in use 150 years ago. What he did 
write, 
in the final paragraph of his last chapter in The Origin of Species, was this:

 It is interesting to contemplate an entangled bank, clothed with many 
plants of many kinds, with birds singing on the bushes, with various insects 
flitting about, and with worms crawling through the damp earth, and to reflect 
that these elaborately constructed forms, so different from each other, and 
dependent on each other in so complex a manner, have all been produced by laws 
acting around us. These laws, taken in the largest sense, being Growth with 
Reproduction; inheritance which is almost implied by reproduction; Variability 
from the 

Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-18 Thread Warren W. Aney
I've been trying to follow this discussion with little profit until I read
this last posting from Wirt Atmar.  This is the most intelligent, succinct,
evocative and accesible (and inspiring) explanation I've ever read on the
topic of basic evolution.  Maybe it's old-hat to evolutionary biologists,
but it's going to be part of this wildlife ecologist's permanent lexicon.

Thanks, Wirt, for persisting on this topic.

Warren Aney
Senior Wildlife Ecologist
Tigard, OR

-Original Message-
From: Ecological Society of America: grants, jobs, news
[mailto:[EMAIL PROTECTED] Behalf Of Wirt Atmar
Sent: Tuesday, 18 July, 2006 14:20
To: ECOLOG-L@LISTSERV.UMD.EDU
Subject: Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection


Dan writes:

 I am not an expert on evolution (far from it) but I have a
 hunch that relates to Hutchinson's quote and analogy about
 the evolutionary play in the ecological theater.

Let me say that you can do no wrong by reading and memorizing G. Evelyn
Hutchinson, and especially his student, Robert MacArthur.

The metaphor I tend to use however invokes a different art form, that of a
movie. The study of ecology, which entails investigations into the totality
of
the biotic interactions we find on earth, is like the last, current frame of
a
movie that has been running at 24 frames per second for the last several
hundred years.

When we do ecology, we're looking only at the last frame of the movie.
Ecology is evolution in now time, captured in the current frame, but no
matter how
intricately we tease apart the ecological physics of those interactions in
this last frame, the interactions will never make complete sense unless they
are
examined over the course of the entire movie.

The ghosts of competitions past, where pronghorn antelope run at high
speed
from a cheetah that's no longer present on the North American plains, is as
good an example as we have of the necessity of imposing time into our
studies,
making Hutchinson's the evolutionary play in the ecological theater phrase
all the more relevant.

Why are developing these metaphors important? On one hand, saying all of
this
is obvious. On the other, these discussions have almost no practical value
when you're in the field, taking detailed measurements. But science
doesn't
mean data. The mathematician Henri Poincare wrote, Science is built of
facts
the way a house is built of bricks, but an accumulation of facts is no more
science than a pile of bricks is a house.

Science literally means understanding, and without developing these
perspectives, we really don't understand much of anything. Evolving truly
accurate
mental metaphors and models is fundamental to doing science, of any stripe.

Saying this, what then of the idea of the evolutionary algorithm? In that
regard, you write:

  My hunch combined with your analogy below of evolution as
  algorithm might be considered ecology as operating system.
  This focuses on ecology at the ecosystem and biosphere level.
  Your description of the algorithm seems to explain and
  characterize selection well, but it does not seem to account
  for 1) generation of novelty, other than via random or
  error-related mutation, 2) feedbacks that result when the
  organisms and communities/ecosystems alter the environment
  and then have to adapt to their own alterations (as studied
  in niche construction and ecosystem engineers) and
  3) the infrastructure and maintenance of elements, energy,
  materials that make the instantiation or materialization of
  new forms (actors) possible, participates in juxtaposing
  them in new plays and cleans up the mess after the play
  (i.e. decomposition and recycling) so that the theater is
  not cluttered from past performances. I could convert these
  to algorithm or application/program vs operating system
  examples relation to hardware realizations, memory and/or
  disk space/clutter.

  Algorithms are great, but for them to work one needs an
 operating system that can continue to run and allow many
 programs to run and that is robust and does not itself
 crash. There is also work by folks following up on Robert
 Rosen that suggests that much of the essence of life process
 is non-computable, not algorithmic and non-mechanistic. Some
 of the work here focuses on ambiguity and circularity, both
 of which algorithms do not handle well but life seems
 accustomed to.

I previously wrote the evolutionary algorithm as:

Given self-reproduction, Darwinian evolution is composed of only these five
components:

 o  a bounded arena
 o  a replicating population which must eventually expand beyond the
bounds of the arena
 o  thermodynamically inescapable replicative error, guaranteeing
variation within the reproducing population
 o  competition for space in that arena among the inevitable variants
 o  the consequential competitive exclusion of the lesser fit

But it's important to note that Darwin probably would have said the same
thing, if the word

Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-15 Thread James J. Roper
All,

I think this question is important, in that apparently there are a 
variety of opinions out there as to what Natural Selection does and does 
not.  In all this discussion, nobody that believes NS favors extinction 
has put NS into a logical framework (premises, assumptions, - basically, 
a syllogism) that would explain the process.  AND, it seems to me that 
most that opine that NS favors extinction, seem also to think that 
extinction only occurs by evolution by NS.

I would say that extinction can occur for many reasons that have nothing 
to do with natural selection.  In today's world, habitat loss, disease, 
exploitation, and so on.  Probably was true in the past as well.  It is 
not true that every extinction was the result of a struggle between a 
winning species and a losing species.

The syllogism that best explains (in my book) NS is the following:

IF
1. Individuals vary phenotypically for some trait or traits, AND
2. Those traits are due to genotypic variability, AND
3. Fitness is associated with those phenotypic trait or traits, THEN,

Individuals with the trait associated with greater fitness will leave 
MORE genes of that phenotypic trait in subsequent generations.  Ergo, 
Natural Selection.  If conditions favor that same process for many 
generations, we are likely to have evolution by natural selection.  And, 
remember, phenotypic variation may be only environmental.

Now, I would say, with this syllogism, just like the expression SH__ 
HAPPENS we can say extinction happens with or without natural selection.
.
Finally, we can think of evolution by natural selection as a process 
that generates adaptations.  Adaptations are advantages given a certain 
set of environmental circumstances.  Sure, adaptations in the wrong 
circumstances can become hindrances, but natural selection did not 
make them to hinder the organism.  Rather circumstances changed (Ice 
Age, for example).  Difficult to imagine natural selection favoring a 
maladaptation

Fitness is defined as differential reproductive success, not natural 
selection.

Cheers,

Jim

Jane Shevtsov wrote:
 Imagine a stable population in which a favorable new genotype has 
 appeared and is increasing. That sure looks like selection FOR the new 
 genotype to me. On the other hand, if we start with the same 
 population and change the environment so some of the old genotypes no 
 longer do well, I'd call that selection AGAINST those genotypes.

 This is all just semantics. If confused, stick to differential 
 reproduction.

 Jane

 At 07:16 AM 7/13/2006, Malcolm McCallum wrote:
 Am I understanding you correct? =20
 Natural Selection selects against unfavorable phenotypes.
 Sexual Selection selects for favorable phenotypes.
 =20
 =20
 =20
 VISIT HERPETOLOGICAL CONSERVATION AND BIOLOGY www.herpconbio.org =
 http://www.herpconbio.org=20
 A New Journal Published in Partnership with Partners in Amphibian and =
 Reptile Conservation
 and the World Congress of Herpetology.
 =20
 Malcolm L. McCallum
 Assistant Professor
 Department of Biological Sciences
 Texas AM University Texarkana
 2600 Robison Rd.
 Texarkana, TX 75501
 O: 1-903-223-3134
 H: 1-903-791-3843
 Homepage: https://www.eagle.tamut.edu/faculty/mmccallum/index.html
 =20

 

 From: Ecological Society of America: grants, jobs, news on behalf of =
 James J. Roper
 Sent: Thu 7/13/2006 6:37 AM
 To: ECOLOG-L@LISTSERV.UMD.EDU
 Subject: Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection



 But Wirt,

 Natural selection doesn't cull but rather it favors.  And selecting
 for something is very different than selecting against something.=20
 Favoring a trait leads to adaptation.  That is, those with a trait leave
 more descendents.  Even so, it is not that simple.  At any rate, John
 Endler does a wonderful job of clearing things up with Natural
 Selection in the Wild and I highly recommend it for anyone who has not
 read it, and, don't forget, The Extended Phenotype by Dawkins, that
 should also be required reading.

  Interpreting literally what I wrote leads to a condition that I =
 normally rail
  against myself. Selection never selects for anything. Selection =
 operates
  only as a culling mechanism, removing the least appropriate, least =
 competitive
  phenotypes of the demic excess that currently fills the competitive =
 arena.
  =20
 What the heck does demic excess really mean?

 Cheers,

 Jim

 ==
  

 The whole person must have both the humility to nurture the Earth and 
 the pride to go to Mars. --Wyn Wachhorst, The Dream of Spaceflight

 Jane Shevtsov
 co-founder, http://www.worldbeyondborders.org/World Beyond Borders
 visit my blog, http://perceivingwholes.blogspot.com/Perceiving Wholes

 Perhaps one day... the world, our world, won't be upside down, and 
 then any newborn human being will be welcome. Saying, Welcome. Come. 
 Come in. Enter. The entire

Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-15 Thread Wirt Atmar
Jim writes:

 But Wirt,
  
  Natural selection doesn't cull but rather it favors.  And selecting 
  for something is very different than selecting against something.  
  Favoring a trait leads to adaptation.  That is, those with a trait leave 
  more descendents.  Even so, it is not that simple.  At any rate, John 
  Endler does a wonderful job of clearing things up with Natural 
  Selection in the Wild and I highly recommend it for anyone who has not 
  read it, and, don't forget, The Extended Phenotype by Dawkins, that 
  should also be required reading.

Let me try one more time, if you don't mind. To do that, let me begin at the 
beginning and write evolution as an algorithm. Given self-reproduction, 
Darwinian evolution is composed of only these five components:

 o  a bounded arena 
 o  a replicating population which must eventually expand beyond the 
bounds of the arena
 o  thermodynamically inescapable replicative error, guaranteeing 
variation within the reproducing population
 o  competition for space in that arena among the inevitable variants
 o  the consequential competitive exclusion of the lesser fit
  
If resources are more abundant than the population's current demands, then, 
as a first order approximation, there is no effective competition among the 
population's members, thus there is no selection. The competitive exclusion of 
the least fit only begins in earnest when the resource space fills. 

These few statements are the essence of Darwinian evolutionary ecology. 


THE NATURE OF SELECTION

Let me apologize for stating the obvious, but given the comments on the list, 
I thought it best to be as clear as possible. However, the simplicity of the 
evolutionary algorithm doesn't mean that it can't be substantially 
misinterpreted. In that regard, Malcolm asked a pertinent question:

 Am I understanding you correctly?  
 Natural Selection selects against unfavorable phenotypes.
 Sexual Selection selects for favorable phenotypes.

No, unfortunately, you are misunderstanding me. The selective processes of 
sexual and natural selection are similar, but the agents of selection are quite 
different. They are similar however in that they both act to cull the least 
appropriate individuals from the population.

Natural selection can be said to be the consequence of all of the extrinsic 
forces that impinge on a population, but sexual selection is quite different, 
startlingly so if you think about it for a minute. It is a mechanism of 
selection that was invented within the phyletic lineage. It is a form of 
selection 
which the lineage imposes on itself, and it can be quite intense.

Two forms of error bedevil populations. They can be described as:

 o  design error
 o  manufacturing error


NATURAL SELECTION CORRECTS DESIGN ERRORS 

Design error is associated with the population not being currently centered 
on a local optimum, and thus rendering a population not as competitive as it 
might be. Design error is quickly mitigated however by selection inexorably 
moving the population across an apaptive topography to that point of maximum 
optimality that is achievable in the current situation.

This movement is accomplished by constantly culling the least appropriate 
(fit) of the excess population (that inevitable fraction of the population 
above the carrying capacity of the current arena). At every stage of this 
evolutionary movement, fitness is a relative quality. Some phenotypic trials 
will be 
more competitive than others, and their stochastic survival is more likely than 
their less-competitive conspecifics.

I earlier gave the examples of longer tarsal hairs in barn flies and a 32 
base-pair deletion in an allele of the CCR5 chemokine receptor in humans as 
simple, point mutation instances that allowed populations to move extremely 
rapidly 
in the face of a drastically changed environment. Because these examples are 
so simple, it seems perfectly reasonable to say that selection is selecting 
for these properties, but this is not the normal condition, nor does it 
present an accurate representation of the evolutionary process. 

The interaction of a lineage's underlying genetic code with its manufactured 
phenotypes is an extraordinarily complex process, being both highly polygenic 
and pleiotropic. Because of this, selection cannot select for any single 
quality in isolation of the remainder of the genotype. Rather, evolutionary 
movement across an adaptive topography, as exemplified by the onset of either 
endemism or the full speciation of a population as the lineage partitions a new 
niche 
for itself, must involve a genotypic revolution, precisely as Ernst Mayr 
argued.


SEXUAL SELECTION MITIGATES MANUFACTURING ERROR

The second form of error is manufacturing error. Although design error 
can be effectively quelled by natural selection moving a population to a new 
point of optimality, manufacturing error is inevitable and persistent, even 
when 

Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-13 Thread James J. Roper
But Wirt,

Natural selection doesn't cull but rather it favors.  And selecting 
for something is very different than selecting against something.  
Favoring a trait leads to adaptation.  That is, those with a trait leave 
more descendents.  Even so, it is not that simple.  At any rate, John 
Endler does a wonderful job of clearing things up with Natural 
Selection in the Wild and I highly recommend it for anyone who has not 
read it, and, don't forget, The Extended Phenotype by Dawkins, that 
should also be required reading.

 Interpreting literally what I wrote leads to a condition that I normally rail 
 against myself. Selection never selects for anything. Selection operates 
 only as a culling mechanism, removing the least appropriate, least 
 competitive 
 phenotypes of the demic excess that currently fills the competitive arena.
   
What the heck does demic excess really mean?

Cheers,

Jim

-- 
-
James J. Roper, Ph.D.
Universidade Federal do Paraná
Depto. de Zoologia
Caixa Postal 19020
81531-990 Curitiba, Paraná, Brasil
=
E-mail: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Phone/Fone/Teléfono:   55 41 33611764
celular:   55 41 99870543
e-fax:1-206-202-0173 (in the USA)
=
Zoologia na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/zoologia/
Ecologia e Conservação na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/ecologia/
-
  http://jjroper.sites.uol.com.br


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-13 Thread Malcolm McCallum
Am I understanding you correct? =20
Natural Selection selects against unfavorable phenotypes.
Sexual Selection selects for favorable phenotypes.
=20
=20
=20
VISIT HERPETOLOGICAL CONSERVATION AND BIOLOGY www.herpconbio.org =
http://www.herpconbio.org=20
A New Journal Published in Partnership with Partners in Amphibian and =
Reptile Conservation
and the World Congress of Herpetology.
=20
Malcolm L. McCallum
Assistant Professor
Department of Biological Sciences
Texas AM University Texarkana
2600 Robison Rd.
Texarkana, TX 75501
O: 1-903-223-3134
H: 1-903-791-3843
Homepage: https://www.eagle.tamut.edu/faculty/mmccallum/index.html
=20



From: Ecological Society of America: grants, jobs, news on behalf of =
James J. Roper
Sent: Thu 7/13/2006 6:37 AM
To: ECOLOG-L@LISTSERV.UMD.EDU
Subject: Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection



But Wirt,

Natural selection doesn't cull but rather it favors.  And selecting
for something is very different than selecting against something.=20
Favoring a trait leads to adaptation.  That is, those with a trait leave
more descendents.  Even so, it is not that simple.  At any rate, John
Endler does a wonderful job of clearing things up with Natural
Selection in the Wild and I highly recommend it for anyone who has not
read it, and, don't forget, The Extended Phenotype by Dawkins, that
should also be required reading.

 Interpreting literally what I wrote leads to a condition that I =
normally rail
 against myself. Selection never selects for anything. Selection =
operates
 only as a culling mechanism, removing the least appropriate, least =
competitive
 phenotypes of the demic excess that currently fills the competitive =
arena.
 =20
What the heck does demic excess really mean?

Cheers,

Jim

--
-
James J. Roper, Ph.D.
Universidade Federal do Paran=E1
Depto. de Zoologia
Caixa Postal 19020
81531-990 Curitiba, Paran=E1, Brasil
=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=
=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D
E-mail: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Phone/Fone/Tel=E9fono:   55 41 33611764
celular:   55 41 99870543
e-fax:1-206-202-0173 (in the USA)
=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=
=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D=3D
Zoologia na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/zoologia/
Ecologia e Conserva=E7=E3o na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/ecologia/
-
  http://jjroper.sites.uol.com.br


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-13 Thread Jim Sparks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Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-13 Thread NZ Muth
Part of this disagreement seems to stem from a detachment of ecological 
processes (death and reproduction) and resulting  evolutionary patterns. 
Various ecological processes act in a non-random ways to remove 
phenotypes (and indirectly genotypes) from populations. I am hesitant to 
reserve the term natural selection for only those occasion when there is 
subsequent response to selection. Doing so unnecessarily entangles 
selective pressures (ecological processes or events that affect 
reproduction and mortality in a non-random fashion) with mechanisms of 
inheritance (primarily genetic variability).

Imagine the case where you have two phenotypically identical populations 
that have different underlying genetics. If these populations have 
different heritabilites, application of the identical selective 
pressures could lead to dramatically different outcomes. In this 
scenario only the responses to selective pressures would differ. It 
would seem inconsistent to me to retro-actively claim that natural 
selection was only operating in the one case where there was a response. 
Rather, natural selection was only effective in producing evolutionarily 
relevant change in one case.

James J. Roper wrote:


 Natural selection doesn't cull but rather it favors.  And 
 selecting for something is very different than selecting against 
 something.  Favoring a trait leads to adaptation.  That is, those with 
 a trait leave more descendents.  Even so, it is not that simple.  At 
 any rate, John Endler does a wonderful job of clearing things up with 
 Natural Selection in the Wild and I highly recommend it for anyone 
 who has not read it, and, don't forget, The Extended Phenotype by 
 Dawkins, that should also be required reading. 


Perhaps I should have not said the dreaded g-word so casually. 
Empirically speaking natural selection seems most effective operating 
within a population. However, theoretically speaking, there is no reason 
to think it can't operate on higher scale entities. Though we may both 
wish it to be true, we are unlikely able to commit this matter to the 
grave quite yet.

 Besides, natural selection works with individuals, not populations... 


-- 

Norris Z. Muth

Department of Ecology and Evolution
State University of New York at Stony Brook
650 Life Sciences Building
Stony Brook, NY 11794-5245

[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://life.bio.sunysb.edu/~nmuth
http://life.bio.sunysb.edu/ee/pigliuccilab/



Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-13 Thread Jane Shevtsov
Imagine a stable population in which a favorable new genotype has 
appeared and is increasing. That sure looks like selection FOR the 
new genotype to me. On the other hand, if we start with the same 
population and change the environment so some of the old genotypes no 
longer do well, I'd call that selection AGAINST those genotypes.

This is all just semantics. If confused, stick to differential reproduction.

Jane

At 07:16 AM 7/13/2006, Malcolm McCallum wrote:
Am I understanding you correct? =20
Natural Selection selects against unfavorable phenotypes.
Sexual Selection selects for favorable phenotypes.
=20
=20
=20
VISIT HERPETOLOGICAL CONSERVATION AND BIOLOGY www.herpconbio.org =
http://www.herpconbio.org=20
A New Journal Published in Partnership with Partners in Amphibian and =
Reptile Conservation
and the World Congress of Herpetology.
=20
Malcolm L. McCallum
Assistant Professor
Department of Biological Sciences
Texas AM University Texarkana
2600 Robison Rd.
Texarkana, TX 75501
O: 1-903-223-3134
H: 1-903-791-3843
Homepage: https://www.eagle.tamut.edu/faculty/mmccallum/index.html
=20



From: Ecological Society of America: grants, jobs, news on behalf of =
James J. Roper
Sent: Thu 7/13/2006 6:37 AM
To: ECOLOG-L@LISTSERV.UMD.EDU
Subject: Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection



But Wirt,

Natural selection doesn't cull but rather it favors.  And selecting
for something is very different than selecting against something.=20
Favoring a trait leads to adaptation.  That is, those with a trait leave
more descendents.  Even so, it is not that simple.  At any rate, John
Endler does a wonderful job of clearing things up with Natural
Selection in the Wild and I highly recommend it for anyone who has not
read it, and, don't forget, The Extended Phenotype by Dawkins, that
should also be required reading.

  Interpreting literally what I wrote leads to a condition that I =
normally rail
  against myself. Selection never selects for anything. Selection =
operates
  only as a culling mechanism, removing the least appropriate, least =
competitive
  phenotypes of the demic excess that currently fills the competitive =
arena.
  =20
What the heck does demic excess really mean?

Cheers,

Jim

==
The whole person must have both the humility to nurture the Earth 
and the pride to go to Mars. --Wyn Wachhorst, The Dream of Spaceflight

Jane Shevtsov
co-founder, http://www.worldbeyondborders.org/World Beyond Borders
visit my blog, http://perceivingwholes.blogspot.com/Perceiving Wholes

Perhaps one day... the world, our world, won't be upside down, and 
then any newborn human being will be welcome. Saying, Welcome. Come. 
Come in. Enter. The entire earth will be your kingdom. Your legs will 
be your passport, valid forever. --Eduardo Galeano, Latin American writer


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-13 Thread James J. Roper
Norris,

I think you have a good point to illustrate the problem:

 Imagine the case where you have two phenotypically identical 
 populations that have different underlying genetics. If these 
 populations have different heritabilites, application of the identical 
 selective pressures could lead to dramatically different outcomes. In 
 this scenario only the responses to selective pressures would differ. 
 It would seem inconsistent to me to retro-actively claim that natural 
 selection was only operating in the one case where there was a 
 response. Rather, natural selection was only effective in producing 
 evolutionarily relevant change in one case.
There is no inconsistency, because for natural selection to act, the 
phenotype must have a connection (heritability) with its underlying 
genotype.  So, in your example above, let's just say that one 
population's phenotype was totally environmental (a good year, perhaps) 
while the other population's identical phenotype was genetic.  Well, in 
both cases perhaps the individuals with the same, high quality 
phenotype would be favored (leaving more descendants) but only the 
population with a genetic basis would leave behind the tendency that 
was based on the phenotypic expression of the genotype.  The other, in a 
different environment, would no longer show the same phenotype.

Did I explain well?

Cheers,

Jim

-- 
-
James J. Roper, Ph.D.
Universidade Federal do Paraná
Depto. de Zoologia
Caixa Postal 19020
81531-990 Curitiba, Paraná, Brasil
=
E-mail: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Phone/Fone/Teléfono:   55 41 33611764
celular:   55 41 99870543
e-fax:1-206-202-0173 (in the USA)
=
Zoologia na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/zoologia/
Ecologia e Conservação na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/ecologia/
-
  http://jjroper.sites.uol.com.br


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-12 Thread Wirt Atmar
Jim writes:

 Sure, natural selection can be occurring while extinction is taking 
 place, but the extinction is NOT the result of natural selection.

If you don't wish to buy my examples, which I'll certainly stand by, it 
nevertheless might be useful to remember that Darwin labeled one of his 
sections in 
the Origin of Species, Extinction caused by natural selection. You can 
read the section on-line at:

 http://www.bartleby.com/11/4006.html

Wirt Atmar


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-12 Thread James J. Roper, Ph.D.
Wirt,

I will certainly disagree here!  Friendly disagreement, of course.
 In my continuing bid to become the group's curmudgeon,
Since there are no other candidates, I guess you will be elected!  :-)
 Natural selection judges only whatever advantages it finds in populations in 
 the moment. What it truly never does is assess the long-term consequences of 
 its preferences.
   
Natural selection is not a judge.  It is only differential 
representation of genes in subsequent generations, in which more 
successful genes become more common from one generation to the next.  
Sure, natural selection can be occurring while extinction is taking 
place, but the extinction is NOT the result of natural selection.

For example, we could say that natural selection is favoring longer 
bills, while habitat loss is eliminating the species.  That is, those 
birds with longer bills leave relatively more descendents, but, it is a 
moot point because it was habitat loss that eliminated the species.
 The first is the reversion of a sexual lineage back to parthenogenesis.
Parthenogensis is unaffected by natural selection, because one of the 
premises of natural selection is genetic variability among the 
population.  And, the accident of becoming parthenogenetic also was 
NOT the result of natural selection, but rather a point event.
 Doing this offers the lineage a number of hypothetical advantages, most 
 especially 
 freeing itself from the burden of maintaining males
Males are not a burden.  Species do not suffer ecological costs, 
individuals do.  And, you would not say often find a situation in which 
males compete with females, and both lose future reproductive success 
due to this competition.
 A population free of males is also capable of rapid expansions into recently 
 vacated territories.
But, not for reasons of natural selection.
 It can also survive in extremely adverse situations where a sexual population 
 would go extinct, simply due to low population numbers and the difficulty in 
 finding a mate.
   
Often, species that reproduce both sexually and asexually do the sexual 
part exactly WHEN the conditions are adverse, presumably because it is 
precisely those conditions that favor genetic (and phenotypic) 
variability.  Rotifers and aphids, for example.
 The second condition is the evolution of high-order polyploidy.
High-order polyploidy is also the result of point changes in a 
population, not natural selection.  This does not result from a gradual 
change, nor a genetic tendency?  That is, adults do NOT reproduce a 
variable set of offspring, some polyploid and the rest normal, that 
after the fact leave a variable number of offspring  There is no 
EVOLUTION for polyploidy, it happens by accident.  After that, the 
polyploid often becomes genetically isolated from its ancestors, and 
then perhaps natural selection acts on it, and all its polyploid 
descendents, based on their phenotypic (and underlying genotypic) 
variability.
 High-order polyploidy seems on the surface to be an excellent 
 information-assurance 
 mechanism, mitigating the informational corruption of any body of information 
 that is 
 replicated generation after generation indefinitely.
   
Accidents are not adaptations.
 While we find both types of populations in nature, their rarity is prima 
 facie evidence that they are not strategies that are successful on the 
 long-term, 
   
That is a circular argument.  Also, there are examples of both that have 
probably been around since the cambrian.  So, duration is also evidence 
of success.
 However, the phenomenon is unknown in mammals, and I have long attributed the 
 evolution of differential imprinting of the chromosomes that pass through 
 either maternal or paternal gametogenesis to be an evolutionary brake that 
 prevents a reversion to parthenogenesis in mammals.
You cannot call parthenogenesis a reversion, since ancestral vertebrates 
were probably not parthenogenetic.  As accidents, there is nothing to 
explain.  Mammals are just unable to have these kinds of accidents.  
Hybridizing lizards MAY become parthenogenic (Cnemidophorus), but they 
don't have to.

There are no evolutionary brakes, as that implies planned evolution, and 
by your own accounting, evolution does not plan...nor does natural 
selection.

Mutations are not planned, they just happen.

Cheers,
Jim

-- 
-
James J. Roper, Ph.D.
Universidade Federal do Paraná
Depto. de Zoologia
Caixa Postal 19020
81531-990 Curitiba, Paraná, Brasil
=
E-mail: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Phone/Fone/Teléfono:   55 41 33611764
celular:   55 41 99870543
e-fax:1-206-202-0173 (in the USA)
=
Zoologia na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/zoologia/
Ecologia e Conservação na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/ecologia/
-
  http://jjroper.sites.uol.com.br


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-12 Thread Wirt Atmar
Jim writes:

 Sorry, the scenario is to poorly defined to say anything about it, and 
  there is probably no contradiction.  But, there is also no reason to 
  think that natural selection is always in action.  And, certainly, 
  natural selection CANNOT select for extinction.

In my continuing bid to become the group's curmudgeon, let me say that 
natural selection can quite easily select for extinction. Natural selection 
judges 
only whatever advantages it finds in populations in the moment. What it truly 
never does is assess the long-term consequences of its preferences.

Although there are probably a dozen hypothetical scenarios where natural 
selection of one attribute or another could drive a lineage to extinction, let 
me 
just mention two that are well-known and reasonably well-documented.

The first is the reversion of a sexual lineage back to parthenogenesis. Doing 
this offers the lineage a number of hypothetical advantages, most especially 
freeing itself from the burden of maintaining males, who often represent 
substantial ecological costs to the species and who quite frequently do not 
participate in the economy of deme. A population free of males is also capable 
of 
rapid expansions into recently vacated territories. It can also survive in 
extremely adverse situations where a sexual population would go extinct, simply 
due 
to low population numbers and the difficulty in finding a mate.

The second condition is the evolution of high-order polyploidy. High-order 
polyploidy seems on the surface to be an excellent information-assurance 
mechanism, mitigating the informational corruption of any body of information 
that is 
replicated generation after generation indefinitely.

While we find both types of populations in nature, their rarity is prima 
facie evidence that they are not strategies that are successful on the 
long-term, 
and that any lineage that adopts them for whatever short-term gain it may 
accrue also soon disappears. Both mechanisms so evolutionary stabilize a 
lineage 
that it cannot adapt to changing conditions.

Reversion to parthenogenesis is relatively common in the arthropods, but it 
also is known to occur in vertebrates as complex as reptiles and birds. It's 
very rare in these animals, but it does occur. 

However, the phenomenon is unknown in mammals, and I have long attributed the 
evolution of differential imprinting of the chromosomes that pass through 
either maternal or paternal gametogenesis to be an evolutionary brake that 
prevents a reversion to parthenogenesis in mammals. Syngamous chromosomes 
derived 
from either gender have been rendered incapable of producing a viable 
individual because some critical information has been suppressed on one 
chromosome or 
the other. Only when the chromosome is matched with the complementary gender's 
is the library complete and embryogenesis allowed to go forward.

On a second. related subject, two people wrote privately and asked if I had a 
reference for the barn fly story that I told. Unfortunately I don't. I heard 
the story at the XII International Congress of Entomology at Canberra in 1972, 
as a contributed talk. Only the keynote and plenary talks were published. If 
there is any published work on the subject somewhere, it is probably published 
in an agricultural bulletin somewhere in Australia.

Nonetheless, there is another virtually identical story regarding the CCR5 
chemokine receptor in human immune systems that is more current and a great 
deal 
more readily available. 

Ordinarily, the CCR5 gene appears to be involved with the inflammatory immune 
response and thus serves an important purpose, but in some people bearing one 
particular allele of the gene, the gene is defective for its primary purpose. 
Very similar to the fly story, this defective allele also cripples one of two 
receptor molecules that the HIV virus requires when infecting a macrophage, 
and thus the homozygous bearers of the defective CCR5 appear completely immune 
to HIV infection, rendering them as completely protected from this plague as 
were the flies with the longer tarsal hairs.

As this article from the CDC states:

At least 23 alleles have been described for the coding region of this gene, 
and most of them are very rare. The most common and most studied is the 32 
allele, a 32 base pair (bp) deletion that confers almost absolute protection 
from 
infection with macrophage tropic (M-tropic) viruses in homozygous individuals 
and provides an average 2 to 3 year delay in the progression to AIDS in those 
heterozygous for the deletion.

  --http://www.cdc.gov/genomics/hugenet/factsheets/FS_CCR5.htm

If you're interested, you won't have any trouble finding articles on this 
example, where once again a mild genetic defect (in normal circumstances) 
proves 
to be of great benefit in a shifted environment. Indeed, if the selection 
coefficient were as strong in humans due to HIV as the toxin was to the flies, 
we 
too would all 

Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-12 Thread NZ Muth
Perhaps there are valid points on both sides of this argument:

James J. Roper, Ph.D. wrote:

 Natural selection is not a judge.  It is only differential 
 representation of genes in subsequent generations, in which more 
 successful genes become more common from one generation to the next.  
 Sure, natural selection can be occurring while extinction is taking 
 place, but the extinction is NOT the result of natural selection.

It seems to me a bit arbitrary to accept that natural selection is 
taking place when a certain fraction of individuals are selectively 
culled from a population, yet when that fraction reaches 100% that 
something different is necessarily going on. To be sure, the RESPONSE of 
a population to natural selection when mortality is 100% will be a moot 
point (unless one is considering selection of higher scale entities, 
dare I say groups?), but to deny that the same processes are at work 
seems like a bid for special treatment.

Wirt Atmar writes:

In my continuing bid to become the group's curmudgeon, let me say that 
natural selection can quite easily select for extinction.

I might argue a semantic point here. While you make a valid argument that past 
natural selection can lead to evolutionary dead ends and extinction, I don't 
think it is accurate to say natural selection is selecting for extinction 
itself. Rather, natural selection for certain traits (other than 
extinction-proneness) may ultimately lead to extinction. A minor point perhaps, 
but an important distinction.

Hope this is a helpful contribution to an interesting discussion.
Norris


-- 

Norris Z. Muth

Department of Ecology and Evolution
State University of New York at Stony Brook
650 Life Sciences Building
Stony Brook, NY 11794-5245

[EMAIL PROTECTED]
http://life.bio.sunysb.edu/~nmuth
http://life.bio.sunysb.edu/ee/pigliuccilab/



Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-12 Thread Wirt Atmar
Norris writes:

 In my continuing bid to become the group's curmudgeon, let me say that 
 natural selection can quite easily select for extinction.
  
 I might argue a semantic point here. While you make a valid argument that 
 past natural selection can lead to evolutionary dead ends and extinction, I 
 don't think it is accurate to say natural selection is selecting for 
 extinction itself. Rather, natural selection for certain traits (other 
than 
 extinction-proneness) may ultimately lead to extinction. A minor point 
 perhaps, but an important distinction.

No, what you write is not a small point. When I wrote that natural selection 
can quite easily select for extinction, I was simply being sloppy in my 
language. What I meant, and what I should have written was natural selection 
can 
quite easily select for [the short-term advantageous conditions that 
ultimately lead to the] extinction [of the lineage].

Interpreting literally what I wrote leads to a condition that I normally rail 
against myself. Selection never selects for anything. Selection operates 
only as a culling mechanism, removing the least appropriate, least competitive 
phenotypes of the demic excess that currently fills the competitive arena.

If selection were only culling the black balls from an urn filled with red 
and black balls, what would be the harm in saying that it was selecting for 
the red balls? If the genetic representation of the individuals' code were that 
independent, there wouldn't be any, but no such situation can exist in a 
complexly interwoven informational system, especially one where the twin 
phenomena 
of polygeny and pleiotropy dominate. 

I've previously written about this misuse of language as being one of the 
fundamental philosophical errors that plagues evolutionary biology, so I'm more 
than a little embarrassed that I wrote that line myself, but it's not what I 
meant, and hopefully that's clear from the context of my other comments.

One paper that is on-line which contains my criticisms of such language is at:

  http://aics-research.com/research/notes.html#IIIC

This paper is on the simulation of evolution for purposes of evolving machine 
intelligence and was published in an engineering journal in 1994. Although 
the idiom of the paper is primarily engineering, engineers designing extremely 
complex systems face precisely the same problems that nature does in optimizing 
its designs, and thus the subjects of accurately determining what is being 
evolved, optimized and selected very rapidly converge.

If you get these qualities wrong, you're offered every opportunity to quite 
completely misunderstand the evolutionary process, which is arguably a more 
serious consequence for engineers than biologists.

Wirt Atmar


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-12 Thread James J. Roper, Ph.D.
 It seems to me a bit arbitrary to accept that natural selection is 
 taking place when a certain fraction of individuals are selectively 
 culled from a population, yet when that fraction reaches 100% that 
 something different is necessarily going on. To be sure, the RESPONSE 
 of a population to natural selection when mortality is 100% will be a 
 moot point (unless one is considering selection of higher scale 
 entities, dare I say groups?), but to deny that the same processes are 
 at work seems like a bid for special treatment.
Indivdiuals are not selectively culled from a population, but rather 
they leave fewer descendants than others.

I would say that a population decline is probably completely independent 
of natural selection, in that something else is causing the decline.  
Natural selection is only about the differential representation of genes 
in subsequent generations, in which some individuals with some traits 
leave more descendents - WHEN natural selection is occuring.

So, my point has nothing to do with how many individuals are involved.  
Besides, natural selection works with individuals, not populations...

Cheers,

JIm

-- 
-
James J. Roper, Ph.D.
Universidade Federal do Paraná
Depto. de Zoologia
Caixa Postal 19020
81531-990 Curitiba, Paraná, Brasil
=
E-mail: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Phone/Fone/Teléfono:   55 41 33611764
celular:   55 41 99870543
e-fax:1-206-202-0173 (in the USA)
=
Zoologia na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/zoologia/
Ecologia e Conservação na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/ecologia/
-
  http://jjroper.sites.uol.com.br


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-11 Thread James J. Roper, Ph.D.
Sorry, the scenario is to poorly defined to say anything about it, and 
there is probably no contradiction.  But, there is also no reason to 
think that natural selection is always in action.  And, certainly, 
natural selection CANNOT select for extinction.

Read Natural Selection in the Wild by Endler.

Jim

Kim van der Linde wrote:
 Hi all,

 I am having an interesing discussion at the moment about Natural 
 selection. The context is a single population of individuals that, due 
 to changes in the environment, are now maladapted and the population 
 is reducing in size. Based on the often used definition of 
 differential reproduction, when there is not much to differentiate 
 with, there is no longer differential selection, and as such, no 
 natural selection. However, they are maladapted, so unfit to survive. 
 Any opinions about this nice contradiction?

 Cheers,

 Kim


-- 
-
James J. Roper, Ph.D.
Universidade Federal do Paraná
Depto. de Zoologia
Caixa Postal 19020
81531-990 Curitiba, Paraná, Brasil
=
E-mail: [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Phone/Fone/Teléfono:   55 41 33611764
celular:   55 41 99870543
e-fax:1-206-202-0173 (in the USA)
=
Zoologia na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/zoologia/
Ecologia e Conservação na UFPR
http://www.bio.ufpr.br/ecologia/
-
  http://jjroper.sites.uol.com.br


Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-09 Thread Kim van der Linde
Hi all,

I am having an interesing discussion at the moment about Natural 
selection. The context is a single population of individuals that, due 
to changes in the environment, are now maladapted and the population is 
reducing in size. Based on the often used definition of differential 
reproduction, when there is not much to differentiate with, there is no 
longer differential selection, and as such, no natural selection. 
However, they are maladapted, so unfit to survive. Any opinions about 
this nice contradiction?

Cheers,

Kim

-- 
http://www.kimvdlinde.com


Re: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection

2006-07-09 Thread Malcolm McCallum
Actually, in the below senario there is Natural Selection and it is =
working.  Since those organisms are now maladapted, and declining to =
extinction Natural Selection is selecting them for extinction.
=20
Natural Selection selects against unfit organisms, not for fit ones.  =
This is much different from selecting for the most fit organisms.  This =
is particularly important because it is this selection against =
maladapted individuals that maintains diversity within a population.  If =
Natural selection selected for a particular genome, the entire =
population would rapidly become homogeneous. The heterogeneity dictates =
that the population has many different characteristics, some of which =
are ideally adapted to the current climatic/habitat conditions, others =
are only marginally adapted to this optima. As the climates change or =
habitats success, dominance of different traits shifts do to =
differential selection pressure across a continuum of from least to most =
adapted.  The least adapted will decline, possibly becoming extirpated.  =
The most adapted will proliferate and dominate.  Another shift in optima =
occurs and the population traits shift in response. =20
=20
This is not unlike a place of employment.  People who can't do the job =
are fired.  But there is wide variation in the ability of employees to =
do the same job.  Some of these receive raises and promotions due to =
their ability to excel while others are demoted or do not receive =
raises.  This array of employees remains employed and functioning in the =
workplace, they all reproduce! =20
=20
To learn more about this interesting relationship it would be good to =
get yourself a copy of Dawkin's The Selfish Gene.  In my opinion, it =
is the best evolution book out there (still) because anyone can grasp =
what is written.  My genetics class is required to read this! =20
=20
I hope that answers your question and if you need clarification, feel =
free to send an email!=20
=20
VISIT HERPETOLOGICAL CONSERVATION AND BIOLOGY www.herpconbio.org =
http://www.herpconbio.org=20
A New Journal Published in Partnership with Partners in Amphibian and =
Reptile Conservation
and the World Congress of Herpetology.
=20
Malcolm L. McCallum
Assistant Professor
Department of Biological Sciences
Texas AM University Texarkana
2600 Robison Rd.
Texarkana, TX 75501
O: 1-903-223-3134
H: 1-903-791-3843
Homepage: https://www.eagle.tamut.edu/faculty/mmccallum/index.html
=20



From: Ecological Society of America: grants, jobs, news on behalf of Kim =
van der Linde
Sent: Sat 7/8/2006 11:36 PM
To: ECOLOG-L@LISTSERV.UMD.EDU
Subject: Maldaptation, Extinction and Natural selection



Hi all,

I am having an interesing discussion at the moment about Natural
selection. The context is a single population of individuals that, due
to changes in the environment, are now maladapted and the population is
reducing in size. Based on the often used definition of differential
reproduction, when there is not much to differentiate with, there is no
longer differential selection, and as such, no natural selection.
However, they are maladapted, so unfit to survive. Any opinions about
this nice contradiction?

Cheers,

Kim

--
http://www.kimvdlinde.com