Re: [EM] Amalgamation details, hijacking, and free-riding

2011-08-06 Thread Jameson Quinn
Well, kinda; but in a sense, that pushes the strategy into the
tree-building.

2011/8/6 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk

 On 4.8.2011, at 2.09, Jameson Quinn wrote:

  Free riding in some form is inevitable in a good system. (That is, any
 system which avoids free riding entirely would be horribly warped by that
 necessity).

 How about tree methods? If candidates are ordered as a binary tree (instead
 of an open list), then there are no choices between three or more branches,
 and related free riding becomes impossible.

 Juho




 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Amalgamation details, hijacking, and free-riding

2011-08-06 Thread Juho Laatu
Tree building could be voluntary or mandatory. If voluntary, then parties and 
wings can stop free riding in their own area. If mandatory, then the most 
difficult part is to organize the parties as a tree (= party external tree). 
One should have rules on how to build a tree also in the case when there is no 
consensus on what the structure of the tree should be.

One simple approach would be to allow the already agreed (= voluntary) binary 
branches (= trees of a forest) to join themselves (or the bigger trees that 
they are already part of) into other trees of the forest in random order. Or 
maybe largest ones first into the largest tree, starting from the third 
largest, after joining the two largest ones together first. I assumed that the 
voluntary branches (that were agreed already before the forced phase) would be 
considered atomic (= no joining inside them).

Did you mean that there would be concrete strategic opportunities in the 
tree-bulding phase, or that one just needs to think a bit on how to form the 
tree or how to force the tree to be formed? Sincere strategy seems quite good 
to me. Or maybe one could nominate fake parties next to one's strongest 
competitors in the hope of making some of the voters of the competing party 
vote for the wrong party (that could get a seat if many enough voters make that 
mistake).

Juho


P.S. I might come back with a proposal of considering trees to be a good method 
that is simple and understandable to the voters, very strategy free, and even 
close to but better than plurality.



On 6.8.2011, at 10.46, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 Well, kinda; but in a sense, that pushes the strategy into the tree-building.
 
 2011/8/6 Juho Laatu juho4...@yahoo.co.uk
 On 4.8.2011, at 2.09, Jameson Quinn wrote:
 
  Free riding in some form is inevitable in a good system. (That is, any 
  system which avoids free riding entirely would be horribly warped by that 
  necessity).
 
 How about tree methods? If candidates are ordered as a binary tree (instead 
 of an open list), then there are no choices between three or more branches, 
 and related free riding becomes impossible.
 
 Juho
 
 
 
 
 
 Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
 


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Record activity on the EM list?

2011-08-06 Thread James Gilmour
 Juho Laatu   Sent: Thursday, August 04, 2011 5:12 PM
  On 4.8.2011, at 14.21, James Gilmour wrote:
  There is only one real issue in elections: representation of the 
  voters.
  
  If in a single winner partisan election the voters vote 51% for A and 
  49% for B, we have a major problem in representation.
 
 Ok, 49% of the voters without representation.

This throws the problem into its sharpest perspective.  There are related, 
difficult problems when there are three, four or more
candidates for the one seat.


 If one uses single-member districts to elect multiple 
 representatives, then this means also some randomness in the 
 results. This is not really a problem of single-winner 
 methods themselves but a problem in how they are used (as 
 multi-winner methods).

I agree.  It is fundamentally wrong to use any single-winner, single-member 
district voting system to elect the members of a
representative assembly (e.g. city council, state legislature).


  But if the voters vote in the same way (51% to 49%) in a two-member 
  election, any sensible voting system will give one seat to A and one 
  seat to B.
  
  Compared to that difference in providing representation of the 
  voters, all the other differences between single-winner and 
  multi-winner elections are trivial.
 
 From this point of view single-winner methods are more 
 problematic than multi-winner methods (at least when used 
 to elect multiple representatives from single-member 
 districts).

No  -  not just when (improperly) used to elect the members of a 
representative assembly.  THE problem is inherent in the
single-winner election.   As you go on to say in your next comment.

 This problem of single-winner methods is quite 
 impossible to fix (most single-winner methods respect the 
 will of the majority).

The extreme problem (51% to 49%) is impossible to fix and so it is the greatest 
challenge in electoral science to obtain the most
representative outcome.  In the two-candidate election, the best we can do is 
to guarantee representation to the majority.

 
 The 51% vs. 49% problem is present also in accurately 
 proportional representative bodies since also those bodies 
 may make majority decisions. One way to alleviate this kind 
 of narrow majority related problems is to seek compromise 
 decisions.

I have to part company with you here.  It should NOT, in my view, be part of 
the function of the voting system to manipulate the
votes to obtain any outcome other than representation of the voters.  It is 
not part of the function of a voting system to seek
consensus.

If the voters want to vote for candidates who will seek consensus, that's fine  
-  but that is very different for making seek
consensus an objective of the voting system.

The function of the voting system should simply be to return the most 
representative result in terms of representing the voters,
as expressed by the voters' responses to the candidates who have offered 
themselves for election.

Seeking consensus and not seeking consensus are aspects of how the elected 
members will behave within the elected assembly.  And
of course, the voters may rightly take such views into account in their 
assessments of the candidates before they cast their votes.
But that is just part of candidate appraisal.  Given a sensitive voting system, 
the outcome (seats won) will reflect the views of
the voters, which may include views on seeking consensus.

James


 That is what in principle happens e.g. in 
 coalition governments. Coalition governments may represent 
 well over 50% of the voters. Let's assume that this is the 
 case. The program of the government may contain multiple 
 topics that would be 51% vs. 49% questions in the 
 representative body or among the voters, but probably all 
 coalition members will get more than they lose. Let's assume 
 that the coalition is heterogeneous so that it does not agree 
 on all the 51% vs. 49% decisions that is has to make. Maybe 
 there are two 51% vs. 49% topics that go the right way 
 against every one such topic that goes wrong. In that way we 
 don't have a narrow majority that always makes 51% decisions 
 but a supermajority that has considerably higher support behind
   everything it does (although all parties of the coalition 
 do not like all the decisions).
 
 In two-party systems the balance is based more on two 
 alternating policies. Often both parties have quite centrist 
 policies since both try to meet the needs of the median 
 voters. In some topics they may however have also clearly 
 opposite positions. I guess the overall policy and results of 
 two-party system governments are typically more 51% majority 
 driven than in multi-party governments. (Coalition 
 governments may however also have only narrow majority and 
 the coalitions may be quite fixed, e.g. left vs. right, and 
 as a result their decisions may follow the 51% majority style.)
 
 My point is just that in addition to multi-winner methods 

Re: [EM] Record activity on the EM list?

2011-08-06 Thread Juho Laatu
I was also looking for pure proportional representation. The compromise 
decisions would take place after the election in a representative body or in a 
government. The election methods need not be tampered. My theory was just that 
in the case that the majority (of parties) that forms the government is 
considerably larger than 51% the decisions could have wider support than in the 
typical 51+% governments of a two-party system. The larger government would 
have to make compromises that are at least acceptable to all parties in the 
government.

Juho


On 6.8.2011, at 17.39, James Gilmour wrote:

 Juho Laatu   Sent: Thursday, August 04, 2011 5:12 PM
 On 4.8.2011, at 14.21, James Gilmour wrote:
 There is only one real issue in elections: representation of the 
 voters.
 
 If in a single winner partisan election the voters vote 51% for A and 
 49% for B, we have a major problem in representation.
 
 Ok, 49% of the voters without representation.
 
 This throws the problem into its sharpest perspective.  There are related, 
 difficult problems when there are three, four or more
 candidates for the one seat.
 
 
 If one uses single-member districts to elect multiple 
 representatives, then this means also some randomness in the 
 results. This is not really a problem of single-winner 
 methods themselves but a problem in how they are used (as 
 multi-winner methods).
 
 I agree.  It is fundamentally wrong to use any single-winner, single-member 
 district voting system to elect the members of a
 representative assembly (e.g. city council, state legislature).
 
 
 But if the voters vote in the same way (51% to 49%) in a two-member 
 election, any sensible voting system will give one seat to A and one 
 seat to B.
 
 Compared to that difference in providing representation of the 
 voters, all the other differences between single-winner and 
 multi-winner elections are trivial.
 
 From this point of view single-winner methods are more 
 problematic than multi-winner methods (at least when used 
 to elect multiple representatives from single-member 
 districts).
 
 No  -  not just when (improperly) used to elect the members of a 
 representative assembly.  THE problem is inherent in the
 single-winner election.   As you go on to say in your next comment.
 
 This problem of single-winner methods is quite 
 impossible to fix (most single-winner methods respect the 
 will of the majority).
 
 The extreme problem (51% to 49%) is impossible to fix and so it is the 
 greatest challenge in electoral science to obtain the most
 representative outcome.  In the two-candidate election, the best we can do 
 is to guarantee representation to the majority.
 
 
 The 51% vs. 49% problem is present also in accurately 
 proportional representative bodies since also those bodies 
 may make majority decisions. One way to alleviate this kind 
 of narrow majority related problems is to seek compromise 
 decisions.
 
 I have to part company with you here.  It should NOT, in my view, be part of 
 the function of the voting system to manipulate the
 votes to obtain any outcome other than representation of the voters.  It is 
 not part of the function of a voting system to seek
 consensus.
 
 If the voters want to vote for candidates who will seek consensus, that's 
 fine  -  but that is very different for making seek
 consensus an objective of the voting system.
 
 The function of the voting system should simply be to return the most 
 representative result in terms of representing the voters,
 as expressed by the voters' responses to the candidates who have offered 
 themselves for election.
 
 Seeking consensus and not seeking consensus are aspects of how the 
 elected members will behave within the elected assembly.  And
 of course, the voters may rightly take such views into account in their 
 assessments of the candidates before they cast their votes.
 But that is just part of candidate appraisal.  Given a sensitive voting 
 system, the outcome (seats won) will reflect the views of
 the voters, which may include views on seeking consensus.
 
 James
 
 
 That is what in principle happens e.g. in 
 coalition governments. Coalition governments may represent 
 well over 50% of the voters. Let's assume that this is the 
 case. The program of the government may contain multiple 
 topics that would be 51% vs. 49% questions in the 
 representative body or among the voters, but probably all 
 coalition members will get more than they lose. Let's assume 
 that the coalition is heterogeneous so that it does not agree 
 on all the 51% vs. 49% decisions that is has to make. Maybe 
 there are two 51% vs. 49% topics that go the right way 
 against every one such topic that goes wrong. In that way we 
 don't have a narrow majority that always makes 51% decisions 
 but a supermajority that has considerably higher support behind
  everything it does (although all parties of the coalition 
 do not like all the decisions).
 
 In two-party systems the 

[EM] Chicken problem (was: SODA and the Condorcet criterion)

2011-08-06 Thread Jameson Quinn
More thoughts on the chicken problem.

Again, in Forest's version, that's a scenario like:

48 A
27 CB
25 BC

C is the pairwise champion, but B is motivated to truncate, and C to
retaliate defensively, until A ends up winning.

In my opinion, scenarios like this make the single most intractable
practical strategy problem in voting theory:

   - Approval, Range, and median-based systems all suffer directly.
   - Most winning-vote-like Condorcet systems fall prey, including
   otherwise-great systems like Schulze.
   - Margins systems have no truncation incentive - but as a direct
   consequence, they give extremely difficult-to-justify results if the B block
   truncates; in fact, they allow a strategic C block to fool the system into
   thinking it's seeing this scenarion when actually B and C are mortal
   enemies.
   - IRV does relatively well with this scenario - but in return, pays no
   attention at all to the second choice of the A voters, which should be
   decisive if it exists.
   - At the other extreme, some systems resolve this problem by forcing
   strict rankings from the A voters - but if they really don't have a
   preference, that ends up being just statistical noise, and doesn't even
   necessarily remove the game-of-chicken incentives if things are balanced
   right. Moreover, forcing B and C voters into strict rankings only makes them
   escalate their truncations into burials.


Most of us, when we want to test our voting systems with a difficult case,
use a strict-ranking Condorcet cycle of three; the old, standard ABC BCA CAB
scenario. That's nice and simple, but not very realistic. To me, the game
of chicken scenario; the resulting Condorcet cycle if B truncates; and
related scenarios that could strategically be made to masquerade as these;
are better practical tests for a voting system. In fact, I'd go so far as to
guess that *a real-life Condorcet cycle would be more likely to be the
result of playing chicken than of honest preferences.*

As Forest already explained, SODA, as currently formulated, resolves the
game of chicken — if all votes are delegated. It can do that because games
among finite candidates are much more tractable than those among oceans of
voters. SODA's sequential trick would be ridiculous with voters; imagine
Your turn to vote is on Sunday at 2:35:58 PM.

In my previous message in this thread (Re: SODA and the Condorcet
criterion), I pointed out that there's still a problem if voters explicitly
truncate by refusing to delegate. But I've been considering this issue, and
eventually I found a solution that I think is simple enough to include in
SODA:

*Make all candidate's predeclared rankings into strict rankings by breaking
declared ties in order of the current approval totals when it's their turn
to use their delegated votes.*


So if B voters truncated, candidate A would see that B was headed for a win,
and would have the option to delegate to C. All the truncation would have
accomplished would be to make A into a kingmaker between B and C. Since A
could have had this kingmaker power, if she had wanted it, from the start,
that's not a problem. The only difference between this end-game kingmaker
power of A's, and if she had simply declared a preference from the start, is
that the end-game power could in theory arise no matter which of B or C has
more approvals, whereas an initial preference would only confer kingmaker
power if the preferred candidate ended up with fewer approvals.

Is this version of SODA really the only system to have a fully-satisfactory
resolution to the chicken problem? Even if it is, is it worth adding this
additional complexity to SODA? Can anyone make a chicken-like scenario which
still stumps this SODA version? (If your scenario has more than 4
candidates, please use DAC instead of approval to find the SODA order of
play.) Or do you know of a different system which creatively resolves the
chicken problem?

JQ

2011/8/5 Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com



 2011/8/5 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 Jameson,

 as you say, it seems that SODA will always elect a candidate that beats
 every other candidate majority
 pairwise.  If rankings are complete, then all pairwise wins will be by
 majority.  So at least to the degree
 that rankings are complete, SODA satisfies the Condorcet Criterion.

 Also, as I mentioned briefly in my last message under this subject
 heading, SODA seems to completely
 demolish the chicken problem.


 Well almost. See below.



 To review for other readers, we're talking about the scenario

 48 A
 27 CB
 25 BC

 Candidates B and C form a clone set that pairwise beats A, and in fact C
 is the Condorcet Winner, but
 under many Condorcet methods, as well as for Range and Approval, there is
 a large temptation for the
 25 B faction to threaten to truncate C, and thereby steal the election
 from C.  Of course C can counter
 the threat to truncate B, but then A wins.  So it is a classical game of
 chicken.

 Some methods like 

Re: [EM] Record activity on the EM list?

2011-08-06 Thread James Gilmour
You can also have minority government (usually single-party), where the 
majorities are by consensus, issue by issue, transcending
the parties.

Incidentally, what is pure proportional representation?  It is a term I have 
come across quite frequently.

James


 -Original Message-
 From: election-methods-boun...@lists.electorama.com 
 [mailto:election-methods-boun...@lists.electorama.com] On 
 Behalf Of Juho Laatu
 Sent: Saturday, August 06, 2011 5:38 PM
 To: EM list
 Subject: Re: [EM] Record activity on the EM list?
 
 
 I was also looking for pure proportional representation. The 
 compromise decisions would take place after the election in a 
 representative body or in a government. The election methods 
 need not be tampered. My theory was just that in the case 
 that the majority (of parties) that forms the government is 
 considerably larger than 51% the decisions could have wider 
 support than in the typical 51+% governments of a two-party 
 system. The larger government would have to make compromises 
 that are at least acceptable to all parties in the government.
 
 Juho
 
 
 On 6.8.2011, at 17.39, James Gilmour wrote:
 
  Juho Laatu   Sent: Thursday, August 04, 2011 5:12 PM
  On 4.8.2011, at 14.21, James Gilmour wrote:
  There is only one real issue in elections: representation of the
  voters.
  
  If in a single winner partisan election the voters vote 51% for A 
  and
  49% for B, we have a major problem in representation.
  
  Ok, 49% of the voters without representation.
  
  This throws the problem into its sharpest perspective.  There are 
  related, difficult problems when there are three, four or more 
  candidates for the one seat.
  
  
  If one uses single-member districts to elect multiple
  representatives, then this means also some randomness in the 
  results. This is not really a problem of single-winner 
  methods themselves but a problem in how they are used (as 
  multi-winner methods).
  
  I agree.  It is fundamentally wrong to use any single-winner, 
  single-member district voting system to elect the members of a 
  representative assembly (e.g. city council, state legislature).
  
  
  But if the voters vote in the same way (51% to 49%) in a 
 two-member
  election, any sensible voting system will give one seat 
 to A and one 
  seat to B.
  
  Compared to that difference in providing representation of the
  voters, all the other differences between single-winner and 
  multi-winner elections are trivial.
  
  From this point of view single-winner methods are more
  problematic than multi-winner methods (at least when used 
  to elect multiple representatives from single-member 
  districts).
  
  No  -  not just when (improperly) used to elect the members 
 of a representative assembly.  THE problem is inherent in the
  single-winner election.   As you go on to say in your next comment.
  
  This problem of single-winner methods is quite
  impossible to fix (most single-winner methods respect the 
  will of the majority).
  
  The extreme problem (51% to 49%) is impossible to fix and 
 so it is the 
  greatest challenge in electoral science to obtain the most 
  representative outcome.  In the two-candidate election, 
 the best we 
  can do is to guarantee representation to the majority.
  
  
  The 51% vs. 49% problem is present also in accurately
  proportional representative bodies since also those bodies 
  may make majority decisions. One way to alleviate this kind 
  of narrow majority related problems is to seek compromise 
  decisions.
  
  I have to part company with you here.  It should NOT, in my 
 view, be 
  part of the function of the voting system to manipulate the 
 votes to 
  obtain any outcome other than representation of the 
 voters.  It is 
  not part of the function of a voting system to seek consensus.
  
  If the voters want to vote for candidates who will seek consensus, 
  that's fine  -  but that is very different for making seek 
 consensus 
  an objective of the voting system.
  
  The function of the voting system should simply be to 
 return the most 
  representative result in terms of representing the voters, as 
  expressed by the voters' responses to the candidates who 
 have offered 
  themselves for election.
  
  Seeking consensus and not seeking consensus are aspects 
 of how the 
  elected members will behave within the elected assembly.  And of 
  course, the voters may rightly take such views into account 
 in their 
  assessments of the candidates before they cast their votes. 
 But that 
  is just part of candidate appraisal.  Given a sensitive 
 voting system, 
  the outcome (seats won) will reflect the views of the voters, which 
  may include views on seeking consensus.
  
  James
  
  
  That is what in principle happens e.g. in
  coalition governments. Coalition governments may represent 
  well over 50% of the voters. Let's assume that this is the 
  case. The program of the government may contain multiple 
  

Re: [EM] Record activity on the EM list?

2011-08-06 Thread Juho Laatu
Term pure proportional representation was just an ad hoc invention that I 
used to refer to methods that aim at providing best possible proportional 
representation and nothing else (no thresholds, no bias, no consensus related 
stuff).

Yes, minority governments need good support in the representative bodies. Since 
their life depends on having that support, hopefully wider than 51%, they 
probably make decisions that are intended to please (or at lest be acceptable 
to) as many parties as possible.

Juho


On 6.8.2011, at 19.52, James Gilmour wrote:

 You can also have minority government (usually single-party), where the 
 majorities are by consensus, issue by issue, transcending
 the parties.
 
 Incidentally, what is pure proportional representation?  It is a term I 
 have come across quite frequently.
 
 James
 
 
 -Original Message-
 From: election-methods-boun...@lists.electorama.com 
 [mailto:election-methods-boun...@lists.electorama.com] On 
 Behalf Of Juho Laatu
 Sent: Saturday, August 06, 2011 5:38 PM
 To: EM list
 Subject: Re: [EM] Record activity on the EM list?
 
 
 I was also looking for pure proportional representation. The 
 compromise decisions would take place after the election in a 
 representative body or in a government. The election methods 
 need not be tampered. My theory was just that in the case 
 that the majority (of parties) that forms the government is 
 considerably larger than 51% the decisions could have wider 
 support than in the typical 51+% governments of a two-party 
 system. The larger government would have to make compromises 
 that are at least acceptable to all parties in the government.
 
 Juho
 
 
 On 6.8.2011, at 17.39, James Gilmour wrote:
 
 Juho Laatu   Sent: Thursday, August 04, 2011 5:12 PM
 On 4.8.2011, at 14.21, James Gilmour wrote:
 There is only one real issue in elections: representation of the
 voters.
 
 If in a single winner partisan election the voters vote 51% for A 
 and
 49% for B, we have a major problem in representation.
 
 Ok, 49% of the voters without representation.
 
 This throws the problem into its sharpest perspective.  There are 
 related, difficult problems when there are three, four or more 
 candidates for the one seat.
 
 
 If one uses single-member districts to elect multiple
 representatives, then this means also some randomness in the 
 results. This is not really a problem of single-winner 
 methods themselves but a problem in how they are used (as 
 multi-winner methods).
 
 I agree.  It is fundamentally wrong to use any single-winner, 
 single-member district voting system to elect the members of a 
 representative assembly (e.g. city council, state legislature).
 
 
 But if the voters vote in the same way (51% to 49%) in a 
 two-member
 election, any sensible voting system will give one seat 
 to A and one 
 seat to B.
 
 Compared to that difference in providing representation of the
 voters, all the other differences between single-winner and 
 multi-winner elections are trivial.
 
 From this point of view single-winner methods are more
 problematic than multi-winner methods (at least when used 
 to elect multiple representatives from single-member 
 districts).
 
 No  -  not just when (improperly) used to elect the members 
 of a representative assembly.  THE problem is inherent in the
 single-winner election.   As you go on to say in your next comment.
 
 This problem of single-winner methods is quite
 impossible to fix (most single-winner methods respect the 
 will of the majority).
 
 The extreme problem (51% to 49%) is impossible to fix and 
 so it is the 
 greatest challenge in electoral science to obtain the most 
 representative outcome.  In the two-candidate election, 
 the best we 
 can do is to guarantee representation to the majority.
 
 
 The 51% vs. 49% problem is present also in accurately
 proportional representative bodies since also those bodies 
 may make majority decisions. One way to alleviate this kind 
 of narrow majority related problems is to seek compromise 
 decisions.
 
 I have to part company with you here.  It should NOT, in my 
 view, be 
 part of the function of the voting system to manipulate the 
 votes to 
 obtain any outcome other than representation of the 
 voters.  It is 
 not part of the function of a voting system to seek consensus.
 
 If the voters want to vote for candidates who will seek consensus, 
 that's fine  -  but that is very different for making seek 
 consensus 
 an objective of the voting system.
 
 The function of the voting system should simply be to 
 return the most 
 representative result in terms of representing the voters, as 
 expressed by the voters' responses to the candidates who 
 have offered 
 themselves for election.
 
 Seeking consensus and not seeking consensus are aspects 
 of how the 
 elected members will behave within the elected assembly.  And of 
 course, the voters may rightly take such views into account 
 in their 
 assessments of 

Re: [EM] Chicken problem (was: SODA and the Condorcet criterion)

2011-08-06 Thread Jan Kok
 To review for other readers, we're talking about the scenario

 48 A
 27 CB
 25 BC

 Candidates B and C form a clone set that pairwise beats A, and in fact C
 is the Condorcet Winner, but
 under many Condorcet methods, as well as for Range and Approval, there is
 a large temptation for the
 25 B faction to threaten to truncate C, and thereby steal the election
 from C.  Of course C can counter
 the threat to truncate B, but then A wins.  So it is a classical game of
 chicken.

 Some methods like IRV cop out by giving the win to A right off the bat,
 so there is no game of chicken.

Wait a minute! IRV elects C in this scenario, if that is how the
voters actually vote, and those are the sincere preferences (A voters
have no preference between B and C).

Much as I hate to say it, IRV works OK in that scenario. On the other
hand, if the A voters prefer B over C, (as in the 2009 Burlington, VT
mayoral election, http://scorevoting.net/Burlington.html) IRV ignores
the preference and still elects C, which seems to be the wrong choice.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] : Chicken problem (was: SODA and the Condorcet

2011-08-06 Thread fsimmons
Jan,

IRV elects C like all of the other methods if the B faction doesn't truncate.  
But IRV elects A when the B 
faction truncates.  Of course, with this knowledge, the B faction isn't likely 
to truncate, and as you say C 
will be elected.

The trouble with IRV is that in the other scenario when the B faction truncates 
sincerely because of 
detesting both A and C, IRV still elects A instead of B.

 Date: Sat, 6 Aug 2011 11:46:12 -0600
 From: Jan Kok 
 To: Jameson Quinn , Election Methods Mailing
 List 
 Subject: Re: [EM] Chicken problem (was: SODA and the Condorcet
 criterion)
  To review for other readers, we're talking about the scenario
 
  48 A
  27 CB
  25 BC
 
  Candidates B and C form a clone set that pairwise beats A, 
 and in fact C
  is the Condorcet Winner, but
  under many Condorcet methods, as well as for Range and 
 Approval, there is
  a large temptation for the
  25 B faction to threaten to truncate C, and thereby steal 
 the election
  from C. ?Of course C can counter
  the threat to truncate B, but then A wins. ?So it is a 
 classical game of
  chicken.
 
  Some methods like IRV cop out by giving the win to A right 
 off the bat,
  so there is no game of chicken.
 
 Wait a minute! IRV elects C in this scenario, if that is how the
 voters actually vote, and those are the sincere preferences (A voters
 have no preference between B and C).
 
 Much as I hate to say it, IRV works OK in that scenario. On the other
 hand, if the A voters prefer B over C, (as in the 2009 
 Burlington, VT
 mayoral election, http://scorevoting.net/Burlington.html) IRV ignores
 the preference and still elects C, which seems to be the wrong choice.
 
 
 --
 
 ___
 Election-Methods mailing list
 Election-Methods@lists.electorama.com
 http://lists.electorama.com/listinfo.cgi/election-methods-
 electorama.com
 
 End of Election-Methods Digest, Vol 86, Issue 18
 
 

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


[EM] AQ variant of DSC

2011-08-06 Thread fsimmons
One way of looking at Woodall's DSC method is that it is designed to elect from 
the clone set that 
extends up to the top rank on the greatest number of ballots, i.e. kind of the 
plurality winner among 
clone sets.

There are two ways in which this description is not precise, but maybe we would 
get a better method if 
we follwed this description more closely.

(1)  The solid coalitions look like clone sets on the ballots that reach up to 
the top, but they don't have to 
look like clone sets on the other ballots.

(2)   This description doesn't tell how DSC narrows down after finding the 
plurality winner solid coalition.  
In fact the entire set of candidates is automatically the solid coalition that 
extends to the top rank on 
100% of the ballots, so for starter we need to narrow down to a proper 
sub-coalition.

With regard to (1),  imagine a one dimensional issue space with the candidates 
distributed as follows:

A..B1..B2..B3...C..D1..D2...E

The set {B1, B2, B3} and the set  {D1, D2}  will be solid coalitions that 
extend to the top rank on the 
ballots of the voters that have a favorite among them, and they will appear as 
clone sets on all of the 
ballots that do not rank C first.  But voters near C may well intermingle the 
B's and the D's like

C B3D1B2D2B1EA

This shows that a geometrical clone doesn't have to end up as a classical 
ballot clone except on the 
ballots of the voters that are situated in the middle of the clone set, in 
which case they will appear as 
solid (or assenting) coalitions that extend to the top rank.  

So Woodal had the right idea for making his method clone independent.

If I uderstand correctly, Woodall invented DSC to prove a point, viz. that a 
method can satisfy later no 
harm, be clone free, and montone.  He didn't invent the method as a serious 
proposal.  So I don't think 
his feelings will be hurt if we suggest an improvement.

My suggestion is that once we have found the proper subset solid coalition that 
extends to the top rank 
on the greatest number of ballots, strike from the ballots the candidates that 
are not in that coalition, and 
iterate until there is only one candidate left.  Elect the sole remaining 
candidate.

For incomplete rankings we can modify DAC in the same way, by replacing the 
term solid with the 
term assenting.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Chicken problem (was: SODA and the Condorcet criterion)

2011-08-06 Thread Juho Laatu
On 6.8.2011, at 19.40, Jameson Quinn wrote:

 More thoughts on the chicken problem.
 
 Again, in Forest's version, that's a scenario like:
 
 48 A
 27 CB
 25 BC
 
 C is the pairwise champion, but B is motivated to truncate, and C to 
 retaliate defensively, until A ends up winning.
 
 In my opinion, scenarios like this make the single most intractable practical 
 strategy problem in voting theory: 
 Approval, Range, and median-based systems all suffer directly. 
 Most winning-vote-like Condorcet systems fall prey, including otherwise-great 
 systems like Schulze. 
 Margins systems have no truncation incentive - but as a direct consequence, 
 they give extremely difficult-to-justify results if the B block truncates; in 
 fact, they allow a strategic C block to fool the system into thinking it's 
 seeing this scenarion when actually B and C are mortal enemies. 
 IRV does relatively well with this scenario - but in return, pays no 
 attention at all to the second choice of the A voters, which should be 
 decisive if it exists. 
 At the other extreme, some systems resolve this problem by forcing strict 
 rankings from the A voters - but if they really don't have a preference, that 
 ends up being just statistical noise, and doesn't even necessarily remove the 
 game-of-chicken incentives if things are balanced right. Moreover, forcing B 
 and C voters into strict rankings only makes them escalate their truncations 
 into burials.
 
 Most of us, when we want to test our voting systems with a difficult case, 
 use a strict-ranking Condorcet cycle of three; the old, standard ABC BCA CAB 
 scenario. That's nice and simple, but not very realistic. To me, the game of 
 chicken scenario; the resulting Condorcet cycle if B truncates; and related 
 scenarios that could strategically be made to masquerade as these; are better 
 practical tests for a voting system. In fact, I'd go so far as to guess that 
 a real-life Condorcet cycle would be more likely to be the result of playing 
 chicken than of honest preferences.
 
 As Forest already explained, SODA, as currently formulated, resolves the game 
 of chicken — if all votes are delegated. It can do that because games among 
 finite candidates are much more tractable than those among oceans of voters. 
 SODA's sequential trick would be ridiculous with voters; imagine Your turn 
 to vote is on Sunday at 2:35:58 PM.
 
 In my previous message in this thread (Re: SODA and the Condorcet criterion), 
 I pointed out that there's still a problem if voters explicitly truncate by 
 refusing to delegate. But I've been considering this issue, and eventually I 
 found a solution that I think is simple enough to include in SODA:
 
 Make all candidate's predeclared rankings into strict rankings by breaking 
 declared ties in order of the current approval totals when it's their turn to 
 use their delegated votes.
 
 So if B voters truncated, candidate A would see that B was headed for a win, 
 and would have the option to delegate to C. All the truncation would have 
 accomplished would be to make A into a kingmaker between B and C. Since A 
 could have had this kingmaker power, if she had wanted it, from the start, 
 that's not a problem. The only difference between this end-game kingmaker 
 power of A's, and if she had simply declared a preference from the start, is 
 that the end-game power could in theory arise no matter which of B or C has 
 more approvals, whereas an initial preference would only confer kingmaker 
 power if the preferred candidate ended up with fewer approvals.
 
 Is this version of SODA really the only system to have a fully-satisfactory 
 resolution to the chicken problem? Even if it is, is it worth adding this 
 additional complexity to SODA? Can anyone make a chicken-like scenario which 
 still stumps this SODA version? (If your scenario has more than 4 candidates, 
 please use DAC instead of approval to find the SODA order of play.) Or do you 
 know of a different system which creatively resolves the chicken problem?

Remember trees :-). In a tree where B and C form one branch they and their 
voters are bound to support each others.

Juho


 
 JQ
 
 2011/8/5 Jameson Quinn jameson.qu...@gmail.com
 
 
 2011/8/5 fsimm...@pcc.edu
 
 Jameson,
 
 as you say, it seems that SODA will always elect a candidate that beats every 
 other candidate majority
 pairwise.  If rankings are complete, then all pairwise wins will be by 
 majority.  So at least to the degree
 that rankings are complete, SODA satisfies the Condorcet Criterion.
 
 Also, as I mentioned briefly in my last message under this subject heading, 
 SODA seems to completely
 demolish the chicken problem.
 
 Well almost. See below.
  
 
 To review for other readers, we're talking about the scenario
 
 48 A
 27 CB
 25 BC
 
 Candidates B and C form a clone set that pairwise beats A, and in fact C is 
 the Condorcet Winner, but
 under many Condorcet methods, as well as for Range and Approval, there is a 
 

Re: [EM] : Chicken problem (was: SODA and the Condorcet

2011-08-06 Thread Jameson Quinn
2011/8/6 fsimm...@pcc.edu

 Jan,

 IRV elects C like all of the other methods if the B faction doesn't
 truncate.  But IRV elects A when the B
 faction truncates.  Of course, with this knowledge, the B faction isn't
 likely to truncate, and as you say C
 will be elected.

 The trouble with IRV is that in the other scenario when the B faction
 truncates sincerely because of
 detesting both A and C, IRV still elects A instead of B.


Also, if the A faction votes AB, then B clearly should win, but does not
under IRV. So yes, IRV solves the chicken dilemma, but in so doing causes
other problems. (This same argument, as it happens, works against tree-based
methods.)

I still claim that SODA is the only system I know of that can solve the
chicken dilemma without over-solving it and making other problems.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info