Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-29 Thread James Gilmour
> > Robert Bristow-Johnson wrote (9 Nov 2009):
> >
> > "Of course IRV, Condorcet, and Borda use different methods  to tabulate 
> > the votes and select the winner and my opinion is that IRV ("asset 
> > voting", I might call it "commodity voting": your vote is a 
> > "commodity" that you transfer according to your preferences) is a 
> > kabuki dance of transferred votes.  and there is an *arbitrary* 
> > evaluation in the elimination of candidates in the IRV rounds: 2nd- 
> > choice votes don't count for shit in deciding who to eliminate (who 
> > decided that?  2nd-choice votes are as good as last-choice?  under 
> > what meaningful and consistent philosophy was that decided?), then 
> > when your candidate is eliminated your 2nd-choice vote counts as much 
> > as your 1st-choice."

These statements suggest a misunderstanding of how STV voting works and what 
preferences (US "rankings") mean in the STV voting
system.  In all STV elections, the preferences are contingency choices.  Your 
vote is transferred to your second choice only in the
event that your first choice cannot secure election or does not need you 
support to secure election.

This is most easily seen in single-winner STV elections (US = IRV), where the 
sequence of rounds is exactly analogous to the
sequence of rounds in an exhaustive ballot (eliminating one candidate at a time 
in successive ballots).  The only difference is that
in an STV (IRV) election you don't know what all the other voters did in Round 
1 when you come to give your second choice.  So the
preferences (= contingency choices) marked on an STV ballot are quite different 
from the preferences marked on, for example, a Borda
ballot where some attempt will be made to use all of the information 
simultaneously.

The same applies to STV multi-winner elections (STV-PR), though the connection 
is not so obvious in versions of STV that use
fractional transfer values to remove the otherwise unavoidable element of 
chance.  However, the contingency choice nature of the
STV-PR preferences is obvious in those versions of STV-PR that use whole vote 
transfers, e.g. Cambridge MA and the Dáil Éireann.  It
is even more obvious in Thomas Hill's original application of STV-PR when the 
boys formed lines in the schoolyard to show their
support for the various candidates.

These STV preferences are all quite clearly contingency choices and they should 
not be interpreted in any other way.

James Gilmour


No virus found in this outgoing message.
Checked by AVG - www.avg.com 
Version: 9.0.698 / Virus Database: 270.14.86/2533 - Release Date: 11/28/09 
19:34:00



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-17 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear folks,

there is another assumption in Arrow's theorem which people almost
always forget: Determinism. Methods which use some amount of chance can
easily meet all his other criteria, the most trivial example of this
being again Random Ballot (i.e. pick a ballot uniformly at random and
copy its ranking as the group's ranking). Some people think this
violates the no-dictator requirement, but it doesn't since a dictator
would be a person determined *beforehand*.

Yours, Jobst



Raph Frank schrieb:
> The theorem states (from wiki) that there is no method which has the
> following properties:
> 
> * If every voter prefers X over Y, then the group prefers X over Y.
> * If every voter prefers X over Y, then adding Z to the slate
> won't change the group's preference of X over Y.
> * There is no dictator.
> 
> All 3 of those conditions are met for range.  The only problem is that
> adding Z could cause renormalisation changes in how people vote.
> 
> A voter who votes
> 
> A: 100
> B: 0
> 
> might change vote to:
> 
> A: 100
> B: 50
> Z: 0
> 
> after Z is added.
> 
> Thus changing the difference between A and B for that ballot.
> 
> Ranked systems allow full ranking.  Adding another candidate just
> requires that you insert the candidate into the rank order.
> 
> With range this might not be possible.  If the candidate has a rating
> outside the max and min, a voter may have to rescale their prior
> preferences.
> 
> If the assumption is that voters are just allowed add a rating for Z
> and not change any of their other ratings, then it meets the 3
> conditions and thus is a counter example to Arrow's theorem.
> 
> Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Nov 16, 2009, at 4:58 PM, Raph Frank wrote:

> The theorem states (from wiki) that there is no method which has the
> following properties:
> 
>* If every voter prefers X over Y, then the group prefers X over Y.
>* If every voter prefers X over Y, then adding Z to the slate
> won't change the group's preference of X over Y.
>* There is no dictator.
> 
> All 3 of those conditions are met for range.  The only problem is that
> adding Z could cause renormalisation changes in how people vote.

The problem in applying the theorem to range isn't in the properties; it's in 
the formal definition of the method and the proof.

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Arrow%27s_impossibility_theorem#Formal_statement_of_the_theorem

The proof applies to strict social welfare functions, defined as functions 
mapping a set of linear orderings (by voters) to a social ordering. While a 
range ballot (without ties) can be interpreted as a linear ordering, the range 
counting rule is not a function of that ordering, but rather of the cardinal 
values on the ballot. Different range ballots could have the same ordering but 
lead to a different result.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Kevin Venzke
Strictly speaking I don't think Range is an election method according
to Arrow, because you can't determine the winner from the orderings.
It would be hard to make statements about the effect of introducing 
candidate Z when you don't have an assumption about what the outcome is
based on.

You can make it work if you want to I guess.

Kevin Venzke


  

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Raph Frank
The theorem states (from wiki) that there is no method which has the
following properties:

* If every voter prefers X over Y, then the group prefers X over Y.
* If every voter prefers X over Y, then adding Z to the slate
won't change the group's preference of X over Y.
* There is no dictator.

All 3 of those conditions are met for range.  The only problem is that
adding Z could cause renormalisation changes in how people vote.

A voter who votes

A: 100
B: 0

might change vote to:

A: 100
B: 50
Z: 0

after Z is added.

Thus changing the difference between A and B for that ballot.

Ranked systems allow full ranking.  Adding another candidate just
requires that you insert the candidate into the rank order.

With range this might not be possible.  If the candidate has a rating
outside the max and min, a voter may have to rescale their prior
preferences.

If the assumption is that voters are just allowed add a rating for Z
and not change any of their other ratings, then it meets the 3
conditions and thus is a counter example to Arrow's theorem.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Andrew Myers

Jonathan Lundell wrote:

I don't have his proof in front of me (I'm on the road), but I'm pretty sure 
that it assumes ordinal ranking.
  
It seems fairly obvious that the theorem also holds for ratings, because 
ratings can be projected onto rankings without affecting any of Arrow's 
criteria. To put it another way, the proofs I have seen all apply to 
range-based methods in a straightforward way--there needs to be some 
fiddling with the proof to deal with ties, but that issue is not essential.


Letting voters give ratings doesn't mean you escape Arrow's Theorem.

-- Andrew

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Nov 16, 2009, at 2:15 PM, Andrew Myers wrote:

> Jonathan Lundell wrote:
>> This is in part Arrow's justification for dealing only with ordinal (vs 
>> cardinal) preferences in the Possibility Theorem. Add may label it 
>> preposterous, but it's the widely accepted view. Mine as well.
> Arrow's Theorem seems like a red herring in the context of the cardinal vs. 
> ordinal debate. IIA makes just as much sense when applied to range voting as 
> it does to ranked voting. Arrow was just making a simplifying assumption and 
> I don't see that it makes his results lose  generality.

I don't have his proof in front of me (I'm on the road), but I'm pretty sure 
that it assumes ordinal ranking.


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Andrew Myers

Jonathan Lundell wrote:
This is in part Arrow's justification for dealing only with ordinal 
(vs cardinal) preferences in the Possibility Theorem. Add may label it 
preposterous, but it's the widely accepted view. Mine as well.
Arrow's Theorem seems like a red herring in the context of the cardinal 
vs. ordinal debate. IIA makes just as much sense when applied to range 
voting as it does to ranked voting. Arrow was just making a simplifying 
assumption and I don't see that it makes his results lose  generality.


-- Andrew

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Nov 16, 2009, at 11:53 AM, Stéphane Rouillon wrote:

> Would this suggest it could be possible to overcome Arrow's theorem using 
> range ballots?
> I do not want to say Arrow's theorem is false. All I ask is:
> Are prefential ballots one of the hypothesis used in Arrow's theorem proof?

Because the context of Arrow's theorem is ordinal ballots, it doesn't apply (at 
least not directly) to range voting. Arrow felt that there were good and 
sufficient reasons to exclude cardinal preferences from consideration, and most 
social choice thinking has followed suit. That exclusion was not original with 
Arrow.

>  
> > From: jlund...@pobox.com
> > Date: Mon, 16 Nov 2009 11:43:10 -0600
> > To: an...@cs.cornell.edu
> > CC: election-meth...@electorama.com
> > Subject: Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval 
> > andrange voting?
> > 
> > On Nov 16, 2009, at 10:53 AM, Andrew Myers wrote:
> > 
> > > Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:
> > >> Notice that the requirement of Arrow that "social preferences be 
> > >> insensitive to variations in the intensity of preferences" was 
> > >> preposterous. Arrow apparently insisted on this because he believed that 
> > >> it was impossible to come up with any objective measure of preference 
> > >> intensity; however, that was simply his opinion and certainly isn't true 
> > >> where there is a cost to voting. 
> > > Arrow doesn't impose that requirement; that's not what IIA says.
> > 
> > This is in part Arrow's justification for dealing only with ordinal (vs 
> > cardinal) preferences in the Possibility Theorem. Add may label it 
> > preposterous, but it's the widely accepted view. Mine as well.
> > 
> > Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Stéphane Rouillon

Would this suggest it could be possible to overcome Arrow's theorem using range 
ballots?

I do not want to say Arrow's theorem is false. All I ask is:

Are prefential ballots one of the hypothesis used in Arrow's theorem proof?
 
> From: jlund...@pobox.com
> Date: Mon, 16 Nov 2009 11:43:10 -0600
> To: an...@cs.cornell.edu
> CC: election-meth...@electorama.com
> Subject: Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval 
> andrange voting?
> 
> On Nov 16, 2009, at 10:53 AM, Andrew Myers wrote:
> 
> > Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:
> >> Notice that the requirement of Arrow that "social preferences be 
> >> insensitive to variations in the intensity of preferences" was 
> >> preposterous. Arrow apparently insisted on this because he believed that 
> >> it was impossible to come up with any objective measure of preference 
> >> intensity; however, that was simply his opinion and certainly isn't true 
> >> where there is a cost to voting. 
> > Arrow doesn't impose that requirement; that's not what IIA says.
> 
> This is in part Arrow's justification for dealing only with ordinal (vs 
> cardinal) preferences in the Possibility Theorem. Add may label it 
> preposterous, but it's the widely accepted view. Mine as well.
> 
> Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info
  
Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Jonathan Lundell
On Nov 16, 2009, at 10:53 AM, Andrew Myers wrote:

> Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:
>> Notice that the requirement of Arrow that "social preferences be insensitive 
>> to variations in the intensity of preferences" was preposterous. Arrow 
>> apparently insisted on this because he believed that it was impossible to 
>> come up with any objective measure of preference intensity; however, that 
>> was simply his opinion and certainly isn't true where there is a cost to 
>> voting. 
> Arrow doesn't impose that requirement; that's not what IIA says.

This is in part Arrow's justification for dealing only with ordinal (vs 
cardinal) preferences in the Possibility Theorem. Add may label it 
preposterous, but it's the widely accepted view. Mine as well.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Andrew Myers

Abd ul-Rahman Lomax wrote:
Notice that the requirement of Arrow that "social preferences be 
insensitive to variations in the intensity of preferences" was 
preposterous. Arrow apparently insisted on this because he believed 
that it was impossible to come up with any objective measure of 
preference intensity; however, that was simply his opinion and 
certainly isn't true where there is a cost to voting. 

Arrow doesn't impose that requirement; that's not what IIA says.

-- Andrew

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-16 Thread Abd ul-Rahman Lomax

At 12:22 PM 11/8/2009, Terry Bouricius wrote:

A somewhat more accessible (and available online for free) analysis of
strategic vulnerability of various methods is in this doctoral paper by
James Green-Armytage ("Strategic voting and Strategic Nomination:
Comparing seven election methods"). He found that Range and Approval were
just about the worst in terms of manipulability.
http://econ.ucsb.edu/graduate/PhDResearch/electionstrategy10b.pdf


There is a great deal of confusion on the topic of "strategic 
voting," based on a shift in the definition that took place after 
Brams suggested Approval Voting as "strategy-free." Originally, 
strategic voting referred to expressing a preference contrary to 
one's sincere preference, in order to improve, in the eyes of the 
voter, the probability of a better outcome. In the context of ranked 
methods, the meaning was clear, and, for the most part, students of 
voting systems neglected the implications of equal ranking and the 
function of compromise in decision-making.


In that context, there is something offensive about strategic voting, 
it seems "dishonest." Yet strategic voting is how voters attempt to 
remedy defects in voting systems. The problem, if any, is in the 
voting system, not in the strategic voting itself. In a properly 
designed decision-making system, what we call "strategic voting" may 
facilitate a final decision or may postpone it, but would never harm 
the value of the outcome, unless it was a poor strategy that harms 
the outcome from the point of view of the voter, i.e., the voter 
would have been better off voting sincerely.


It's clear that in the real world, people have strong preferences and 
weak preferences. When preference is weak, the voter may rationally 
decide to equally rank voters; I know that in real elections, I 
sometimes have difficulty deciding which of two candidates to vote 
for; an equal ranking there would be "fully sincere," as an accurate 
expression of my preferences, and for me to prefer one over the other 
is actually insincere. Thus pure ranked voting systems force a kind 
of insincerity; equal ranking systems still allow the option of the 
expression of strict preference, so they only increase the options 
for expression open to the voter.


However, what about the situation where a voter does have a 
preference between two candidates, but opts to equally rank them? In 
a Range system of adequate resolution, a "fully sincere" vote should 
be possible, without strategic harm to the voter's interests, but 
this needs definition, which is elusive. Practical Range systems, 
with limited resolution, resemble Approval voting, where preference 
strength below a certain level results in equal ranking. And 
"preference strength" is not independent of the voter's judgment of 
the strategic situation.


I might prefer, say, Jan Kok for President, and I could write his 
name on the ballot, but there is a problem. I would prefer him, 
perhaps, to any candidate actually printed on the ballot, but if I 
rank him above one of the printed names, I'm almost certainly going 
to waste my vote. (Students of voting systems, again, have neglected 
the influence and implications of write-in votes, for, where write-in 
votes are possible, we could argue that most voters vote 
"insincerely" or "strategically." They do not write in their true 
favorite because it would waste their vote, thus they rank one of the 
possible winners above their favorite, which meets the classical 
definition of strategic voting.


I vote strategically so as to exercise maximum power from my right to 
vote, and this is, in fact, what we want voters to do, and what we 
should expect them to do. Voting is a method of making collective 
decisions, and collective decisions must necessarily involve, most of 
the time, some level of compromise, and compromise is "strategic," 
wherein I approve an outcome even though it is not my first preference.


The last classical neglect has been in the implications of majority 
approval or disapproval of an outcome. The study of voting systems 
has been focused on improving methods for making decisions from a 
single ballot. Major respect has been given to the Majority 
Criterion, because of basic democratic traditions, but there is no 
way to extract a majority-approved winner from a single ballot that 
is guaranteed to work, because the reality may be that there is no 
candidate approved by a majority. However, this problem was resolved 
long ago as to practical function: repeated balloting is used. Under 
Robert's Rules of Order, no election is valid unless approved by a 
majority of voters, and Robert's Rules does not allow restricting 
candidacies, i.e., the common runoff voting where the only eligible 
candidates in the runoff election are the top two from the primary, 
violates Robert's Rules, hence special bylaws are required if it is 
decided to implement this. However, a reasonable and not uncommon 
compromise is to

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Dave Ketchum

On Nov 10, 2009, at 7:58 AM, Matthew Welland wrote:

On Tuesday 10 November 2009 03:57:34 am you wrote:

Dear Matthew,

you wrote:
Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet"  
ideals.


  1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
 how they work in one or two sentences.


Well, here's a very simple "Condorcet" system which can easily be
explained in two sentences:

1. Let voters vote on candidate pairs, successively replacing the  
loser

with a different candidate, in a random order of candidates.
2. As soon as all candidates have been included, the winner of the  
last

pair is declared the overall winner.

This system is arguably the earliest example of a "Condorcet"  
system. It
was devised by Ramon Llull in the 13th century and was successfully  
used
for elections in monastaries. It is easily understood by the common  
man

since it resembles a procedure frequently used in child play.


That is an excellent description. Thanks.


Gives a feel for something good enough for their purposes - if there  
is a CW the CW wins.


BUT, if there is a cycle, the best candidate can lose to another cycle  
member - so better make sure the apparent CW gets compared with every  
other candidate.


I've always liked that specific system and think being Condorcet  
compliant

makes great sense in smaller elections or where a perfect choice is
critical.

Implementing it on a large scale seems tough and actually voting in  
it seems
tedious. If there are N candidates am I forced to make N-1  
decisions? If

there is a short circuit way to do the vote then it might be workable.


In voting you could start with thinking who you would approve of.   
Then vote for them, while ignoring the others that you like less.  Do  
any of:

 Approve them by giving them the same rank.
 Vote for the best as in FPTP.
 Rank them to show your preference for better vs lesser.



The improvement over approval still seems marginal, especially in  
large
elections and I think the cost for implementing, tabulating and  
voting is

much higher,


Agreed the implementing costs - mostly in being able to do this.  With  
the ability you get a big help in some elections and less or little in  
others (like 0 when only two candidates).


Tabulating a ballot gets to be labor when a voter ranks many candidates.

Being able to determine winner from the N*N array was an implementing  
cost, but then easy to do via computer (assuming use of an easy  
variant of Condorcet).


Voters who were happy with FPTP will see no benefit - but no cost once  
they see they can vote as they have before.


Voters who have studied range/score will make two groups:  sad to be  
unable to express the exact size of their likes/dislikes; thankful for  
the easier decisions involved here.


Voters who want to rank higher those they like best will be thankful  
to get past approval.


Dave Ketchum



Yours, Jobst




Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Matthew Welland
On Tuesday 10 November 2009 03:57:34 am you wrote:
> Dear Matthew,
>
> you wrote:
> > Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
> >
> >1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
> >   how they work in one or two sentences.
>
> Well, here's a very simple "Condorcet" system which can easily be
> explained in two sentences:
>
> 1. Let voters vote on candidate pairs, successively replacing the loser
> with a different candidate, in a random order of candidates.
> 2. As soon as all candidates have been included, the winner of the last
> pair is declared the overall winner.
>
> This system is arguably the earliest example of a "Condorcet" system. It
> was devised by Ramon Llull in the 13th century and was successfully used
> for elections in monastaries. It is easily understood by the common man
> since it resembles a procedure frequently used in child play.

That is an excellent description. Thanks.

I've always liked that specific system and think being Condorcet compliant 
makes great sense in smaller elections or where a perfect choice is 
critical.

Implementing it on a large scale seems tough and actually voting in it seems 
tedious. If there are N candidates am I forced to make N-1 decisions? If 
there is a short circuit way to do the vote then it might be workable. 

The improvement over approval still seems marginal, especially in large 
elections and I think the cost for implementing, tabulating and voting is 
much higher,


> Yours, Jobst
>
> Matthew Welland schrieb:
> > Thanks all for the discussion and pointers. I still can't concretely
> > conclude anything yet but here are some rambling and random thoughts
> > based on what was said and my prior experiences.
> >
> > Plurality
> >
> >1. Leads to two lowest common denominator parties which are not
> >   accountable to the voters. This conclusion supported by real
> > world observation.
> >2. Feels right to the non-critical mind, "one man, one vote"
> >3. Very fast at the polls
> >
> > Approval
> >
> >1. Encourages participation of minor parties and thus should keep
> > the big guys paying attention to a wider base.
> >2. Almost zero marginal implementation cost. Hanging chads count
> > just fine :)
> >3. Understandable by anyone but feels wrong at first "not fair, you
> >   get more than one vote".
> >4. Apparently has a terrible flaw but no one seems to be able to
> >   articulate it in layman terms. No real world experience available
> >   to illustrate the problem. Here is where I need to learn more.
> >   Data provided to date is unconvincing to me.
> >5. Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate
> >   between "I like", "I like a lot" etc. (note: this seems like
> >   perfectionism to me. Large numbers of voters and opinions all
> > over the bell curve should make individual expression at the greater
> > level of granularity irrelevant.)
> >6. Very fast at the polls. Pick yer favorites and head home for beer
> >   and telly.
> >
> > Range
> >
> >1. Can break the vicious cycle of plurality
> >2. Not voting for someone at all can have a strong influence on
> >   election outcome. This is very non-intuitive and would take some
> >   getting used to.
> >3. Allows for nuanced voting.
> >4. Pain in the ass at the polls (relatively speaking). You can't
> >   safely disregard the candidates you don't care about so you
> > *have* to assign everyone a ranking, possibly addressable by defaulting
> > to zero for all candidates? This is considered a feature and I agree it
> > has merit. But in reality it is a deal breaker for joe six pack and co.
> > (and for lazy sobs like me).
> >
> > IRV
> >
> >1. Demonstrably broken. 'nuff said.
> >
> > Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
> >
> >1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
> >   how they work in one or two sentences.
> >2. Technically superior to other systems.
> >3. Not clear what problem with approval they would solve. Unless you
> >   are a perfectionist and insist that individuals express nuances
> > of opinion...
> >
> > Some time ago I put together a site (primitive and unfinished[i]) to
> > promote approval voting and in the process I spent a lot of time trying
> > different systems on the web and repeatedly testing my own site. I
> > noticed some interesting things from all that playing around.
> >
> >1. It was very uncomfortable to go back to plurality after trying
> >   other systems. It "feels" unfair and broken.
> >2. It was very tedious voting in any of the ranking systems.
> >3. Approval felt boring but good.
> >
> > I have checked in on this list now and then and I admit I don't have
> > the time or skills to follow all the arguments but it strikes me that
> > approval voting is good enough to break the deadlock, at least i

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Juho
This method is also quite hand countable (unlike many other Condorcet  
methods). That was certainly an important feature in those days :-).  
It has some randomness in the results (when no Condorcet winner exists).


Here's another one. Elect the candidate that wins all others in  
pairwise comparisons. If there is no such candidate, elect the one  
that needs least number of additional votes to win all others.  (This  
is of course the famous minmax(margins) that I have promoted quite  
often.)


Juho


On Nov 10, 2009, at 12:57 PM, Jobst Heitzig wrote:


Dear Matthew,

you wrote:

Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.

  1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
 how they work in one or two sentences.


Well, here's a very simple "Condorcet" system which can easily be
explained in two sentences:

1. Let voters vote on candidate pairs, successively replacing the  
loser

with a different candidate, in a random order of candidates.
2. As soon as all candidates have been included, the winner of the  
last

pair is declared the overall winner.

This system is arguably the earliest example of a "Condorcet"  
system. It
was devised by Ramon Llull in the 13th century and was successfully  
used
for elections in monastaries. It is easily understood by the common  
man

since it resembles a procedure frequently used in child play.

Yours, Jobst


Matthew Welland schrieb:

Thanks all for the discussion and pointers. I still can't concretely
conclude anything yet but here are some rambling and random thoughts
based on what was said and my prior experiences.

Plurality

  1. Leads to two lowest common denominator parties which are not
 accountable to the voters. This conclusion supported by real  
world

 observation.
  2. Feels right to the non-critical mind, "one man, one vote"
  3. Very fast at the polls

Approval

  1. Encourages participation of minor parties and thus should keep  
the

 big guys paying attention to a wider base.
  2. Almost zero marginal implementation cost. Hanging chads count  
just

 fine :)
  3. Understandable by anyone but feels wrong at first "not fair, you
 get more than one vote".
  4. Apparently has a terrible flaw but no one seems to be able to
 articulate it in layman terms. No real world experience  
available

 to illustrate the problem. Here is where I need to learn more.
 Data provided to date is unconvincing to me.
  5. Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate
 between "I like", "I like a lot" etc. (note: this seems like
 perfectionism to me. Large numbers of voters and opinions all  
over

 the bell curve should make individual expression at the greater
 level of granularity irrelevant.)
  6. Very fast at the polls. Pick yer favorites and head home for  
beer

 and telly.

Range

  1. Can break the vicious cycle of plurality
  2. Not voting for someone at all can have a strong influence on
 election outcome. This is very non-intuitive and would take some
 getting used to.
  3. Allows for nuanced voting.
  4. Pain in the ass at the polls (relatively speaking). You can't
 safely disregard the candidates you don't care about so you  
*have*

 to assign everyone a ranking, possibly addressable by defaulting
 to zero for all candidates? This is considered a feature and I
 agree it has merit. But in reality it is a deal breaker for joe
 six pack and co. (and for lazy sobs like me).

IRV

  1. Demonstrably broken. 'nuff said.

Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.

  1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
 how they work in one or two sentences.
  2. Technically superior to other systems.
  3. Not clear what problem with approval they would solve. Unless  
you
 are a perfectionist and insist that individuals express  
nuances of

 opinion...

Some time ago I put together a site (primitive and unfinished[i]) to
promote approval voting and in the process I spent a lot of time  
trying

different systems on the web and repeatedly testing my own site. I
noticed some interesting things from all that playing around.

  1. It was very uncomfortable to go back to plurality after trying
 other systems. It "feels" unfair and broken.
  2. It was very tedious voting in any of the ranking systems.
  3. Approval felt boring but good.

I have checked in on this list now and then and I admit I don't  
have the

time or skills to follow all the arguments but it strikes me that
approval voting is good enough to break the deadlock, at least in US
politics and that it doesn't have any major flaws. The very
understandable desire to be able to articulate in a finer grained  
way in
your vote is perfectionism. With millions of voters, for every  
person on
the fence about a particular candidate there will be some to either  
side

who will essentially make or break the vote

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Robert,

you wrote:
> Round Robin tournament, Ranked Ballot:  The contestant who wins in a
> single match is the candidate who is preferred over the other in more
> ballots.  The candidate who is elected to office is the contestant who
> loses to no one in the round robin tournament.
> 
> that's two sentences and two labels.

But it's incomplete as well...

Yours, Jobst

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Jobst Heitzig
Dear Matthew,

you wrote:
> Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
>
>1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
>   how they work in one or two sentences.

Well, here's a very simple "Condorcet" system which can easily be
explained in two sentences:

1. Let voters vote on candidate pairs, successively replacing the loser
with a different candidate, in a random order of candidates.
2. As soon as all candidates have been included, the winner of the last
pair is declared the overall winner.

This system is arguably the earliest example of a "Condorcet" system. It
was devised by Ramon Llull in the 13th century and was successfully used
for elections in monastaries. It is easily understood by the common man
since it resembles a procedure frequently used in child play.

Yours, Jobst


Matthew Welland schrieb:
> Thanks all for the discussion and pointers. I still can't concretely
> conclude anything yet but here are some rambling and random thoughts
> based on what was said and my prior experiences.
> 
> Plurality
> 
>1. Leads to two lowest common denominator parties which are not
>   accountable to the voters. This conclusion supported by real world
>   observation.
>2. Feels right to the non-critical mind, "one man, one vote"
>3. Very fast at the polls
> 
> Approval
> 
>1. Encourages participation of minor parties and thus should keep the
>   big guys paying attention to a wider base.
>2. Almost zero marginal implementation cost. Hanging chads count just
>   fine :)
>3. Understandable by anyone but feels wrong at first "not fair, you
>   get more than one vote".
>4. Apparently has a terrible flaw but no one seems to be able to
>   articulate it in layman terms. No real world experience available
>   to illustrate the problem. Here is where I need to learn more.
>   Data provided to date is unconvincing to me.
>5. Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate
>   between "I like", "I like a lot" etc. (note: this seems like
>   perfectionism to me. Large numbers of voters and opinions all over
>   the bell curve should make individual expression at the greater
>   level of granularity irrelevant.)
>6. Very fast at the polls. Pick yer favorites and head home for beer
>   and telly.
> 
> Range
> 
>1. Can break the vicious cycle of plurality
>2. Not voting for someone at all can have a strong influence on
>   election outcome. This is very non-intuitive and would take some
>   getting used to.
>3. Allows for nuanced voting.
>4. Pain in the ass at the polls (relatively speaking). You can't
>   safely disregard the candidates you don't care about so you *have*
>   to assign everyone a ranking, possibly addressable by defaulting
>   to zero for all candidates? This is considered a feature and I
>   agree it has merit. But in reality it is a deal breaker for joe
>   six pack and co. (and for lazy sobs like me).
> 
> IRV
> 
>1. Demonstrably broken. 'nuff said.
> 
> Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
> 
>1. No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain
>   how they work in one or two sentences.
>2. Technically superior to other systems.
>3. Not clear what problem with approval they would solve. Unless you
>   are a perfectionist and insist that individuals express nuances of
>   opinion... 
> 
> Some time ago I put together a site (primitive and unfinished[i]) to
> promote approval voting and in the process I spent a lot of time trying
> different systems on the web and repeatedly testing my own site. I
> noticed some interesting things from all that playing around.
> 
>1. It was very uncomfortable to go back to plurality after trying
>   other systems. It "feels" unfair and broken.
>2. It was very tedious voting in any of the ranking systems.
>3. Approval felt boring but good. 
> 
> I have checked in on this list now and then and I admit I don't have the
> time or skills to follow all the arguments but it strikes me that
> approval voting is good enough to break the deadlock, at least in US
> politics and that it doesn't have any major flaws. The very
> understandable desire to be able to articulate in a finer grained way in
> your vote is perfectionism. With millions of voters, for every person on
> the fence about a particular candidate there will be some to either side
> who will essentially make or break the vote. If you are on the fence,
> approve or disapprove, it won't matter.
> 
> So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval? I'm
> not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect results. I'm
> interested in flaws that result in big problems such as those we see
> with plurality and IRV.
> 
> 
> [i] www.approvalvote.org
> 
> 
> 
> -

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Raph Frank
On Tue, Nov 10, 2009 at 8:18 AM, robert bristow-johnson
 wrote:
> i will say this: even though it is prohibited in the present IRV that
> Burlington VT has, there is no reason that ties should not be allowed in any
> ranked ballot.

It is unclear how this should work with IRV.

My personal preference is that both votes would count at full
strength.  The other possibility is that they are divided equally
between all remaining candidates.

In both cases, the count is more difficult.

> is that putting it in an accessible context?  so then with Approval voting,
> for sure this grandma marks "X" by her grandson's name.  but does she or
> doesn't she Approve her good ol' incumbent?  Approval doesn't let you mark
> it "Approve except in the race with my top choice."

However, if you know who the top-2 are, then this isn't a major problem.

The point with approval is that it tends to converge to a condorcet
winner, or a candidate who is almost as good.

It might even be better at finding honest condorcet winners than an
actual condorcet method, assuming that the voters vote tactically in
both cases.

> i mean isn't that the essential flaw?  e.g. the flaw with the Electoral
> College is that sometimes it elects the wrong candidate.  it does pretty
> good when it selects the same winner as the popular vote, but when it
> disagrees with the popular vote it *never* creates more legitimacy or
> confidence in the election results.  so then why have it?  what good is it?

It would have probably been better if they set it up so the college
actually meets, but then add a requirement that the majority of the
electors must agree.

If combined with PR at the state level when electing electors, then a
candidate who has the support of the majority of the population should
end up winnng.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread Juho

On Nov 10, 2009, at 6:48 AM, Matthew Welland wrote:

Thanks all for the discussion and pointers. I still can't concretely  
conclude anything yet but here are some rambling and random thoughts  
based on what was said and my prior experiences.


Plurality
Leads to two lowest common denominator parties which are not  
accountable to the voters. This conclusion supported by real world  
observation.
Use of single winner districts has this tendency in general. The other  
single winner methods below give some more space to third parties but  
if you want to get rid of favouring the major parties and get  
proportional representation of all the parties/interest groups then  
some proportional multi winner methods method could be used.



Feels right to the non-critical mind, "one man, one vote"
Very fast at the polls
Approval
Encourages participation of minor parties and thus should keep the  
big guys paying attention to a wider base.
Almost zero marginal implementation cost. Hanging chads count just  
fine :)
Understandable by anyone but feels wrong at first "not fair, you get  
more than one vote".
Apparently has a terrible flaw but no one seems to be able to  
articulate it in layman terms. No real world experience available to  
illustrate the problem. Here is where I need to learn more. Data  
provided to date is unconvincing to me.
Here's one example. We have left and right wings with approximately  
50%-50% support. Left wing has two candidates (L1, L2). Most right  
wing voters approve only the right wing candidate (R). Some left wing  
candidates approve both leftist candidates but some approve only one  
of them. Right wing candidate wins.


In order to avoid this problem left wing might recommend all its  
supporters to approve both left wing candidates. If they do so left  
wing will not have the above mentioned problem of vote splitting but  
on the other hand L1 and L2 will get the same number of votes since  
nobody can indicate if L1 is better than L2 or the other way around.  
Choice between L1 and L2 is quite random since the decision will be  
left to those left wing voters who don't follow the recommended  
strategy and to those right wing voters who approve also one of the  
left wing candidates.


In this example the problem thus is that voters can not express at the  
same time both that left/right wing is better and that one of the  
candidates of that wing is better than some others of them. This  
problem may lead to interest within the left wing to nominate only one  
candidate (=no spoilers, no leftist third parties) and we might be  
close to the plurality related problems again. Approval may work in  
this case quite well as long as the third party is small and all its  
voters understand that they should approve also one of the major  
parties (left), but when the support of that third candidate grows  
things become more complicated.


Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate between  
"I like", "I like a lot" etc.  (note: this seems like perfectionism  
to me. Large numbers of  voters and opinions all over the bell curve  
should make individual expression at the greater level of  
granularity irrelevant.)
Out of the discussed methods Range is the only one that can express  
"like"/"like a lot". But it has its own problems (partly due to this  
property).


The example above tries to demonstrate that while large number of  
sincere Approval votes might statistically lead to a good result there  
is the risk that the votes will be not as well in balance (for  
strategy and candidate positioning related reasons). I think it is a  
general assumption that in Approval voters would not vote sincerely in  
th sense that they would approve those candidates that they consider  
"approvable" but they would follow strategy "approve part of the  
leaders (likely winners) and candidates that you prefer to them".


Very fast at the polls. Pick yer favorites and head home for beer  
and telly.

Range
Can break the vicious cycle of plurality
I didn't understand this. (If this is about the two party dominance I  
commented already above.)


Not voting for someone at all can have a strong influence on  
election outcome. This is very non-intuitive and would take some  
getting used to.

Allows for nuanced voting.
This is the benefit of Range. The related problem is that while this  
works well in non-competitive elections (e.g. polls, olympics with  
neutral judges) in competitive ones (e.g. political elections) voters  
have an incentive to exaggerate. This may lead to Approval-like  
behaviour where most voters give min and max points to most  
candidates. In that case Range would be very much like Approval.)


Pain in the ass at the polls (relatively speaking). You can't safely  
disregard the candidates you don't care about so you *have* to  
assign everyone a ranking, possibly addressable by defaulting to  
zero for all candidates? This is considered a feature and I a

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-10 Thread robert bristow-johnson


On Nov 9, 2009, at 11:48 PM, Matthew Welland wrote:


Approval
Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate  
between "I like", "I like a lot" etc. (note: this seems like  
perfectionism to me. Large numbers of voters and opinions all over  
the bell curve should make individual expression at the greater  
level of granularity irrelevant.)


we should be able to express our preferences.  Approval reduces our  
metric of preference to a 1-bit number, a dichotomy.  i would like to  
have more bits in that number.



Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals.
No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain how  
they work in one or two sentences.


Round Robin tournament, Ranked Ballot:  The contestant who wins in a  
single match is the candidate who is preferred over the other in more  
ballots.  The candidate who is elected to office is the contestant  
who loses to no one in the round robin tournament.


that's two sentences and two labels.


Technically superior to other systems.
Not clear what problem with approval they would solve. Unless you  
are a perfectionist and insist that individuals express nuances of  
opinion...


like which candidate they like better than the other candidate?


It was very tedious voting in any of the ranking systems.


it's tedious to decide who you like better?  who you would prefer if  
any two candidates are presented?


i will say this: even though it is prohibited in the present IRV that  
Burlington VT has, there is no reason that ties should not be allowed  
in any ranked ballot.


but i would agree it would be tedious to allocate preference points  
in Range.



So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval?


it's essentially like Plurality except you get to mark "X" on more  
than one candidate (like you do in multi-seat races).  i don't like  
it for multi-seat (in the state senate for the county i am in, all of  
our senators are elected from the county at large and there are 6 for  
my county) i always think i'm hurting a candidate i actively support  
by voting for another candidate from the same party that i approve  
of.  so then i mark "X" on only one candidate and, if enough people  
vote tactically like that, the election works like Plurality.  we  
want an improvement to Plurality because we might like a three or  
four party system (or 3 parties and viable independents).  we want to  
not have to consider the likelihood of wasting our vote by deciding  
who to Approve of.  we know we approve of the candidate we support,  
but it is a tactical decision to decide if you approve of a candidate  
you would normally approve of but is not the candidate that you have  
actively supported.


like what if you're a little old lady and you like and support you  
representative legislator for re-election.  and you support him over  
any likely candidate from the other party, and it might be close so  
you wanna feel like you helped him.  but your grandson that you  
cherish and are proud is running as an independent.  in fact you gave  
money to your grandson's campaign.  you support your grandson.  you  
don't know if he'll win or not, but you do not want to harm his  
chances.  you also don't want your good ol' incumbent you've always  
supported.  you want to make sure he doesn't lose to the other major  
party candidate.  but you wouldn't mind harming his chances if the  
race ended up between him and your grandson.


is that putting it in an accessible context?  so then with Approval  
voting, for sure this grandma marks "X" by her grandson's name.  but  
does she or doesn't she Approve her good ol' incumbent?  Approval  
doesn't let you mark it "Approve except in the race with my top choice."


I'm not interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect  
results. I'm interested in flaws that result in big problems such  
as those we see with plurality and IRV.


how 'bout electing the wrong candidate?

i mean isn't that the essential flaw?  e.g. the flaw with the  
Electoral College is that sometimes it elects the wrong candidate.   
it does pretty good when it selects the same winner as the popular  
vote, but when it disagrees with the popular vote it *never* creates  
more legitimacy or confidence in the election results.  so then why  
have it?  what good is it?  it's either ineffective in "filtering"  
the popular vote or, when it *is* effective it makes matters worse.   
such a useful device!


with Condorcet you elect the candidate that, from the set of voters  
who have an opinion, is preferred by a majority of that set over any  
other candidate that you pick.


any winner of an election system that elects a candidate who is not  
the Condercet winner, has elected someone whom was rejected by the  
voting majority in favor of the Condorcet winner who wasn't elected.   
how is that congruent to the principle of democracy?  do we have  
elections and explicitly give it t

Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting? (long)

2009-11-09 Thread Matthew Welland
Thanks all for the discussion and pointers. I still can't concretely 
conclude anything yet but here are some rambling and random thoughts based 
on what was said and my prior experiences.

Plurality
Leads to two lowest common denominator parties which are not accountable to 
the voters. This conclusion supported by real world observation.
Feels right to the non-critical mind, "one man, one vote"
Very fast at the polls
Approval
Encourages participation of minor parties and thus should keep the big guys 
paying attention to a wider base.
Almost zero marginal implementation cost. Hanging chads count just fine :)
Understandable by anyone but feels wrong at first "not fair, you get more 
than one vote".
Apparently has a terrible flaw but no one seems to be able to articulate it 
in layman terms. No real world experience available to illustrate the 
problem. Here is where I need to learn more. Data provided to date is 
unconvincing to me.
Does not meet the desire of some to be able to differentiate between "I 
like", "I like a lot" etc.  (note: this seems like perfectionism to me. 
Large numbers of  voters and opinions all over the bell curve should make 
individual expression at the greater level of granularity irrelevant.)
Very fast at the polls. Pick yer favorites and head home for beer and telly.
Range
Can break the vicious cycle of plurality
Not voting for someone at all can have a strong influence on election 
outcome. This is very non-intuitive and would take some getting used to. 
Allows for nuanced voting. 
Pain in the ass at the polls (relatively speaking). You can't safely 
disregard the candidates you don't care about so you *have* to assign 
everyone a ranking, possibly addressable by defaulting to zero for all 
candidates? This is considered a feature and I agree it has merit. But in 
reality it is a deal breaker for joe six pack and co. (and for lazy sobs 
like me).
IRV
Demonstrably broken. 'nuff said.
Suite of complicated systems that strive to reach "Condorcet" ideals. 
No regular bloke would ever trust 'em because you can't explain how they 
work in one or two sentences.
Technically superior to other systems.
Not clear what problem with approval they would solve. Unless you are a 
perfectionist and insist that individuals express nuances of opinion... 
Some time ago I put together a site (primitive and unfinished[i]) to promote 
approval voting and in the process I spent a lot of time trying different 
systems on the web and repeatedly testing my own site. I noticed some 
interesting things from all that playing around.
It was very uncomfortable to go back to plurality after trying other 
systems. It "feels" unfair and broken.
It was very tedious voting in any of the ranking systems.
Approval felt boring but good. 
I have checked in on this list now and then and I admit I don't have the 
time or skills to follow all the arguments but it strikes me that approval  
voting is good enough to break the deadlock, at least in US politics and 
that it doesn't have any major flaws. The very understandable desire to be 
able to articulate in a finer grained way in your vote is perfectionism. With 
millions of voters, for every person on the fence about a particular 
candidate there will be some to either side who will essentially make or 
break the vote. If you are on the fence, approve or disapprove, it won't 
matter.
So, to re-frame my question. What is the fatal flaw with approval? I'm not 
interested in subtle flaws that result in imperfect results. I'm interested 
in flaws that result in big problems such as those we see with plurality and 
IRV.

[i] www.approvalvote.org


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-08 Thread Juho

On Nov 8, 2009, at 8:43 PM, Raph Frank wrote:

On Sun, Nov 8, 2009 at 5:22 PM, Terry Bouricius > wrote:
A somewhat more accessible (and available online for free) analysis  
of
strategic vulnerability of various methods is in this doctoral  
paper by

James Green-Armytage ("Strategic voting and Strategic Nomination:
Comparing seven election methods"). He found that Range and  
Approval were

just about the worst in terms of manipulability.
http://econ.ucsb.edu/graduate/PhDResearch/electionstrategy10b.pdf


His assumptions about how people vote are not very realistic.


There are many small things in the paper that can be discussed but I  
think he gives a good solid basis for further discussions and  
improvements to make the results more accurate from real life  
modelling point of view. This is a good attempt to describe the  
practical properties of various methods from a neutral scientific  
point of view.




Plurality -> vote for favourite

Top 2 - run-off -> vote for favourite and then best of top 2
Alternative vote -> honest ranking
Minimax -> honest ranking
Borda -> honest ranking

Approval -> vote for better than mean


Two short comments on this one.
- One could alternatively assume that sincere voting in Approval would  
already be (at least partially) based on applying the basic strategy  
of trying to make a difference between the (two, three) most probable  
winners. Strategic voting would mean additional strategies on top of  
the basic one.
- Unfortunately the model that James Green-Armytage used was not yet  
able to handle strategic nominations in Approval. I think cloning has  
an impact in Approval (clones may easily harm you).


Juho


Range -> give max to favourite and min to least favourite and scale  
the rest


His analysis is pretty interesting and he has created a condition for
each method that is needed for the winner to be vulnerable to loss if
a group of voters switched their vote.

In practice, people are able to handle the basics of plurality  
strategy.


It would be interesting to see how approval scores with a pre-election
poll being performed.  For example, each voter approves based on a
mean threshold and then use the result of that election to work out
the top-2.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for  
list info



Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-08 Thread Michael Allan
Terry and Matthew,

Terry Bouricius wrote:
> I'm not sure if it is quite at the layman level, but Prof. Nicloaus 
> Tideman's recent book "Collective Decisions and Voting" has an analysis of 
> vulnerability to strategic manipulation of virtually every single-winner 
> voting method that has ever been proposed...

He leaves out the methods that facilitate communication among the
voters, namely liquid democracy, delegable proxy or delegate cascade.
These are all forms of continuous, peer-to-peer voting.  Their overall
are difficult to manipulate, except by force of reason.  (This assumes
that all votes/voters are public.)

These methods are not proof against micro-strategy by individual
voters, but their combined effects cannot significantly sway the
overall results (not in theory, anyway).

> A somewhat more accessible (and available online for free) analysis of 
> strategic vulnerability of various methods is in this doctoral paper by 
> James Green-Armytage ("Strategic voting and Strategic Nomination: 
> Comparing seven election methods"). He found that Range and Approval were 
> just about the worst in terms of manipulability.
> http://econ.ucsb.edu/graduate/PhDResearch/electionstrategy10b.pdf

He makes the same omission, at least in that paper.  Please, does
anyone know where Green-Armytage analyzes his "liquid democracy" from
the angle of strategic voting?

Matthew Welland wrote:
> It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
> strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
> improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
> analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or supports this
> assertion?
> 
> Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or range
> voting?

In that they encourage voters to be manipulative.  In terms of action
theory, these voting methods (and almost all others) are tools of
strategic action.  The voter uses them in an attempt to attain a
preconceived end.  So they are tools of *teleological* action.

But to attain the preconceived end, the voter must calculate on the
behaviour of other voters.  This introduces a social aspect to the
action, which is therefore subclassed as *strategic* action.

The only alternative in this context is *communicative* action.  In
communicative action, the voters coordinate their voting behaviour by
discussion that is aimed at mutual understanding and consensus.
Ordinary voting methods do not support this.^[2]  For this you need a
communicative method, such as continuous, peer-to-peer voting (top).

[1] I'm not sure that the terminology aligns perfectly with voting
theory.  Action theory is from sociology:

Jürgen Habermas.  1981.  The Theory of Communicative Action.
Volume 1.  Reason and Rationalization of Society.  Translated by
Thomas McCarthy, 1984.  Beacon Hill, Boston.  pp. 75-101.

[2] Not only do these voting methods not support communicative action,
but they serve as substitutes for it.  They are therefore defined
as "steering media".  The archetypal steering medium is money,
which serves as a substitute for inter-communicative bartering.
[ref. Vol. 2 of above]

-- 
Michael Allan

Toronto, 647-436-4521
Skype michael_c_allan
http://zelea.com/


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-08 Thread Raph Frank
On Sun, Nov 8, 2009 at 5:22 PM, Terry Bouricius
 wrote:
> A somewhat more accessible (and available online for free) analysis of
> strategic vulnerability of various methods is in this doctoral paper by
> James Green-Armytage ("Strategic voting and Strategic Nomination:
> Comparing seven election methods"). He found that Range and Approval were
> just about the worst in terms of manipulability.
> http://econ.ucsb.edu/graduate/PhDResearch/electionstrategy10b.pdf

His assumptions about how people vote are not very realistic.

Plurality -> vote for favourite

Top 2 - run-off -> vote for favourite and then best of top 2
Alternative vote -> honest ranking
Minimax -> honest ranking
Borda -> honest ranking

Approval -> vote for better than mean
Range -> give max to favourite and min to least favourite and scale the rest

His analysis is pretty interesting and he has created a condition for
each method that is needed for the winner to be vulnerable to loss if
a group of voters switched their vote.

In practice, people are able to handle the basics of plurality strategy.

It would be interesting to see how approval scores with a pre-election
poll being performed.  For example, each voter approves based on a
mean threshold and then use the result of that election to work out
the top-2.

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Re: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval andrange voting?

2009-11-08 Thread Terry Bouricius
Matthew,

I'm not sure if it is quite at the layman level, but Prof. Nicloaus 
Tideman's recent book "Collective Decisions and Voting" has an analysis of 
vulnerability to strategic manipulation of virtually every single-winner 
voting method that has ever been proposed and concludes that Range Voting 
along with Borda and four other methods "have defects that are so serious 
as to disqualify them from consideration." (page 238). Range Voting 
advocates on this list dispute his definition of "resistance to strategy."

A somewhat more accessible (and available online for free) analysis of 
strategic vulnerability of various methods is in this doctoral paper by 
James Green-Armytage ("Strategic voting and Strategic Nomination: 
Comparing seven election methods"). He found that Range and Approval were 
just about the worst in terms of manipulability.
http://econ.ucsb.edu/graduate/PhDResearch/electionstrategy10b.pdf


Terry Bouricius


 - Original Message - 
From: "Matthew Welland" 
To: "Election Methods Mailing List" 
Sent: Saturday, November 07, 2009 3:12 PM
Subject: [EM] Anyone got a good analysis on limitations of approval 
andrange voting?


It seems to me that approval and range voting eliminate most of the
strategic opportunity in single winner elections and the marginal
improvement of other methods is fairly small. Can anyone point me to
analysis, preferably at a layman level, that contradicts or supports this
assertion?

Or, in succinct terms, what are the strategic flaws in approval or range
voting?

Thanks,

Matt
-=-

Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info


Election-Methods mailing list - see http://electorama.com/em for list info