[peirce-l] Re: Existent vs Real

2006-02-20 Thread Irving Anellis
Jim Platt wrote (in part):
 - Original Message -
 From: Jim Piat [EMAIL PROTECTED]
 To: Peirce Discussion Forum peirce-l@lyris.ttu.edu
 Subject: [peirce-l] Re: Existent vs Real
 Date: Sun, 19 Feb 2006 12:02:23 -0500
 
 
 
 
 
 Dear Iving,
 
 Thanks for those observation.  

---
It is important to understand that I was running on memory here, and I'm 
certain that there are plenty of folks on this list who can be of better 
service in respect to explicating Meinong's ontology. Judging from the growing 
amount of recent books on Meinong, I would think that his ideas have begun to 
overcome the stigma attached to them by Russell in On Denoting (1905). I do 
recommend looking at Meinong's original, before going to the many commentaries. 
I recall that even Nick Griffin, a respected Russell scholar, published a paper 
in which he argued that Russell played somewhat fast and loose with Meinong's 
ideas, both when reviewing Meinong's writings and when working out the theory 
of descriptions in On Denoting as a way to get rid of existence claims about 
uch inconvenient entities as round squares, Pegasus and the present King of 
France. As I recall, the best presentation that Meinong gave of his theory was 
in his Ueber Gegenstaende hoeherer Ordnung..., the theme of which, if not the 
opening line of which, ran something like: Es gibt keine Vorstellungen ohne 
etwas zu vorstellen.

Irving Anellis



-- 
___

Search for businesses by name, location, or phone number.  -Lycos Yellow Pages

http://r.lycos.com/r/yp_emailfooter/http://yellowpages.lycos.com/default.asp?SRC=lycos10


---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber archive@mail-archive.com



[peirce-l] Re: Existent vs Real

2006-02-19 Thread Jim Piat

Irving Anellis wrote (in part):

To be able to formulate the judgment that 'The present King of France is 
bald' meant for Meinong that the present King of France must have being at 
some ontological level or another (i.e have some sort of ontological status, 
even if he does not exist) in order to be able to formulate the judgment, 
and assert it, that he's bald. The same must hold, Meinong would argue, even 
if one were to deny the existence of the present King of France, or the 
round square. Just being able to take it as a subject of a judgment , to be 
able to represent it, gives it, ipso facto, some ontological status. Thus 
Meinong. ... And what Moltke Gram once alliteratively called (if I can 
remember back to 1970) 'Meinong's muddled metaphysical mire'.



Dear Iving,

Thanks for those observation.  I hope it was clear that I side with Meinong 
on this issue.  I think it is better to sort through the ways we actually do 
deal with various kinds of objects rather than trying to dismiss them by 
closing our eyes and insisting they don't exist  -- as if existence were the 
only real mode of being.  (All the while knowing full well  that we have not 
only the potential to open our eyes but that even while we deny their 
existence we are mindful of them even with our eyes closed.)  So no,  I'm 
not a nominalist.  Though I salute the nominalists  for first calling to my 
attention that there was a problem with some of my unexamined assumptions 
about certain types of objects.   Faulty assumptions that later Wittgenstein 
and Peirce helped me to clarify and to begin to rise above.  Or so it seems 
to me just now.  And for the first time in this particular way  -- not to 
put too fine a point on it.


Part of my wacky (often exasperating)  take on most issues is due to my lack 
of a historical persepective.  My exposure to philosophy and its concerns 
has been very spotty and is full of large gaps about subjects commonly known 
to most who have studied philosophy sytematically.  Passion refusing to 
submit to discipline.  But I must say that most who have studied philosophy 
systematically are amazingly tolerant of those of us who have not.  The 
famed philosophical openness is definitely alive and well on the Peirce 
list. And the passion.  And yes the discipline too  -- as collectively we 
strive toward truth.  Perhaps passion and error are an individual matter 
while discipline (in the best dialogical sense) and truth are a communal 
matter.


Thanks again,
Jim Piat 


---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber archive@mail-archive.com



[peirce-l] Re: Existent vs Real

2006-02-19 Thread Irving Anellis
For anyone who may have missed it, I'm forwarding Alan Ryan's obituary of P. F. 
Strawson, as posted on Russell-l.


Irving Anellis:


Message: 4
From: Kenneth Blackwell [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Subject: Obit. of Strawson
To: Russell Studies Discussions [EMAIL PROTECTED]
Date: Sat, 18 Feb 2006 10:09:07 -0500

Here's an obituary of Peter Strawson by Alan Ryan. -- Ken


Sir Peter Strawson

Distinguished Oxford philosopher whose spare, elegant work
made sense of Kant's metaphysics

Published: 18 February 2006

Peter Frederick Strawson, philosopher: born London 23
November 1919; Assistant Lecturer in Philosophy, University
College of North Wales 1946; John Locke Scholar, Oxford
University 1946, Reader in Philosophy 1966-68, Waynflete
Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy 1968-87; Lecturer in
Philosophy, University College, Oxford 1947, Fellow
1948-68, Honorary Fellow 1979-2006; FBA 1960; Fellow,
Magdalen College, Oxford 1968-87, Honorary Fellow 1989; Kt
1977; married 1945 Grace Hall Martin (two sons, two
daughters); died Oxford 13 February 2006.



Encountering philosophy as an undergraduate in 1959 was a
wonderful and astonishing experience. That was the year in
which two philosophical works appeared whose impact on the
discipline was out of all proportion to their modest size
and unpretentious prose. One was Stuart Hampshire's Thought
and Action; the other, by Peter Strawson, was Individuals.
Its demure sub-title, An Essay in Descriptive
Metaphysics, gives no hint of the revolution it wrought.



Almost any student fresh from school at the end of the
Fifties would have thought that philosophy in England was
defined by Bertrand Russell and A.J. Ayer, that
metaphysics was the name of something foreign and
obscure, and that a thinker such as Immanuel Kant was
wilfully opaque and unreadable. It turned out that the
attempts of English empiricists to build the world out of
sense-data wouldn't wash; and it soon became possible to
read Kant with pleasure - or at any rate to see in Kant
some of what Strawson had so usefully taught us to see in
Kant's work.



For most of his career in Oxford, Peter Strawson defined
what philosophy was, and how it should be practised; he had
already acquired a considerable reputation by the time he
published Individuals and it was succeeded in 1966 by The
Bounds of Sense, which remains one of the best ways in to
the vertiginous difficulties of Kant's Critique of Pure
Reason.



Strawson was born in west London in 1919 and attended
Christ's College, Finchley (followed by his younger
brother, the future Maj-Gen John Strawson); from there he
went to St John's College, Oxford in 1937. Unlike most
Oxford philosophers of his day, he read Philosophy,
Politics and Economics rather than Greats. It was still
regarded as a scandal 20 years later that the examiners
gave him a second class degree when he graduated in 1940.



The tale went that Isaiah Berlin had very much admired his
brisk and combative philosophy papers and had given them
clear first class marks, but that Sandy Lindsay, the Master
of Balliol, and a survivor from the days of Oxford
Idealism, had found them brash, and too dismissive of
philosophers he admired, and had marked them down
accordingly. The Second World War was on, Berlin was
heading for the United States, there were no viva voce
examinations, and the old Oxford rule that the lower mark
prevailed cost Strawson his First. It was rumoured among
the undergraduates of the Sixties that Berlin had anyway
left the scripts in a taxi . . .



At all events, Strawson went off to war, first in the Royal
Artillery and then in the Royal Electrical and Mechanical
Engineers. He was demobilised as a captain in the REME. In
1945, he married Grace Hall Martin - universally known as
Ann - with whom he would have two daughters and two sons.
After the war, he was appointed to an assistant
lecturership in philosophy at the University College of
North Wales at Bangor. He returned to Oxford almost
immediately; in 1946 he won the John Locke Scholarship, and
in 1947 became a lecturer in philosophy at University
College, Oxford. The following year he was elected to a
permanent fellowship in philosophy at the college.



During the 20 years he was there, the fellows of University
College were strikingly more interesting than most of their
peers, and part of the reason was the high standard set by
Peter Strawson. He was courteous, urbane and readily amused
- he frequently looked as though he was sharing some small
joke with the Almighty while he conversed with his
colleagues - but, without ever insisting on it, he left one
in no doubt that he expected intelligent conversation.



Those were the qualities he brought to his work as an
undergraduate tutor and a graduate supervisor; like some
other very distinguished philosophers, he was as good at
getting through to the less philosophically talented as he
was at stimulating the very brightest. He never looked for,
and never attempted to make, disciples, and 

[peirce-l] Re: Existent vs Real

2006-02-18 Thread Jim Piat

Dea Folks,

I'm thinking it might be helpful to try to distinguish between the notions 
of real and true. One can contrast real with imaginary and true with false. 
Some further preliminary thoughts below.  As in maybe---


Peirce proposes that being comes in three modes  -- the potential, the 
actual and the tending toward.  He calls all three modes real -- as opposed 
to mere fictions, figments of the imagination, or as some might say 
nominally real or real in name only.  So then what is a fiction?  Fictions, 
in my view, are category mistakes.  As when when we mistake one catergory of 
reality for another.  For example,  when we miscategorize something that is 
potentially real as something that is actually real.


Mistaking one form of reality for another is the sort of category mistake we 
call a fiction.  However if we examine the sort of error we can make within 
each category of being we come upon the notion of truth vs falshood.  For 
example to mistake the  impossible for the potential is a falsehood within 
the potential mode of being.  Likewise to mistake what has occured for what 
has not occured is a falsehood within the actual/perceptual mode of being. 
Finally to mistake the tending toward for what is not being tended toward is 
a falsehood within the category of science.


The distinction between real and true, that arises from the above viewpoint, 
becomes a matter or how both the real and the true are established.  Real is 
established by dtermining not whether something conforms to fact or reason 
but whether or not it has been rightly classified as potential, actual or 
tending toward.  True, on the other hand, is a matter that depends upon 
determining whether something conforms to observation and logic.


Put still another way  -- Being is divided into three kinds of reality and 
within each of these real modes of being (feeling, reactions, and thoughts) 
truth can be established by appeals to observation and logic.  To say 
something is unreal is to say it has been miscatergorized.  To say something 
is untrue is to say it has been mistakenly observed or reasoned.


Maybe--

Cheers,
Jim Piat

And Ben  -- I would still want to argue that all of these errors are at root 
instances of the general rule that all error is a matter of mistaking the 
whole for the part. Error lies not in misperception but in drawing a false 
conclusion.  And overgeneralizing from one's personal limited experience to 
god's will is in my limited experience the universal error underlying all 
errors.  In this way all we experience is both true but not the whole truth. 
No one is wrong  -- but neither is any individual by his or herself entirely 
correct. By its very nature of affording more than one POV the ultimately 
truth of reality is a property of the whole  and error of the part. 
Perhaps.


---
Message from peirce-l forum to subscriber archive@mail-archive.com



[peirce-l] Re: Existent vs Real

2006-02-16 Thread Joseph Ransdell
I have no problem with this, Thomas, as showing the need for the distinction 
of the existent vs. the real, but then I wasn't really putting the need for 
it in question but only intending to indicate that I don't always understand 
how to apply it effectively.

Joe Ransdell

- Original Message - 
From: Thomas Riese [EMAIL PROTECTED]
To: Peirce Discussion Forum peirce-l@lyris.ttu.edu
Sent: Thursday, February 16, 2006 1:52 AM
Subject: [peirce-l] Existent vs Real


Joe,

I propose, to fix our ideas, that we try our hands at the following:

(from Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism; 1906)
[CP 4.546]
Let us begin with the question of Universes. It is rather a question of an
advisable point of view than of the truth of a doctrine. A logical
universe is,
no doubt, a collection of logical subjects, but not necessarily of
meta-physical
Subjects, or substances; for it may be composed of characters, of
elementary
facts, etc. See my definition in Baldwin's Dictionary. Let us first try
whether we may not assume that there is but one kind of Subjects which are
either existing things or else quite fictitious. Let it be asserted that
there
is some married woman who will commit suicide in case her husband fails in
business. Surely that is a very different proposition from the assertion
that
some married woman will commit suicide if all married men fail in
business. Yet
if nothing is real but existing things, then, since in the former
proposition
nothing whatever is said as to what the lady will or will not do if her
husband
does not fail in business, and since of a given married couple this can
only be
false if the fact is contrary to the assertion, it follows it can only be
false
if the husband does fail in business and if the wife then fails to commit
suicide. But the proposition only says that there is some married couple of
which the wife is of that temper. Consequently, there are only two ways in
which
the proposition can be false, namely, first, by there not being any married
couple, and secondly, by every married man failing in business while no
married
woman commits suicide. Consequently, all that is required to make the
proposition true is that there should either be some married man who does
not
fail in business, or else some married woman who commits suicide. That is,
the
proposition amounts merely to asserting that there is a married woman who
will
commit suicide if every married man fails in business. The equivalence of
these
two propositions is the absurd result of admitting no reality but
existence. If,
however, we suppose that to say that a woman will suicide if her husband
fails,
means that every possible course of events would either be one in which the
husband would not fail or one in which the wife would commit suicide,
then, to
make that false it will not be requisite for the husband actually to fail,
but
it will suffice that there are possible circumstances under which he would
fail,
while yet his wife would not commit suicide. Now you will observe that
there is
a great difference between the two following propositions:

First, There is some one married woman who under all possible conditions
would
commit suicide or else her husband would not have failed.

Second, Under all possible circumstances there is some married woman or
other
who would commit suicide, or else her husband would not nave failed.

The former of these is what is really meant by saying that there is some
married
woman who would commit suicide if her husband were to fail, while the
latter is
what the denial of any possible circumstances except those that really take
place logically leads to [our] interpreting (or virtually interpreting),
the
Proposition as asserting.

[CP 4.547]
In other places, I have given many other reasons for my firm belief
that there are real possibilities. I also think, however, that, in
addition to
actuality and possibility, a third mode of reality must be recognized in
that
which, as the gipsy fortune-tellers express it, is sure to come true,
or, as
we may say is destined,(n1) although I do not mean to assert that this is
affirmation rather than the negation of this Mode of Reality. I do not see
by
what confusion of thought anybody can persuade himself that he does not
believe
that tomorrow is destined to come. The point is that it is today really
true
that tomorrow the sun will rise; or that, even if it does not, the clocks
or
something, will go on. For if it be not real it can only be fiction: a
Proposition is either True or False. But we are too apt to confound
destiny with
the impossibility of the opposite. I see no impossibility in the sudden
stoppage
of everything. In order to show the difference, I remind you that
impossibility is that which, for example, describes the mode of falsity
of the
idea that there should be a collection of objects so multitudinous that
there
would not be characters enough in the universe of characters to
distinguish all
those things from one another. Is